All publications

All publications (co)authored by S. Shelah


You can select other lists here.
Click the Sh:-number to get to the papers' detail page (which may include pdf's of the paper).
Can't find an Sh:-number (in particular, an "F-number")? You can try your luck here.

The books by S. Shelah

  1. Sh:a
    Shelah, S. (1978). Classification theory and the number of nonisomorphic models, Vol. 92, North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam-New York, p. xvi+544. MR: 513226
    type: book
    abstract: (none)
    keywords:
  2. Sh:b
    Shelah, S. (1982). Proper forcing, Vol. 940, Springer-Verlag, Berlin-New York, p. xxix+496. MR: 675955
    type: book
    abstract: (none)
    keywords:
  3. Sh:c
    Shelah, S. (1990). Classification theory and the number of nonisomorphic models, Second, Vol. 92, North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam, p. xxxiv+705. MR: 1083551
    type: book
    abstract: (none)
    keywords:
  4. Sh:d
    Shelah, S. (1986). Around classification theory of models, Vol. 1182, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, p. viii+279. DOI: 10.1007/BFb0098503 MR: 850051
    Contains [Sh:171], [Sh:197], [Sh:212], [Sh:228], [Sh:229], [Sh:232], [Sh:233], [Sh:234], [Sh:237a], [Sh:237b], [Sh:237c], [Sh:237d], [Sh:237e], [Sh:247], [Sh:E8]

    type: book
    abstract: (none)
    keywords:
  5. Sh:e
    Shelah, S. Non-structure theory, Oxford University Press. To appear.
    Contains [Sh:309], [Sh:331], [Sh:363], [Sh:384], [Sh:421], [Sh:482], [Sh:511], [Sh:E58], [Sh:E59], [Sh:E60], [Sh:E61], [Sh:E62], [Sh:E63]

    type: book
    abstract: (none)
    keywords:
  6. Sh:f
    Shelah, S. (1998). Proper and improper forcing, Second, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, p. xlviii+1020. DOI: 10.1007/978-3-662-12831-2 MR: 1623206
    See [Sh:253], [Sh:263]

    type: book
    abstract: (none)
    keywords:
  7. Sh:g
    Shelah, S. (1994). Cardinal arithmetic, Vol. 29, The Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press, New York, p. xxxii+481. MR: 1318912
    Contains [Sh:282a], [Sh:333], [Sh:345a], [Sh:345b], [Sh:355], [Sh:365], [Sh:371], [Sh:380], [Sh:386], [Sh:400]. See [Sh:E12]

    type: book
    abstract: (none)
    keywords:
  8. Sh:h
    Shelah, S. (2009). Classification theory for abstract elementary classes, Vol. 18, College Publications, London, p. vi+813. MR: 2643267
    Contains [Sh:88r], [Sh:300x], [Sh:600], [Sh:705], [Sh:734], [Sh:E53]. See [Sh:E54]

    type: book
    abstract: (none)
    keywords:
  9. Sh:i
    Shelah, S. (2009). Classification theory for abstract elementary classes. Vol. 2, Vol. 20, College Publications, London, p. iii+694. MR: 2649290
    Contains [Sh:300a], [Sh:300b], [Sh:300c], [Sh:300d], [Sh:300e], [Sh:300f], [Sh:300g], [Sh:300z], [Sh:838], [Sh:E46]

    type: book
    abstract: (none)
    keywords:

Peer reviewed research articles (co)authored by S. Shelah that are published.

  1. Sh:1
    Shelah, S. (1969). Stable theories. Israel J. Math., 7, 187–202. DOI: 10.1007/BF02787611 MR: 0253889
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  2. Sh:2
    Shelah, S. (1969). Note on a min-max problem of Leo Moser. J. Combinatorial Theory, 6, 298–300. MR: 241312
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: fin, (fc)
  3. Sh:3
    Shelah, S. Finite diagrams stable in power. Ann. Math. Logic, 2(1), 69–118. DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(70)90007-0 MR: 0285374
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, M: nec, (mod)
  4. Sh:4
    Shelah, S. (1970). On theories T categorical in |T|. J. Symbolic Logic, 35, 73–82. DOI: 10.2307/2271158 MR: 0282818
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (cat)
  5. Sh:5
    Shelah, S. (1970). On languages with non-homogeneous strings of quantifiers. Israel J. Math., 8, 75–79. DOI: 10.1007/BF02771553 MR: 0262064
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  6. Sh:6
    Shelah, S. (1970). A note on Hanf numbers. Pacific J. Math., 34, 541–545. http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.pjm/1102976446 MR: 0268033
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (mod)
  7. Sh:7
    Shelah, S. (1970). On the cardinality of ultraproduct of finite sets. J. Symbolic Logic, 35, 83–84. DOI: 10.2307/2271159 MR: 0325388
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ods, (set), (mod), (up)
  8. Sh:8
    Shelah, S. (1971). Two cardinal compactness. Israel J. Math., 9, 193–198. DOI: 10.1007/BF02771584 MR: 0302437
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  9. Sh:9
    Shelah, S. Remark to “local definability theory” of Reyes. Ann. Math. Logic, 2(4), 441–447. DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(71)90004-0 MR: 0282822
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (mod)
  10. Sh:10
    Shelah, S. (1971). Stability, the f.c.p., and superstability; model theoretic properties of formulas in first order theory. Ann. Math. Logic, 3(3), 271–362. DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(71)90015-5 MR: 0317926
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  11. Sh:11
    Shelah, S. (1971). On the number of non-almost isomorphic models of T in a power. Pacific J. Math., 36, 811–818. http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.pjm/1102970932 MR: 0285375
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod), (inf-log)
  12. Sh:12
    Shelah, S. (1971). The number of non-isomorphic models of an unstable first-order theory. Israel J. Math., 9, 473–487. DOI: 10.1007/BF02771463 MR: 0278926
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (nni)
  13. Sh:13
    Shelah, S. (1971). Every two elementarily equivalent models have isomorphic ultrapowers. Israel J. Math., 10, 224–233. DOI: 10.1007/BF02771574 MR: 0297554
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (mod), (up)
  14. Sh:14
    Shelah, S. (1972). Saturation of ultrapowers and Keisler’s order. Ann. Math. Logic, 4, 75–114. DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(72)90012-5 MR: 0294113
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (up)
  15. Sh:15
    Shelah, S. (1972). Uniqueness and characterization of prime models over sets for totally transcendental first-order theories. J. Symbolic Logic, 37, 107–113. DOI: 10.2307/2272553 MR: 0316239
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  16. Sh:16
    Shelah, S. (1972). A combinatorial problem; stability and order for models and theories in infinitary languages. Pacific J. Math., 41, 247–261. http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.pjm/1102968432 MR: 0307903
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: nec, S: ico, (mod)
  17. Sh:17
    Shelah, S. (1972). For what filters is every reduced product saturated? Israel J. Math., 12, 23–31. DOI: 10.1007/BF02764810 MR: 0304157
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (mod)
  18. Sh:18
    Shelah, S. (1972). On models with power-like orderings. J. Symbolic Logic, 37, 247–267. DOI: 10.2307/2272971 MR: 0446955
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (mod), (inf-log)
  19. Sh:19
    Erdős, P., & Shelah, S. (1972). Separability properties of almost-disjoint families of sets. Israel J. Math., 12, 207–214. DOI: 10.1007/BF02764666 MR: 0319770
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (cont)
  20. Sh:20
    Schmerl, J. H., & Shelah, S. (1972). On power-like models for hyperinaccessible cardinals. J. Symbolic Logic, 37, 531–537. DOI: 10.2307/2272739 MR: 0317925
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (inf-log)
  21. Sh:21
    Erdős, P., & Shelah, S. (1972). On problems of Moser and Hanson. In Graph theory and applications (Proc. Conf., Western Michigan Univ., Kalamazoo, Mich., 1972; dedicated to the memory of J. W. T. Youngs), Vol. 303, Springer, Berlin, pp. 75–79. MR: 0337646
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: fin, (fc)
  22. Sh:22
    Shelah, S. (1972). A note on model complete models and generic models. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 34, 509–514. DOI: 10.2307/2038398 MR: 294114
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (mod)
  23. Sh:23
    Galvin, F., & Shelah, S. (1973). Some counterexamples in the partition calculus. J. Combinatorial Theory Ser. A, 15, 167–174. DOI: 10.1016/s0097-3165(73)80004-4 MR: 0329900
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (pc), (cont)
  24. Sh:24
    Shelah, S. (1973). First order theory of permutation groups. Israel J. Math., 14, 149–162; errata, ibid.15 (1973), 437–441. DOI: 10.1007/BF02762670 MR: 0416909
    See [Sh:25]

    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  25. Sh:26
    Shelah, S. (1973). Notes on combinatorial set theory. Israel J. Math., 14, 262–277. DOI: 10.1007/BF02764885 MR: 0327522
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (pc), (graph), (univ)
  26. Sh:27
    Moran, G., & Shelah, S. (1973). Size direction games over the real line. III. Israel J. Math., 14, 442–449. DOI: 10.1007/BF02764720 MR: 0321551
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (cont)
  27. Sh:28
    Shelah, S. (1973). There are just four second-order quantifiers. Israel J. Math., 15, 282–300. DOI: 10.1007/BF02787572 MR: 0335237
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  28. Sh:29
    Shelah, S. (1974). A substitute for Hall’s theorem for families with infinite sets. J. Combinatorial Theory Ser. A, 16, 199–208. DOI: 10.1016/0097-3165(74)90044-2 MR: 0332497
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (fc)
  29. Sh:30
    McKenzie, R. N., & Shelah, S. (1974). The cardinals of simple models for universal theories. In Proceedings of the Tarski Symposium, Vol. XXV, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, R.I., pp. 53–74. MR: 0360261
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (mod), (ua)
  30. Sh:31
    Shelah, S. (1974). Categoricity of uncountable theories. In Proceedings of the Tarski Symposium, Vol. XXV, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, R.I., pp. 187–203. MR: 0373874
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (cat)
  31. Sh:32
    Erdős, P., Hajnal, A., & Shelah, S. (1974). On some general properties of chromatic numbers. In Topics in topology (Proc. Colloq., Keszthely, 1972), Vol. 8, North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp. 243–255. MR: 0357194
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico
  32. Sh:33
    Shelah, S. (1974). The Hanf number of omitting complete types. Pacific J. Math., 50, 163–168. http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.pjm/1102913702 MR: 0363877
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (mod)
  33. Sh:34
    Shelah, S. (1973). Weak definability in infinitary languages. J. Symbolic Logic, 38, 399–404. DOI: 10.2307/2273033 MR: 0369027
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod), (nni), (inf-log)
  34. Sh:35
    Milner, E. C., & Shelah, S. (1974). Sufficiency conditions for the existence of transversals. Canadian J. Math., 26, 948–961. DOI: 10.4153/CJM-1974-089-8 MR: 373907
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico
  35. Sh:36
    Shelah, S. (1977). Remarks on cardinal invariants in topology. General Topology and Appl., 7(3), 251–259. MR: 0482614
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: top, (inv), (gt)
  36. Sh:37
    Shelah, S. (1975). A two-cardinal theorem. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 48, 207–213. DOI: 10.2307/2040719 MR: 357105
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, S: ico, (mod), (fc)
  37. Sh:38
    Shelah, S. (1975). Graphs with prescribed asymmetry and minimal number of edges. In Infinite and finite sets (Colloq., Keszthely, 1973; dedicated to P. Erdős on his 60th birthday), Vol. III, Vol. 10, North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp. 1241–1256. MR: 0371727
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: fin, (auto), (fc)
  38. Sh:39
    Shelah, S. (1973). Differentially closed fields. Israel J. Math., 16, 314–328. DOI: 10.1007/BF02756711 MR: 0344116
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (sta)
  39. Sh:40
    Shelah, S. (1975). Notes on partition calculus. In Infinite and finite sets (Colloq., Keszthely, 1973; dedicated to P. Erdős on his 60th birthday), Vol. III, Vol. 10, North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp. 1257–1276. MR: 0406798
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (pc)
  40. Sh:41
    Milner, E. C., & Shelah, S. (1975). Some theorems on transversals. In Infinite and finite sets (Colloq., Keszthely, 1973; dedicated to P. Erdős on his 60th birthday), Vol III, Vol. 10, North Holland, Amsterdam, pp. 1115–1126. MR: 0376358
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico
  41. Sh:42
    Shelah, S. (1975). The monadic theory of order. Ann. Of Math. (2), 102(3), 379–419. DOI: 10.2307/1971037 MR: 0491120
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod), (mon)
  42. Sh:43
    Shelah, S. (1975). Generalized quantifiers and compact logic. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 204, 342–364. DOI: 10.2307/1997362 MR: 376334
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  43. Sh:44
    Shelah, S. (1974). Infinite abelian groups, Whitehead problem and some constructions. Israel J. Math., 18, 243–256. DOI: 10.1007/BF02757281 MR: 0357114
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (ab), (wh)
  44. Sh:45
    Shelah, S. (1975). Existence of rigid-like families of abelian p-groups. In Model theory and algebra (A memorial tribute to Abraham Robinson), Vol. 498, Springer, Berlin, pp. 384–402. MR: 0412299
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (ab)
  45. Sh:46
    Shelah, S. (1975). Colouring without triangles and partition relation. Israel J. Math., 20, 1–12. DOI: 10.1007/BF02756751 MR: 0427073
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (pc)
  46. Sh:47
    Makowsky, J. A., Shelah, S., & Stavi, J. (1976). \Delta-logics and generalized quantifiers. Ann. Math. Logic, 10(2), 155–192. DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(76)90021-8 MR: 0457146
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  47. Sh:48
    Shelah, S. (1975). Categoricity in \aleph_1 of sentences in L_{\omega_1,\omega}(Q). Israel J. Math., 20(2), 127–148. DOI: 10.1007/BF02757882 MR: 0379177
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, M: nec, (mod), (inf-log), (cat)
  48. Sh:49
    Shelah, S. (1976). A two-cardinal theorem and a combinatorial theorem. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 62(1), 134–136 (1977). DOI: 10.2307/2041962 MR: 434800
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, S: ico, (mod), (pc)
  49. Sh:50
    Shelah, S. (1976). Decomposing uncountable squares to countably many chains. J. Combinatorial Theory Ser. A, 21(1), 110–114. DOI: 10.1016/0097-3165(76)90053-4 MR: 0409196
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (cont), (trees), (linear order), (aron)
  50. Sh:51
    Shelah, S. (1975). Why there are many nonisomorphic models for unsuperstable theories. In Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians (Vancouver, B. C., 1974), Vol. 1, Canad. Math. Congress, Montreal, Que., pp. 259–263. MR: 0422015
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (ba)
  51. Sh:52
    Shelah, S. (1975). A compactness theorem for singular cardinals, free algebras, Whitehead problem and transversals. Israel J. Math., 21(4), 319–349. DOI: 10.1007/BF02757993 MR: 0389579
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (ab)
  52. Sh:53
    Litman, A., & Shelah, S. (1977). Models with few isomorphic expansions. Israel J. Math., 28(4), 331–338. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760639 MR: 0469741
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (mod)
  53. Sh:54
    Shelah, S. (1975). The lazy model-theoretician’s guide to stability. Logique et Analyse (N.S.), 18(71-72), 241–308. MR: 0539969
    See [Sh:54a]

    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, M: nec, (mod)
  54. Sh:55
    Macintyre, A. J., & Shelah, S. (1976). Uncountable universal locally finite groups. J. Algebra, 43(1), 168–175. DOI: 10.1016/0021-8693(76)90150-2 MR: 0439625
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, O: alg, (mod), (nni), (stal)
  55. Sh:56
    Shelah, S. (1976). Refuting Ehrenfeucht conjecture on rigid models. Israel J. Math., 25(3-4), 273–286. DOI: 10.1007/BF02757005 MR: 0485326
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (mod)
  56. Sh:57
    Amit, R., & Shelah, S. (1976). The complete finitely axiomatized theories of order are dense. Israel J. Math., 23(3-4), 200–208. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761800 MR: 0485315
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (mod), (linear order)
  57. Sh:58
    Shelah, S. (1977). Decidability of a portion of the predicate calculus. Israel J. Math., 28(1-2), 32–44. DOI: 10.1007/BF02759780 MR: 0505410
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (mod), (fmt)
  58. Sh:59
    Hiller, H. L., & Shelah, S. (1977). Singular cohomology in L. Israel J. Math., 26(3–4), 313–319. DOI: 10.1007/BF03007650 MR: 0444469
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  59. Sh:60
    Hodges, W., Lachlan, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1977). Possible orderings of an indiscernible sequence. Bull. London Math. Soc., 9(2), 212–215. DOI: 10.1112/blms/9.2.212 MR: 0476525
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, O: fin, (mod), (auto), (fc)
  60. Sh:61
    Shelah, S. (1976). Interpreting set theory in the endomorphism semi-group of afree algebra or in a category. Ann. Sci. Univ. Clermont, (60 Math. No. 13), 1–29. MR: 0505511
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: alg, (mod), (ua)
  61. Sh:62
    Makowsky, J. A., & Shelah, S. (1979). The theorems of Beth and Craig in abstract model theory. I. The abstract setting. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 256, 215–239. DOI: 10.2307/1998109 MR: 546916
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  62. Sh:63
    Shelah, S., & Stern, J. (1978). The Hanf number of the first order theory of Banach spaces. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 244, 147–171. DOI: 10.2307/1997892 MR: 506613
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: top, (mod)
  63. Sh:64
    Shelah, S. (1977). Whitehead groups may be not free, even assuming CH. I. Israel J. Math., 28(3), 193–204. DOI: 10.1007/BF02759809 MR: 0469757
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (ab)
  64. Sh:65
    Devlin, K. J., & Shelah, S. (1978). A weak version of \diamondsuit which follows from 2^{\aleph_0}<2^{\aleph_1}. Israel J. Math., 29(2-3), 239–247. DOI: 10.1007/BF02762012 MR: 0469756
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (cont), (wd)
  65. Sh:66
    Shelah, S. (1978). End extensions and numbers of countable models. J. Symbolic Logic, 43(3), 550–562. DOI: 10.2307/2273531 MR: 503792
    type: article
    abstract: The answer to the question from page 562 (the end). is negative; have known a solution but not sure if have Not record it. For any countable model $M$ with countable vocabulary with predicates only. Not including < and $E$. First we choose a function $F$ from $Q$ the rationals onto $M$ such that the pre-image of any element is dense Second we define a model $N$ Universe. The rationals <. Is interpreted. As the rational order $E$ is interpreted as the equivalence relation $xEy iff F(x)=F(y)$ For any predicate $P$ of the vocabulary of $M$ is interpreted as it's pre-image by $F$ No $Th(N)$ is a countable fo theory with the same number of countable models up to isomorphism as $Th(M)$ So we are done giving a negative answer to the question
    keywords: M: odm, (mod), (nni)
  66. Sh:67
    Shelah, S. (1978). On the number of minimal models. J. Symbolic Logic, 43(3), 475–480. DOI: 10.2307/2273522 MR: 0491148
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (mod)
  67. Sh:68
    Shelah, S. (1978). Jonsson algebras in successor cardinals. Israel J. Math., 30(1-2), 57–64. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760829 MR: 0505434
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  68. Sh:69
    Shelah, S. (1980). On a problem of Kurosh, Jónsson groups, and applications. In Word problems, II (Conf. on Decision Problems in Algebra, Oxford, 1976), Vol. 95, North-Holland, Amsterdam-New York, pp. 373–394. MR: 579953
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (grp)
  69. Sh:70
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1979). Modest theory of short chains. II. J. Symbolic Logic, 44(4), 491–502. DOI: 10.2307/2273288 MR: 550378
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod), (mon)
  70. Sh:71
    Shelah, S. (1980). A note on cardinal exponentiation. J. Symbolic Logic, 45(1), 56–66. DOI: 10.2307/2273354 MR: 560225
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: pcf, (set)
  71. Sh:72
    Shelah, S. (1978). Models with second-order properties. I. Boolean algebras with no definable automorphisms. Ann. Math. Logic, 14(1), 57–72. DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(78)90008-6 MR: 501097
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (ba)
  72. Sh:73
    Shelah, S. (1978). Models with second-order properties. II. Trees with no undefined branches. Ann. Math. Logic, 14(1), 73–87. DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(78)90009-8 MR: 501098
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (trees)
  73. Sh:74
    Shelah, S. (1978). Appendix to: “Models with second-order properties. II. Trees with no undefined branches” (Ann. Math. Logic 14 (1978), no. 1, 73–87). Ann. Math. Logic, 14, 223–226. DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(78)90017-7 MR: 506531
    See [Sh:E28]

    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, S: ico, (mod), (pc)
  74. Sh:75
    Shelah, S. (1978). A Banach space with few operators. Israel J. Math., 30(1-2), 181–191. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760838 MR: 508262
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (set)
  75. Sh:76
    Shelah, S. (1980). Independence of strong partition relation for small cardinals, and the free-subset problem. J. Symbolic Logic, 45(3), 505–509. DOI: 10.2307/2273418 MR: 583369
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (pc)
  76. Sh:77
    Shelah, S. (1977). Existentially-closed groups in \aleph_1 with special properties. Bull. Soc. Math. Grèce (N.S.), 18(1), 17–27. MR: 528419
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (mod), (grp)
  77. Sh:78
    Shelah, S. (1979). Hanf number of omitting type for simple first-order theories. J. Symbolic Logic, 44(3), 319–324. DOI: 10.2307/2273125 MR: 540663
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  78. Sh:79
    Shelah, S. (1979). On uniqueness of prime models. J. Symbolic Logic, 44(2), 215–220. DOI: 10.2307/2273729 MR: 534571
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  79. Sh:80
    Shelah, S. (1978). A weak generalization of MA to higher cardinals. Israel J. Math., 30(4), 297–306. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761994 MR: 0505492
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  80. Sh:81
    Abraham, U., Devlin, K. J., & Shelah, S. (1978). The consistency with CH of some consequences of Martin’s axiom plus 2^{\aleph_0}>\aleph_1. Israel J. Math., 31(1), 19–33. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761378 MR: 0505488
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  81. Sh:82
    Shelah, S. (1981). Models with second order properties. III. Omitting types for L(Q). Arch. Math. Logik Grundlag., 21(1-2), 1–11. DOI: 10.1007/BF02011630 MR: 625527
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod)
  82. Sh:83
    Giorgetta, D., & Shelah, S. (1984). Existentially closed structures in the power of the continuum. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 26(2), 123–148. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(84)90013-7 MR: 739576
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (grp)
  83. Sh:84
    Rubin, M., & Shelah, S. (1980). On the elementary equivalence of automorphism groups of Boolean algebras; downward Skolem-Löwenheim theorems and compactness of related quantifiers. J. Symbolic Logic, 45(2), 265–283. DOI: 10.2307/2273187 MR: 569397
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (ba), (auto)
  84. Sh:85
    Devlin, K. J., & Shelah, S. (1979). A note on the normal Moore space conjecture. Canadian J. Math., 31(2), 241–251. DOI: 10.4153/CJM-1979-025-8 MR: 528801
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: top, (gt), (normal), (wd)
  85. Sh:86
    Devlin, K. J., & Shelah, S. (1979). Souslin properties and tree topologies. Proc. London Math. Soc. (3), 39(2), 237–252. DOI: 10.1112/plms/s3-39.2.237 MR: 548979
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: top, (set), (gt), (trees), (wd), (aron)
  86. Sh:87a
    Shelah, S. (1983). Classification theory for nonelementary classes. I. The number of uncountable models of \psi \in L_{\omega_1,\omega }. Part A. Israel J. Math., 46(3), 212–240. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761954 MR: 733351
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: nec, M: non, (cat), (wd)
  87. Sh:87b
    Shelah, S. (1983). Classification theory for nonelementary classes. I. The number of uncountable models of \psi \in L_{\omega_1,\omega }. Part B. Israel J. Math., 46(4), 241–273. DOI: 10.1007/BF02762887 MR: 730343
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: nec, M: non, (cat), (wd)
  88. Sh:88
    Shelah, S. (1987). Classification of nonelementary classes. II. Abstract elementary classes. In Classification theory (Chicago, IL, 1985), Vol. 1292, Springer, Berlin, pp. 419–497. DOI: 10.1007/BFb0082243 MR: 1033034
    Contains [Sh:88a]

    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: nec, M: smt, (mod), (cat), (wd), (aec)
  89. Sh:89
    Shelah, S. (1979). Boolean algebras with few endomorphisms. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 74(1), 135–142. DOI: 10.2307/2042119 MR: 521887
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, S: ico, (ba), (cont)
  90. Sh:90
    Shelah, S. (1977). Remarks on \lambda-collectionwise Hausdorff spaces. Topology Proc., 2(2), 583–592 (1978). MR: 540629
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (gt)
  91. Sh:91
    Hiller, H. L., Huber, M. K., & Shelah, S. (1978). The structure of \mathrm{Ext}(A, \mathbf Z) and V=L. Math. Z., 162(1), 39–50. DOI: 10.1007/BF01437821 MR: 0492007
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  92. Sh:92
    Shelah, S. (1980). Remarks on Boolean algebras. Algebra Universalis, 11(1), 77–89. DOI: 10.1007/BF02483083 MR: 593014
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (ba)
  93. Sh:93
    Shelah, S. (1980). Simple unstable theories. Ann. Math. Logic, 19(3), 177–203. DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(80)90009-1 MR: 595012
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla
  94. Sh:94
    Shelah, S. (1979). Weakly compact cardinals: a combinatorial proof. J. Symbolic Logic, 44(4), 559–562. DOI: 10.2307/2273294 MR: 550384
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico
  95. Sh:95
    Shelah, S. (1981). Canonization theorems and applications. J. Symbolic Logic, 46(2), 345–353. DOI: 10.2307/2273626 MR: 613287
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (pc)
  96. Sh:96
    Shelah, S., & Ziegler, M. (1979). Algebraically closed groups of large cardinality. J. Symbolic Logic, 44(4), 522–532. DOI: 10.2307/2273291 MR: 550381
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (grp)
  97. Sh:97
    Rudin, M. E., & Shelah, S. (1978). Unordered types of ultrafilters. Topology Proc., 3(1), 199–204 (1979). MR: 540490
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (gt)
  98. Sh:98
    Shelah, S. (1980). Whitehead groups may not be free, even assuming CH. II. Israel J. Math., 35(4), 257–285. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760652 MR: 594332
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (ab), (wh)
  99. Sh:99
    Harrington, L. A., & Shelah, S. (1985). Some exact equiconsistency results in set theory. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 26(2), 178–188. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093870823 MR: 783595
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: dst, (trees), (aron)
  100. Sh:100
    Shelah, S. (1980). Independence results. J. Symbolic Logic, 45(3), 563–573. DOI: 10.2307/2273423 MR: 583374
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (nni), (univ), (linear order)
  101. Sh:101
    Makowsky, J. A., & Shelah, S. (1981). The theorems of Beth and Craig in abstract model theory. II. Compact logics. Arch. Math. Logik Grundlag., 21(1-2), 13–35. DOI: 10.1007/BF02011631 MR: 625528
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt
  102. Sh:102
    Abraham, U., & Shelah, S. (1982). Forcing with stable posets. J. Symbolic Logic, 47(1), 37–42. DOI: 10.2307/2273379 MR: 644751
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (cont), (trees), (aron)
  103. Sh:103
    Fremlin, D. H., & Shelah, S. (1979). On partitions of the real line. Israel J. Math., 32(4), 299–304. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760459 MR: 571084
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: str, (set), (inv), (meag)
  104. Sh:104
    Laver, R. J., & Shelah, S. (1981). The \aleph_2-Souslin hypothesis. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 264(2), 411–417. DOI: 10.2307/1998547 MR: 603771
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (trees)
  105. Sh:105
    Shelah, S. (1979). On uncountable abelian groups. Israel J. Math., 32(4), 311–330. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760461 MR: 571086
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  106. Sh:106
    Abraham, U., & Shelah, S. (1981). Martin’s axiom does not imply that every two \aleph_1-dense sets of reals are isomorphic. Israel J. Math., 38(1-2), 161–176. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761858 MR: 599485
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (linear order)
  107. Sh:107
    Shelah, S. (1983). Models with second order properties. IV. A general method and eliminating diamonds. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 25(2), 183–212. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(83)90013-1 MR: 725733
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod)
  108. Sh:108
    Shelah, S. (1979). On successors of singular cardinals. In Logic Colloquium ’78 (Mons, 1978), Vol. 97, North-Holland, Amsterdam-New York, pp. 357–380. MR: 567680
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (set), (ab), (af)
  109. Sh:109
    Hodges, W., & Shelah, S. (1981). Infinite games and reduced products. Ann. Math. Logic, 20(1), 77–108. DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(81)90012-7 MR: 611395
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod), (inf-log)
  110. Sh:110
    Shelah, S. (1982). Better quasi-orders for uncountable cardinals. Israel J. Math., 42(3), 177–226. DOI: 10.1007/BF02802723 MR: 687127
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (pure(large))
  111. Sh:111
    Shelah, S. (1986). On power of singular cardinals. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 27(2), 263–299. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093636617 MR: 842153
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: pcf
  112. Sh:112
    Shelah, S., & Stanley, L. J. (1982). S-forcing. I. A “black-box” theorem for morasses, with applications to super-Souslin trees. Israel J. Math., 43(3), 185–224. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761942 MR: 689979
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (trees)
  113. Sh:113
    Shelah, S. (1990). The theorems of Beth and Craig in abstract model theory. III. \Delta-logics and infinitary logics. Israel J. Math., 69(2), 193–213. DOI: 10.1007/BF02937304 MR: 1045373
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod), (inf-log)
  114. Sh:114
    Abraham, U., & Shelah, S. (1985). Isomorphism types of Aronszajn trees. Israel J. Math., 50(1-2), 75–113. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761119 MR: 788070
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (aron)
  115. Sh:115
    Cherlin, G. L., & Shelah, S. (1980). Superstable fields and groups. Ann. Math. Logic, 18(3), 227–270. DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(80)90006-6 MR: 585519
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, O: alg, (mod), (grp)
  116. Sh:116
    Makowsky, J. A., & Shelah, S. (1983). Positive results in abstract model theory: a theory of compact logics. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 25(3), 263–299. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(83)90021-0 MR: 730857
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  117. Sh:117
    Rubin, M., & Shelah, S. (1987). Combinatorial problems on trees: partitions, \Delta-systems and large free subtrees. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 33(1), 43–81. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(87)90075-3 MR: 870686
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (pc)
  118. Sh:118
    Rubin, M., & Shelah, S. (1983). On the expressibility hierarchy of Magidor-Malitz quantifiers. J. Symbolic Logic, 48(3), 542–557. DOI: 10.2307/2273445 MR: 716614
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  119. Sh:119
    Shelah, S. (1981). Iterated forcing and changing cofinalities. Israel J. Math., 40(1), 1–32. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761815 MR: 636904
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (cont), (ref)
  120. Sh:120
    Shelah, S. (1981). Free limits of forcing and more on Aronszajn trees. Israel J. Math., 38(4), 315–334. DOI: 10.1007/BF02762777 MR: 617678
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (trees), (aron)
  121. Sh:121
    Magidor, M., Shelah, S., & Stavi, J. (1983). On the standard part of nonstandard models of set theory. J. Symbolic Logic, 48(1), 33–38. DOI: 10.2307/2273317 MR: 693245
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ods, (set), (ps-dst)
  122. Sh:122
    Shelah, S. (1981). On Fleissner’s diamond. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 22(1), 29–35. http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.ndjfl/1093883337 MR: 603754
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter)
  123. Sh:123
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1982). Monadic theory of order and topology in ZFC. Ann. Math. Logic, 23(2-3), 179–198 (1983). DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(82)90004-3 MR: 701125
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (mod), (mon), (cont)
  124. Sh:124
    Shelah, S. (1981). \aleph_\omega may have a strong partition relation. Israel J. Math., 38(4), 283–288. DOI: 10.1007/BF02762774 MR: 617675
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (pc)
  125. Sh:125
    Shelah, S. (1981). The consistency of \mathrm{Ext}(G,\,\mathbf Z)=\mathbf Q. Israel J. Math., 39(1-2), 74–82. DOI: 10.1007/BF02762854 MR: 617291
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (ab), (iter)
  126. Sh:126
    Shelah, S. (1981). On saturation for a predicate. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 22(3), 239–248. http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.ndjfl/1093883458 MR: 614121
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  127. Sh:127
    Shelah, S. (1981). On uncountable Boolean algebras with no uncountable pairwise comparable or incomparable sets of elements. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 22(4), 301–308. http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.ndjfl/1093883511 MR: 622361
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (cont), (inv(ba))
  128. Sh:128
    Shelah, S. (1985). Uncountable constructions for B.A., e.c. groups and Banach spaces. Israel J. Math., 51(4), 273–297. DOI: 10.1007/BF02764721 MR: 804487
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (ba), (grp), (diam)
  129. Sh:129
    Shelah, S. (1981). On the number of nonisomorphic models of cardinality \lambda L_{\infty \lambda }-equivalent to a fixed model. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 22(1), 5–10. http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.ndjfl/1093883334 MR: 603751
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (nni), (inf-log), (diam)
  130. Sh:130
    Pillay, A., & Shelah, S. (1985). Classification theory over a predicate. I. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 26(4), 361–376. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093870929 MR: 799506
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  131. Sh:131
    Shelah, S. (1982). The spectrum problem. I. \aleph_\varepsilon-saturated models, the main gap. Israel J. Math., 43(4), 324–356. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761237 MR: 693353
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (nni), (sta)
  132. Sh:132
    Shelah, S. (1982). The spectrum problem. II. Totally transcendental and infinite depth. Israel J. Math., 43(4), 357–364. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761238 MR: 693354
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (nni)
  133. Sh:133
    Shelah, S. (1982). On the number of nonisomorphic models in L_{\infty,\kappa } when \kappa is weakly compact. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 23(1), 21–26. http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.ndjfl/1093883562 MR: 634740
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (nni), (diam)
  134. Sh:134
    Gabbay, D. M., Pnueli, A., Shelah, S., & Stavi, J. (1980). On the Temporal Analysis of Fairness. In Proceedings of the 7th ACM SIGPLAN-SIGACT Symposium on Principles of Programming Languages, Association Comp. Machinery, NY, pp. 163–173. DOI: 10.1145/567446.567462
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  135. Sh:135
    Glass, A. M. W., Gurevich, Y., Holland, W. C., & Shelah, S. (1981). Rigid homogeneous chains. Math. Proc. Cambridge Philos. Soc., 89(1), 7–17. DOI: 10.1017/S0305004100057881 MR: 591966
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (leb), (linear order)
  136. Sh:136
    Shelah, S. (1983). Constructions of many complicated uncountable structures and Boolean algebras. Israel J. Math., 45(2-3), 100–146. DOI: 10.1007/BF02774012 MR: 719115
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (ba)
  137. Sh:137
    Shelah, S. (1983). The singular cardinals problem: independence results. In Surveys in set theory, Vol. 87, Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, pp. 116–134. DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511758867.004 MR: 823777
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  138. Sh:138
    Sageev, G., & Shelah, S. (1985). On the structure of \mathrm{Ext}(A,\mathbf Z) in ZFC^+. J. Symbolic Logic, 50(2), 302–315. DOI: 10.2307/2274216 MR: 793108
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  139. Sh:139
    Shelah, S. (1983). On the number of nonconjugate subgroups. Algebra Universalis, 16(2), 131–146. DOI: 10.1007/BF01191760 MR: 692252
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, O: alg, (mod), (nni), (grp)
  140. Sh:140
    Shelah, S. (1981). On endo-rigid, strongly \aleph_1-free abelian groups in \aleph_1. Israel J. Math., 40(3-4), 291–295 (1982). DOI: 10.1007/BF02761369 MR: 654584
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  141. Sh:141
    Gurevich, Y., Magidor, M., & Shelah, S. (1983). The monadic theory of \omega_2. J. Symbolic Logic, 48(2), 387–398. DOI: 10.2307/2273556 MR: 704093
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod), (mon)
  142. Sh:142
    Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (1983). The structure of saturated free algebras. Algebra Universalis, 17(2), 191–199. DOI: 10.1007/BF01194528 MR: 726272
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: alg, (mod), (ua)
  143. Sh:143
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1984). The monadic theory and the “next world”. Israel J. Math., 49(1-3), 55–68. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760646 MR: 788265
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, S: for, (mod), (mon), (cont), (pure(for))
  144. Sh:144
    Magidor, M., Shelah, S., & Stavi, J. (1984). Countably decomposable admissible sets. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 26(3), 287–361. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(84)90006-X MR: 747687
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ods, (set), (inf-log), (ps-dst)
  145. Sh:145
    Eklof, P. C., Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1984). Almost disjoint abelian groups. Israel J. Math., 49(1-3), 34–54. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760645 MR: 788264
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  146. Sh:146
    Abraham, U., & Shelah, S. (1983). Forcing closed unbounded sets. J. Symbolic Logic, 48(3), 643–657. DOI: 10.2307/2273456 MR: 716625
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (cont)
  147. Sh:147
    Harrington, L. A., & Shelah, S. (1982). The undecidability of the recursively enumerable degrees. Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. (N.S.), 6(1), 79–80. DOI: 10.1090/S0273-0979-1982-14970-9 MR: 634436
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: odo
  148. Sh:148
    Sageev, G., & Shelah, S. (1981). Weak compactness and the structure of \mathrm{Ext}(A,\,\mathbf Z). In Abelian group theory (Oberwolfach, 1981), Vol. 874, Springer, Berlin-New York, pp. 87–92. MR: 645920
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  149. Sh:149
    Friedman, S.-D., & Shelah, S. (1983). Tall \alpha-recursive structures. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 88(4), 672–678. DOI: 10.2307/2045460 MR: 702297
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: odo
  150. Sh:150
    Kaufmann, M., & Shelah, S. (1986). The Hanf number of stationary logic. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 27(1), 111–123. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093636530 MR: 819653
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  151. Sh:151
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1983). Interpreting second-order logic in the monadic theory of order. J. Symbolic Logic, 48(3), 816–828. DOI: 10.2307/2273475 MR: 716644
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt
  152. Sh:152
    Harrington, L. A., & Shelah, S. (1982). Counting equivalence classes for co-\kappa-Souslin equivalence relations. In Logic Colloquium ’80 (Prague, 1980), Vol. 108, North-Holland, Amsterdam-New York, pp. 147–152. MR: 673790
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: dst
  153. Sh:153
    Abraham, U., Rubin, M., & Shelah, S. (1985). On the consistency of some partition theorems for continuous colorings, and the structure of \aleph_1-dense real order types. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 29(2), 123–206. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(84)90024-1 MR: 801036
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (cont), (linear order)
  154. Sh:154
    Shelah, S., & Stanley, L. J. (1982). Generalized Martin’s axiom and Souslin’s hypothesis for higher cardinals. Israel J. Math., 43(3), 225–236. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761943 MR: 689980
    See [Sh:154a]

    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  155. Sh:155
    Shelah, S. (1986). The spectrum problem. III. Universal theories. Israel J. Math., 55(2), 229–256. DOI: 10.1007/BF02801997 MR: 868182
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, M: non, (mod), (nni)
  156. Sh:156
    Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (1985). Second-order quantifiers and the complexity of theories. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 26(3), 229–303. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093870870 MR: 796638
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod), (mon)
  157. Sh:157
    Lachlan, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1984). Stable structures homogeneous for a finite binary language. Israel J. Math., 49(1-3), 155–180. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760648 MR: 788267
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (fmt)
  158. Sh:158
    Harrington, L. A., Makkai, M., & Shelah, S. (1984). A proof of Vaught’s conjecture for \omega-stable theories. Israel J. Math., 49(1-3), 259–280. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760651 MR: 788270
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, M: non, (mod)
  159. Sh:159
    Shelah, S., & Woodin, W. H. (1984). Forcing the failure of CH by adding a real. J. Symbolic Logic, 49(4), 1185–1189. DOI: 10.2307/2274270 MR: 771786
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (cont)
  160. Sh:160
    Hodges, W., & Shelah, S. (1986). Naturality and definability. I. J. London Math. Soc. (2), 33(1), 1–12. DOI: 10.1112/jlms/s2-33.1.1 MR: 829382
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ods, (set), (mod)
  161. Sh:161
    Shelah, S. (1985). Incompactness in regular cardinals. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 26(3), 195–228. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093870869 MR: 796637
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (ab), (af)
  162. Sh:162
    Hart, B. T., Laflamme, C., & Shelah, S. (1993). Models with second order properties. V. A general principle. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 64(2), 169–194. arXiv: math/9311211 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(93)90033-A MR: 1241253
    type: article
    abstract: We present a general framework for carrying out some constructions. The unifying factor is a combinatorial principle which we present in terms of a game in which the first player challenges the second player to carry out constructions which would be much easier in a generic extension of the universe, and the second player cheats with the aid of $\Diamond$. Section 1 contains an axiomatic framework suitable for the description of a number of related constructions, and the statement of the main theorem in terms of this framework. In \S2 we illustrate the use of our combinatorial principle. The proof of the main result is then carried out in \S\S3-5.
    keywords: S: ico, (mod), (diam)
  163. Sh:163
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1985). To the decision problem for branching time logic. In Foundations of logic and linguistics (Salzburg, 1983), Plenum, New York, pp. 181–198. MR: 797952
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, M: non, (fmt), (trees)
  164. Sh:164
    Jarden, M., & Shelah, S. (1983). Pseudo-algebraically closed fields over rational function fields. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 87(2), 223–228. DOI: 10.2307/2043693 MR: 681825
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (leb)
  165. Sh:165
    Shelah, S., & Weiss, B. (1982). Measurable recurrence and quasi-invariant measures. Israel J. Math., 43(2), 154–160. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761726 MR: 689974
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: dst, O: top
  166. Sh:166
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1985). Stationary logic and its friends. I. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 26(2), 129–138. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093870821 MR: 783593
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  167. Sh:167
    Shelah, S., & Stanley, L. J. (1986). S-forcing. IIa. Adding diamonds and more applications: coding sets, Arhangelskiı̆’s problem and {\mathcal L}[Q^{<\omega}_1,Q^1_2]. Israel J. Math., 56(1), 1–65. With an appendix by John P. Burgess DOI: 10.1007/BF02776239 MR: 879913
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (gt), (diam)
  168. Sh:168
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1989). On the strength of the interpretation method. J. Symbolic Logic, 54(2), 305–323. DOI: 10.2307/2274850 MR: 997869
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (mod)
  169. Sh:169
    Eklof, P. C., Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1987). On strongly nonreflexive groups. Israel J. Math., 59(3), 283–298. DOI: 10.1007/BF02774142 MR: 920497
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  170. Sh:170
    Shelah, S. (1984). On logical sentences in PA. In Logic colloquium ’82 (Florence, 1982), Vol. 112, North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp. 145–160. DOI: 10.1016/S0049-237X(08)71815-9 MR: 762109
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm
  171. Sh:172
    Shelah, S. (1984). A combinatorial principle and endomorphism rings. I. On p-groups. Israel J. Math., 49(1-3), 239–257. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760650 MR: 788269
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (mod), (ab), (stal)
  172. Sh:173
    Aharoni, R., Nash-Williams, C. S. J. A., & Shelah, S. (1984). Marriage in infinite societies. In Progress in graph theory (Waterloo, Ont., 1982), Academic Press, Toronto, ON, pp. 71–79. MR: 776791
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  173. Sh:174
    Grossberg, R. P., & Shelah, S. (1983). On universal locally finite groups. Israel J. Math., 44(4), 289–302. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761988 MR: 710234
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod), (stal), (univ), (pure(large))
  174. Sh:175
    Shelah, S. (1984). On universal graphs without instances of CH. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 26(1), 75–87. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(84)90042-3 MR: 739914
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (graph), (univ)
  175. Sh:175a
    Shelah, S. (1990). Universal graphs without instances of CH: revisited. Israel J. Math., 70(1), 69–81. DOI: 10.1007/BF02807219 MR: 1057268
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (univ)
  176. Sh:176
    Shelah, S. (1984). Can you take Solovay’s inaccessible away? Israel J. Math., 48(1), 1–47. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760522 MR: 768264
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: dst, (set), (leb), (meag), (AC)
  177. Sh:177
    Shelah, S. (1984). More on proper forcing. J. Symbolic Logic, 49(4), 1034–1038. DOI: 10.2307/2274259 MR: 771775
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter)
  178. Sh:178
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1983). Random models and the Gödel case of the decision problem. J. Symbolic Logic, 48(4), 1120–1124 (1984). DOI: 10.2307/2273674 MR: 727799
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  179. Sh:179
    Shelah, S., & Steinhorn, C. I. (1986). On the nonaxiomatizability of some logics by finitely many schemas. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 27(1), 1–11. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093636517 MR: 819640
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  180. Sh:180
    Shelah, S., & Steinhorn, C. I. (1990). The nonaxiomatizability of L(Q^2_{\aleph_1}) by finitely many schemata. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 31(1), 1–13. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093635328 MR: 1043787
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt
  181. Sh:181
    Kaufmann, M., & Shelah, S. (1984). A nonconservativity result on global choice. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 27(3), 209–214. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(84)90026-5 MR: 765590
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ods, (set), (AC)
  182. Sh:182
    Abraham, U., & Shelah, S. (1986). On the intersection of closed unbounded sets. J. Symbolic Logic, 51(1), 180–189. DOI: 10.2307/2273954 MR: 830084
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for
  183. Sh:183
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1983). Rabin’s uniformization problem. J. Symbolic Logic, 48(4), 1105–1119 (1984). DOI: 10.2307/2273673 MR: 727798
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (mod), (mon)
  184. Sh:184
    Goldfarb, W. D., Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1984). A decidable subclass of the minimal Gödel class with identity. J. Symbolic Logic, 49(4), 1253–1261. DOI: 10.2307/2274275 MR: 771791
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (mod)
  185. Sh:185
    Shelah, S. (1983). Lifting problem of the measure algebra. Israel J. Math., 45(1), 90–96. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760673 MR: 710248
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (leb)
  186. Sh:186
    Shelah, S. (1984). Diamonds, uniformization. J. Symbolic Logic, 49(4), 1022–1033. DOI: 10.2307/2274258 MR: 771774
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (unif), (diam)
  187. Sh:187
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1986). Stationary logic and its friends. II. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 27(1), 39–50. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093636521 MR: 819644
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  188. Sh:188
    Shelah, S. (1984). A pair of nonisomorphic \equiv_{\infty \lambda } models of power \lambda for \lambda singular with \lambda ^\omega =\lambda. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 25(2), 97–104. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093870570 MR: 733596
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod), (nni), (inf-log)
  189. Sh:189
    Shelah, S. (1985). On the possible number \mathrm{no}(M) = the number of nonisomorphic models L_{\infty,\lambda}-equivalent to M of power \lambda, for \lambda singular. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 26(1), 36–50. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093870759 MR: 766665
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (nni), (inf-log)
  190. Sh:190
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (1985). Semirigid classes of cotorsion-free abelian groups. J. Algebra, 93(1), 136–150. DOI: 10.1016/0021-8693(85)90178-4 MR: 780487
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (ab)
  191. Sh:191
    Gitik, M., & Shelah, S. (1984). On the \mathbb I-condition. Israel J. Math., 48(2-3), 148–158. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761160 MR: 770697
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (cont)
  192. Sh:192
    Shelah, S. (1987). Uncountable groups have many nonconjugate subgroups. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 36(2), 153–206. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(87)90016-9 MR: 911580
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (nni), (grp), (wd)
  193. Sh:193
    Lehmann, D. J., & Shelah, S. (1982). Reasoning with time and chance. Inform. And Control, 53(3), 165–198. DOI: 10.1016/S0019-9958(82)91022-1 MR: 715529
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, O: fin, (fmt)
  194. Sh:194
    Aharoni, R., Nash-Williams, C. S. J. A., & Shelah, S. (1983). A general criterion for the existence of transversals. Proc. London Math. Soc. (3), 47(1), 43–68. DOI: 10.1112/plms/s3-47.1.43 MR: 698927
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  195. Sh:195
    Droste, M., & Shelah, S. (1985). A construction of all normal subgroup lattices of 2-transitive automorphism groups of linearly ordered sets. Israel J. Math., 51(3), 223–261. DOI: 10.1007/BF02772666 MR: 804485
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (set), (stal), (auto), (grp), (linear order)
  196. Sh:196
    Aharoni, R., Nash-Williams, C. S. J. A., & Shelah, S. (1984). Another form of a criterion for the existence of transversals. J. London Math. Soc. (2), 29(2), 193–203. DOI: 10.1112/jlms/s2-29.2.193 MR: 744087
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  197. Sh:198
    Levinski, J.-P., Magidor, M., & Shelah, S. (1990). Chang’s conjecture for \aleph_\omega. Israel J. Math., 69(2), 161–172. DOI: 10.1007/BF02937302 MR: 1045371
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  198. Sh:199
    Shelah, S. (1985). Remarks in abstract model theory. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 29(3), 255–288. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(85)90002-8 MR: 808815
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  199. Sh:200
    Shelah, S. (1985). Classification of first order theories which have a structure theorem. Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. (N.S.), 12(2), 227–232. DOI: 10.1090/S0273-0979-1985-15354-6 MR: 776474
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  200. Sh:201
    Kaufmann, M., & Shelah, S. (1985). On random models of finite power and monadic logic. Discrete Math., 54(3), 285–293. DOI: 10.1016/0012-365X(85)90112-8 MR: 790589
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt), (mon)
  201. Sh:202
    Shelah, S. (1984). On co-\kappa-Souslin relations. Israel J. Math., 47(2-3), 139–153. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760513 MR: 738165
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: dst, (linear order)
  202. Sh:203
    Ben-David, S., & Shelah, S. (1986). Souslin trees and successors of singular cardinals. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 30(3), 207–217. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(86)90020-5 MR: 836425
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (trees), (aron)
  203. Sh:204
    Magidor, M., & Shelah, S. (1994). When does almost free imply free? (For groups, transversals, etc.). J. Amer. Math. Soc., 7(4), 769–830. DOI: 10.2307/2152733 MR: 1249391
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (ab), (stal), (af)
  204. Sh:205
    Shelah, S. (1985). Monadic logic and Löwenheim numbers. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 28(2), 203–216. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(85)90026-0 MR: 779162
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod), (inf-log), (mon)
  205. Sh:206
    Shelah, S. (1988). Decomposing topological spaces into two rigid homeomorphic subspaces. Israel J. Math., 63(2), 183–211. DOI: 10.1007/BF02765038 MR: 968538
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (gt)
  206. Sh:207
    Shelah, S. (1984). On cardinal invariants of the continuum. In Axiomatic set theory (Boulder, Colo., 1983), Vol. 31, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, pp. 183–207. DOI: 10.1090/conm/031/763901 MR: 763901
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (iter), (inv)
  207. Sh:208
    Shelah, S. (1985). More on the weak diamond. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 28(3), 315–318. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(85)90019-3 MR: 790390
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (wd)
  208. Sh:209
    Shelah, S., & Todorčević, S. (1986). A note on small Baire spaces. Canad. J. Math., 38(3), 659–665. DOI: 10.4153/CJM-1986-033-8 MR: 845670
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (gt)
  209. Sh:210
    Bonnet, R., & Shelah, S. (1985). Narrow Boolean algebras. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 28(1), 1–12. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(85)90028-4 MR: 776283
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (ba)
  210. Sh:211
    Shelah, S. (1992). The Hanf numbers of stationary logic. II. Comparison with other logics. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 33(1), 1–12. arXiv: math/9201243 DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093636007 MR: 1149955
    type: article
    abstract: We show that the ordering of the Hanf number of $L_{\omega,\omega}(wo)$ (well ordering), $L^c_{\omega,\omega}$ (quantification on countable sets), $L_{\omega, \omega}(aa)$ (stationary logic) and second order logic, have no more restraints provable in $ZFC$ than previously known (those independence proofs assume $CON(ZFC)$ only). We also get results on corresponding logics for $L_{\lambda,\mu}$.
    keywords: M: smt, (mod), (inf-log)
  211. Sh:213
    Denenberg, L., Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1986). Definability by constant-depth polynomial-size circuits. Inform. And Control, 70(2-3), 216–240. DOI: 10.1016/S0019-9958(86)80006-7 MR: 859107
    type: article
    abstract: We investigate the expressive power of constant-depth polynomial-size circuit models. In particular, we construct a circuit model whose expressive power is precisely that of first-order logic.
    keywords: O: fin, (fmt)
  212. Sh:214
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1986). \omega-elongations and Crawley’s problem. Pacific J. Math., 121(1), 121–132. http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.pjm/1102702803 MR: 815039
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  213. Sh:214a
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1986). The solution to Crawley’s problem. Pacific J. Math., 121(1), 133–134. http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.pjm/1102702804 MR: 815040
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  214. Sh:215
    Harrington, L. A., Marker, D. E., & Shelah, S. (1988). Borel orderings. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 310(1), 293–302. DOI: 10.2307/2001122 MR: 965754
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: dst, (linear order)
  215. Sh:216
    Holland, W. C., Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1985). Lawless order. Order, 1(4), 383–397. DOI: 10.1007/BF00582744 MR: 787550
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, S: ico, (grp), (linear order)
  216. Sh:216a
    Holland, W. C., Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1986). Total orders whose carried groups satisfy no laws. In Algebra and order (Luminy-Marseille, 1984), Vol. 14, Heldermann, Berlin, pp. 29–33. MR: 891446
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, S: ico, (grp), (linear order)
  217. Sh:218
    Shelah, S. (1985). On measure and category. Israel J. Math., 52(1-2), 110–114. DOI: 10.1007/BF02776084 MR: 815606
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: dst, (leb), (meag)
  218. Sh:219
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (1985). Modules over arbitrary domains. Math. Z., 188(3), 325–337. DOI: 10.1007/BF01159179 MR: 771988
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  219. Sh:220
    Shelah, S. (1987). Existence of many L_{\infty,\lambda}-equivalent, nonisomorphic models of T of power \lambda. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 34(3), 291–310. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(87)90005-4 MR: 899084
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (nni), (inf-log)
  220. Sh:221
    Abraham, U., Shelah, S., & Solovay, R. M. (1987). Squares with diamonds and Souslin trees with special squares. Fund. Math., 127(2), 133–162. DOI: 10.4064/fm-127-2-133-162 MR: 882623
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set)
  221. Sh:222
    Grossberg, R. P., & Shelah, S. (1986). On the number of nonisomorphic models of an infinitary theory which has the infinitary order property. I. J. Symbolic Logic, 51(2), 302–322. DOI: 10.2307/2274053 MR: 840407
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (nni), (inf-log)
  222. Sh:223
    Droste, M., & Shelah, S. (1987). On the universality of systems of words in permutation groups. Pacific J. Math., 127(2), 321–328. http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.pjm/1102699565 MR: 881762
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ua)
  223. Sh:224
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (1986). Modules over arbitrary domains. II. Fund. Math., 126(3), 217–243. DOI: 10.4064/fm-126-3-217-243 MR: 882431
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  224. Sh:225
    Shelah, S. (1987). On the number of strongly \aleph_\epsilon-saturated models of power \lambda. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 36(3), 279–287. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(87)90020-0 MR: 915901
    See [Sh:225a]

    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (sta)
  225. Sh:225a
    Shelah, S. (1988). Number of strongly \aleph_\epsilon saturated models—an addition. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 40(1), 89–91. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(88)90041-3 MR: 965589
    improvement of [Sh:225]

    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (sta)
  226. Sh:226
    Foreman, M. D., Magidor, M., & Shelah, S. (1986). 0^\sharp and some forcing principles. J. Symbolic Logic, 51(1), 39–46. DOI: 10.2307/2273940 MR: 830070
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  227. Sh:227
    Shelah, S. (1984). A combinatorial theorem and endomorphism rings of abelian groups. II. In Abelian groups and modules (Udine, 1984), Vol. 287, Springer, Vienna, pp. 37–86. DOI: 10.1007/978-3-7091-2814-5_3 MR: 789808
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (ab)
  228. Sh:230
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1985). The decision problem for branching time logic. J. Symbolic Logic, 50(3), 668–681. DOI: 10.2307/2274321 MR: 805676
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, M: odm, O: fin
  229. Sh:231
    Juhász, I., & Shelah, S. (1986). How large can a hereditarily separable or hereditarily Lindelöf space be? Israel J. Math., 53(3), 355–364. DOI: 10.1007/BF02786567 MR: 852486
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (gt)
  230. Sh:235
    Shelah, S., & Soifer, A. (1986). Two problems on \aleph_0-indecomposable abelian groups. J. Algebra, 99(2), 359–369. DOI: 10.1016/0021-8693(86)90033-5 MR: 837550
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab)
  231. Sh:236
    Ben-David, S., & Shelah, S. (1986). Nonspecial Aronszajn trees on \aleph_{\omega+1}. Israel J. Math., 53(1), 93–96. DOI: 10.1007/BF02772672 MR: 861900
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (aron)
  232. Sh:238
    Grossberg, R. P., & Shelah, S. (1986). A nonstructure theorem for an infinitary theory which has the unsuperstability property. Illinois J. Math., 30(2), 364–390. http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.ijm/1256044645 MR: 840135
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, M: nec, M: non, (mod)
  233. Sh:239
    Shelah, S., & Soifer, A. (1986). Countable \aleph_0-indecomposable mixed abelian groups of finite torsion-free rank. J. Algebra, 100(2), 421–429. DOI: 10.1016/0021-8693(86)90085-2 MR: 840585
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab)
  234. Sh:240
    Foreman, M. D., Magidor, M., & Shelah, S. (1988). Martin’s maximum, saturated ideals, and nonregular ultrafilters. I. Ann. Of Math. (2), 127(1), 1–47. DOI: 10.2307/1971415 MR: 924672
    See [Sh:240a]

    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter)
  235. Sh:241
    Shelah, S., & Woodin, W. H. (1990). Large cardinals imply that every reasonably definable set of reals is Lebesgue measurable. Israel J. Math., 70(3), 381–394. DOI: 10.1007/BF02801471 MR: 1074499
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: dst, (set), (leb)
  236. Sh:242
    Blass, A. R., & Shelah, S. (1987). There may be simple P_{\aleph_1}- and P_{\aleph_2}-points and the Rudin-Keisler ordering may be downward directed. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 33(3), 213–243. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(87)90082-0 MR: 879489
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (inv), (large)
  237. Sh:243
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1987). Expected computation time for Hamiltonian path problem. SIAM J. Comput., 16(3), 486–502. DOI: 10.1137/0216034 MR: 889404
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: fin, (fc)
  238. Sh:244a
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1986). Fixed-point extensions of first-order logic. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 32(3), 265–280. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(86)90055-2 MR: 865992
    See [Sh:244]

    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin
  239. Sh:245
    Compton, K. J., Henson, C. W., & Shelah, S. (1987). Nonconvergence, undecidability, and intractability in asymptotic problems. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 36(3), 207–224. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(87)90017-0 MR: 915898
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  240. Sh:246
    Shelah, S. (1991). On a problem in cylindric algebra. In Algebraic logic (Budapest, 1988), Vol. 54, North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp. 645–664. MR: 1153444
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (mod)
  241. Sh:249
    Hajnal, A., Juhász, I., & Shelah, S. (1986). Splitting strongly almost disjoint families. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 295(1), 369–387. DOI: 10.2307/2000161 MR: 831204
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  242. Sh:250
    Shelah, S. (1988). Some notes on iterated forcing with 2^{\aleph_0}>\aleph_2. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 29(1), 1–17. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093637766 MR: 932690
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter)
  243. Sh:251
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1987). When \kappa-free implies strongly \kappa-free. In Abelian group theory (Oberwolfach, 1985), Gordon; Breach, New York, pp. 137–148. MR: 1011309
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (af)
  244. Sh:252
    Foreman, M. D., Magidor, M., & Shelah, S. (1988). Martin’s maximum, saturated ideals and nonregular ultrafilters. II. Ann. Of Math. (2), 127(3), 521–545. DOI: 10.2307/2007004 MR: 942519
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (normal)
  245. Sh:253
    Shelah, S. (1987). Iterated forcing and normal ideals on \omega_1. Israel J. Math., 60(3), 345–380. DOI: 10.1007/BF02780398 MR: 937796
    initial version of Ch. XIII of [Sh:f]

    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (normal)
  246. Sh:254
    Baumgartner, J. E., & Shelah, S. (1987). Remarks on superatomic Boolean algebras. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 33(2), 109–129. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(87)90077-7 MR: 874021
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (ba)
  247. Sh:255
    Eklof, P. C., & Shelah, S. (1987). On groups A such that A\oplus \mathbf Z^n\cong A. In Abelian group theory (Oberwolfach, 1985), Gordon; Breach, New York, pp. 149–163. MR: 1011310
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  248. Sh:256
    Shelah, S. (1987). More on powers of singular cardinals. Israel J. Math., 59(3), 299–326. DOI: 10.1007/BF02774143 MR: 920498
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: pcf, (set), (normal)
  249. Sh:257
    Blass, A. R., & Shelah, S. (1989). Ultrafilters with small generating sets. Israel J. Math., 65(3), 259–271. DOI: 10.1007/BF02764864 MR: 1005010
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (inv)
  250. Sh:258
    Shelah, S., & Stanley, L. J. (1987). A theorem and some consistency results in partition calculus. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 36(2), 119–152. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(87)90015-7 MR: 911579
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (pc)
  251. Sh:260
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (1987). Extraspecial p-groups. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 34(1), 87–97. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(87)90041-8 MR: 887554
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (stal)
  252. Sh:261
    Shelah, S. (1988). A graph which embeds all small graphs on any large set of vertices. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 38(2), 171–183. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(88)90052-8 MR: 938374
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (graph)
  253. Sh:262
    Shelah, S. (1989). The number of pairwise non-elementarily-embeddable models. J. Symbolic Logic, 54(4), 1431–1455. DOI: 10.2307/2274824 MR: 1026608
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (mod)
  254. Sh:263
    Shelah, S. (1987). Semiproper forcing axiom implies Martin maximum but not PFA^+. J. Symbolic Logic, 52(2), 360–367. DOI: 10.2307/2274385 MR: 890443
    represented in Ch. XVII of [Sh:f]

    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  255. Sh:264
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (1988). A Banach space on which there are few operators. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 104(1), 101–105. DOI: 10.2307/2047469 MR: 958051
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non
  256. Sh:265
    Dugas, M. H., Fay, T. H., & Shelah, S. (1987). Singly cogenerated annihilator classes. J. Algebra, 109(1), 127–137. DOI: 10.1016/0021-8693(87)90168-2 MR: 898341
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (ab)
  257. Sh:266
    Shelah, S. (2019). Compactness in singular cardinals revisited. Sarajevo Journal of Mathematics, 15 (28)(2), 201–208. arXiv: 1401.3175 DOI: 10.5644/SJM.15.02.05
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg
  258. Sh:267
    Fleissner, W. G., & Shelah, S. (1989). Collectionwise Hausdorff: incompactness at singulars. Topology Appl., 31(2), 101–107. DOI: 10.1016/0166-8641(89)90074-6 MR: 994403
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (gt)
  259. Sh:268
    Hajnal, A., Kanamori, A., & Shelah, S. (1987). Regressive partition relations for infinite cardinals. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 299(1), 145–154. DOI: 10.2307/2000486 MR: 869404
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (pc)
  260. Sh:269
    Shelah, S. (1989). “Gap 1” two-cardinal principles and the omitting types theorem for \mathcal L (Q). Israel J. Math., 65(2), 133–152. DOI: 10.1007/BF02764857 MR: 998667
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, M: odm
  261. Sh:270
    Shelah, S. (1989). Baire irresolvable spaces and lifting for a layered ideal. Topology Appl., 33(3), 217–221. DOI: 10.1016/0166-8641(89)90102-8 MR: 1026923
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (gt)
  262. Sh:271
    Hodges, W., & Shelah, S. (1991). There are reasonably nice logics. J. Symbolic Logic, 56(1), 300–322. DOI: 10.2307/2274921 MR: 1131747
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  263. Sh:272
    Shelah, S. (1987). On almost categorical theories. In Classification theory (Chicago, IL, 1985), Vol. 1292, Springer, Berlin, pp. 498–500. DOI: 10.1007/BFb0082244 MR: 1033035
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (sta), (cat)
  264. Sh:273
    Shelah, S. (1988). Can the fundamental (homotopy) group of a space be the rationals? Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 103(2), 627–632. DOI: 10.2307/2047190 MR: 943095
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: dst, O: top
  265. Sh:274
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1989). Uniformization principles. J. Symbolic Logic, 54(2), 441–459. DOI: 10.2307/2274859 MR: 997878
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (ab), (unif)
  266. Sh:275
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1989). L_{\infty\omega}-free algebras. Algebra Universalis, 26(3), 351–366. DOI: 10.1007/BF01211842 MR: 1044855
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: nec, (ua)
  267. Sh:276
    Shelah, S. (1988). Was Sierpiński right? I. Israel J. Math., 62(3), 355–380. DOI: 10.1007/BF02783304 MR: 955139
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (iter), (pc)
  268. Sh:277
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1989). Nearly linear time. In Logic at Botik ’89 (Pereslavl-Zalesskiy, 1989), Vol. 363, Springer, Berlin, pp. 108–118. DOI: 10.1007/3-540-51237-3_10 MR: 1030571
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin
  269. Sh:278
    Chatzidakis, Z. M., Cherlin, G. L., Shelah, S., Srour, G., & Wood, C. (1987). Orthogonality of types in separably closed fields. In Classification theory (Chicago, IL, 1985), Vol. 1292, Springer, Berlin, pp. 72–88. DOI: 10.1007/BFb0082232 MR: 1033023
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (sta)
  270. Sh:279
    Shelah, S., & Stanley, L. J. (1988). Weakly compact cardinals and nonspecial Aronszajn trees. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 104(3), 887–897. DOI: 10.2307/2046812 MR: 964870
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (large), (trees), (aron)
  271. Sh:280
    Shelah, S. (1990). Strong negative partition above the continuum. J. Symbolic Logic, 55(1), 21–31. DOI: 10.2307/2274951 MR: 1043541
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  272. Sh:281
    Drezner, Z., & Shelah, S. (1987). On the complexity of the Elzinga-Hearn algorithm for the 1-center problem. Math. Oper. Res., 12(2), 255–261. DOI: 10.1287/moor.12.2.255 MR: 888974
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: fin, (fc)
  273. Sh:282
    Shelah, S. (1988). Successors of singulars, cofinalities of reduced products of cardinals and productivity of chain conditions. Israel J. Math., 62(2), 213–256. DOI: 10.1007/BF02787123 MR: 947823
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  274. Sh:283
    Shelah, S. (1987). On reconstructing separable reduced p-groups with a given socle. Israel J. Math., 60(2), 146–166. DOI: 10.1007/BF02790788 MR: 931873
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (ab)
  275. Sh:284a
    Shelah, S. (1988). Notes on monadic logic. Part A. Monadic theory of the real line. Israel J. Math., 63(3), 335–352. DOI: 10.1007/BF02778038 MR: 969946
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt
  276. Sh:284b
    Shelah, S. (1990). Notes on monadic logic. Part B: Complexity of linear orders in ZFC. Israel J. Math., 69(1), 94–116. DOI: 10.1007/BF02764732 MR: 1046176
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt
  277. Sh:284c
    Shelah, S. (1990). More on monadic logic. Part C. Monadically interpreting in stable unsuperstable \mathcal T and the monadic theory of {}^\omega\lambda. Israel J. Math., 70(3), 353–364. DOI: 10.1007/BF02801469 MR: 1074497
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt
  278. Sh:284d
    Shelah, S. (1989). More on monadic logic. Part D: A note on addition of theories. Israel J. Math., 68(3), 302–306. DOI: 10.1007/BF02764986 MR: 1039475
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt
  279. Sh:285
    Makkai, M., & Shelah, S. (1990). Categoricity of theories in L_{\kappa\omega}, with \kappa a compact cardinal. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 47(1), 41–97. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(90)90016-U MR: 1050561
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, M: nec, (mod), (inf-log), (cat)
  280. Sh:286
    Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1988). Q-sets do not necessarily have strong measure zero. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 102(3), 681–683. DOI: 10.2307/2047245 MR: 929002
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: str, (set), (leb)
  281. Sh:287
    Blass, A. R., & Shelah, S. (1989). Near coherence of filters. III. A simplified consistency proof. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 30(4), 530–538. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093635236 MR: 1036674
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (inv), (large)
  282. Sh:288
    Shelah, S. (1992). Strong partition relations below the power set: consistency; was Sierpiński right? II. In Sets, graphs and numbers (Budapest, 1991), Vol. 60, North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp. 637–668. arXiv: math/9201244 MR: 1218224
    type: article
    abstract: We continue here [Sh276] but we do not relay on it. The motivation was a conjecture of Galvin stating that $2^{\omega}\geq \omega_2$ + $\omega_2\to [\omega_1]^{n}_{h(n)}$ is consistent for a suitable $h:\omega\to\omega$. In section 5 we disprove this and give similar negative results. In section 3 we prove the consistency of the conjecture replacing $\omega_2$ by $2^\omega$, which is quite large, starting with an Erd\H os cardinal. In section 1 we present iteration lemmas which are needed when we replace $\omega$ by a larger $\lambda$ and in section 4 we generalize a theorem of Halpern and Lauchli replacing $\omega$ by a larger $\lambda$.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (iter), (pc)
  283. Sh:289
    Shelah, S. (1989). Consistency of positive partition theorems for graphs and models. In Set theory and its applications (Toronto, ON, 1987), Vol. 1401, Springer, Berlin, pp. 167–193. DOI: 10.1007/BFb0097339 MR: 1031773
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (pc)
  284. Sh:290
    Biró, B., & Shelah, S. (1988). Isomorphic but not lower base-isomorphic cylindric set algebras. J. Symbolic Logic, 53(3), 846–853. DOI: 10.2307/2274576 MR: 961003
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: alg, (mod)
  285. Sh:291
    Mekler, A. H., Nelson, E. M., & Shelah, S. (1993). A variety with solvable, but not uniformly solvable, word problem. Proc. London Math. Soc. (3), 66(2), 225–256. arXiv: math/9301203 DOI: 10.1112/plms/s3-66.2.225 MR: 1199065
    type: article
    abstract: In the literature two notions of the word problem for a variety occur. A variety has a {\em decidable word problem} if every finitely presented algebra in the variety has a decidable word problem. It has a {\em uniformly decidable word problem} if there is an algorithm which given a finite presentation produces an algorithm for solving the word problem of the algebra so presented. A variety is given with finitely many axioms having a decidable, but not uniformly decidable, word problem. Other related examples are given as well.
    keywords: O: alg, (ua)
  286. Sh:292
    Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1988). Souslin forcing. J. Symbolic Logic, 53(4), 1188–1207. DOI: 10.2307/2274613 MR: 973109
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  287. Sh:293
    Shelah, S., & Stanley, L. J. (1993). More consistency results in partition calculus. Israel J. Math., 81(1-2), 97–110. DOI: 10.1007/BF02761299 MR: 1231180
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (pc)
  288. Sh:294
    Shelah, S., & Stanley, L. J. (1992). Coding and reshaping when there are no sharps. In Set theory of the continuum (Berkeley, CA, 1989), Vol. 26, Springer, New York, pp. 407–416. arXiv: math/9201249 DOI: 10.1007/978-1-4613-9754-0_21 MR: 1233827
    type: article
    abstract: Assuming $0^\sharp$ does not exist, $\kappa$ is an uncountable cardinal and for all cardinals $\lambda$ with $\kappa \leq \lambda <\kappa^{+\omega},\ 2^\lambda = \lambda^+$, we present a \lq\lq mini-coding between $\kappa$ and $\kappa^{+\omega}$. This allows us to prove that any subset of $\kappa^{+\omega}$ can be coded into a subset, $W$ of $\kappa^+$ which, further, \lq\lq reshapes the interval $[\kappa,\ \kappa^+)$, i.e., for all $\kappa < \delta < \kappa^+, \ \kappa = (card\ \delta)^{L[W \cap \delta]}$. We sketch two applications of this result, assuming $0^\sharp$ does not exist. First, we point out that this shows that any set can be coded by a real, via a set forcing. The second application involves a notion of abstract condensation, due to Woodin. Our methods can be used to show that for any cardinal $\mu$, condensation for $\mu$ holds in a generic extension by a set forcing.
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  289. Sh:296
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (1989). Nontrivial homeomorphisms of \beta \mathbf N\setminus \mathbf N without the continuum hypothesis. Fund. Math., 132(2), 135–141. DOI: 10.4064/fm-132-2-135-141 MR: 1002627
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (gt)
  290. Sh:297
    Hodkinson, I. M., & Shelah, S. (1993). A construction of many uncountable rings using SFP domains and Aronszajn trees. Proc. London Math. Soc. (3), 67(3), 449–492. DOI: 10.1112/plms/s3-67.3.449 MR: 1238042
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, O: alg, (stal), (aron)
  291. Sh:298
    Eklof, P. C., & Shelah, S. (1987). A calculation of injective dimension over valuation domains. Rend. Sem. Mat. Univ. Padova, 78, 279–284. http://www.numdam.org/item?id=RSMUP_1987__78__279_0 MR: 934519
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  292. Sh:299
    Shelah, S. (1987). Taxonomy of universal and other classes. In Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians (Berkeley, Calif., 1986), Vol. 1, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, pp. 154–162. MR: 934221
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, M: nec, (mod)
  293. Sh:300
    Shelah, S. (1987). Universal classes. In Classification theory (Chicago, IL, 1985), Vol. 1292, Springer, Berlin, pp. 264–418. DOI: 10.1007/BFb0082242 MR: 1033033
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: nec, (mod)
  294. Sh:302
    Grossberg, R. P., & Shelah, S. (1989). On the structure of \mathrm{Ext}_p(G,\mathbf Z). J. Algebra, 121(1), 117–128. DOI: 10.1016/0021-8693(89)90088-4 MR: 992319
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: dst, O: alg, (ab), (wh), (ps-dst)
  295. Sh:302a
    Grossberg, R. P., & Shelah, S. (1998). On cardinalities in quotients of inverse limits of groups. Math. Japon., 47(2), 189–197. arXiv: math/9911225 MR: 1615081
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\lambda$ be $\aleph_0$ or a strong limit of cofinality $\aleph_0$. Suppose that $\langle G_m,\pi_{m,n}\;:\;m\leq n<\omega\rangle$ and $\langle H_m,\pi^t_{m,n}\;:\;m\leq n<\omega\rangle$ are projective systems of groups of cardinality less than $\lambda$ and suppose that for every $n< \omega$ there is a homorphism $\sigma:H_n\rightarrow G_n$ such that all the diagrams commute. If for every $\mu< \lambda$ there exists $\langle f_i\in G_{\omega} \;:\;i< \mu\rangle$ such that $i\neq j\Longrightarrow f_if_j^{-1}\not\in\sigma_{\omega}(H_{\omega})$ then there exists $\langle f_i\in G_{\omega} \;:\;i < 2^{\lambda}\rangle$ such that $i\neq j\Longrightarrow f_if_j^{-1}\not\in\sigma_{\omega}(H_{\omega})$.
    keywords: S: dst, O: alg, (ab), (wh), (ps-dst)
  296. Sh:303
    Komjáth, P., & Shelah, S. (1988). Forcing constructions for uncountably chromatic graphs. J. Symbolic Logic, 53(3), 696–707. DOI: 10.2307/2274566 MR: 960993
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (graph)
  297. Sh:304
    Shelah, S., & Spencer, J. H. (1988). Zero-one laws for sparse random graphs. J. Amer. Math. Soc., 1(1), 97–115. DOI: 10.2307/1990968 MR: 924703
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt), (graph)
  298. Sh:305
    Shelah, S., & Thomas, R., Simon. (1989). Subgroups of small index in infinite symmetric groups. II. J. Symbolic Logic, 54(1), 95–99. DOI: 10.2307/2275018 MR: 987325
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico
  299. Sh:306
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1990). Determining abelian p-groups from their n-socles. Comm. Algebra, 18(2), 287–307. DOI: 10.1080/00927879008823915 MR: 1047311
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (ab)
  300. Sh:307
    Buechler, S., & Shelah, S. (1989). On the existence of regular types. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 45(3), 277–308. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(89)90039-0 MR: 1032833
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (sta)
  301. Sh:308
    Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1990). The Kunen-Miller chart (Lebesgue measure, the Baire property, Laver reals and preservation theorems for forcing). J. Symbolic Logic, 55(3), 909–927. DOI: 10.2307/2274464 MR: 1071305
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (leb), (inv), (meag)
  302. Sh:310
    Gitik, M., & Shelah, S. (1999). Cardinal preserving ideals. J. Symbolic Logic, 64(4), 1527–1551. arXiv: math/9605234 DOI: 10.2307/2586794 MR: 1780068
    type: article
    abstract: We give some general criteria, when $\kappa$-complete forcing preserves largeness properties -- like $\kappa$-presaturation of normal ideals on $\lambda$ (even when they concentrate on small cofinalities). Then we quite accurately obtain the consistency strength ``$NS_\lambda$ is $\aleph_1$-preserving", for $\lambda >\aleph_2$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (sta), (ref)
  303. Sh:312
    Shelah, S. (2017). Existentially closed locally finite groups (Sh312). In Beyond first order model theory, CRC Press, Boca Raton, FL, pp. 221–298. arXiv: 1102.5578 MR: 3729328
    type: article
    abstract: We investigate this class of groups originally called ulf (universal locally finite groups) of cardinality $\lambda$. We prove that for every locally finite group $G$ there is a canonical existentially closed extention of the same cardinality, unique up to isomorphism and increasing with $G$. Also we get, e.g. existence of complete members (i.e. with no non-inner automorphisms) in many cardinals (provably in ZFC). We also get a parallel to stability theory in the sense of investigating definable types.
    keywords: M: non, (stal), (grp)
  304. Sh:313
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1988). Diamond and \lambda-systems. Fund. Math., 131(1), 45–51. DOI: 10.4064/fm-131-1-45-51 MR: 970913
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (diam)
  305. Sh:314
    Mekler, A. H., Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (1999). On the p-rank of Ext. Israel J. Math., 112, 327–356. arXiv: math/9806165 DOI: 10.1007/BF02773487 MR: 1714978
    type: article
    abstract: Assume $V=L$ and $\lambda$ is regular smaller than the first weakly compact cardinal. Under those circumstances and with arbitrary requirements on the structure of $Ext(G,{\mathbb Z})$ (under well known limitations), we construct an abelian group $G$ of cardinality $\lambda$ such that for no $G'\subseteq G$, $|G'|< \lambda$ is $G/G'$ free and $Ext(G,{\mathbb Z})$ realizes our requirements.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (ab), (wh)
  306. Sh:315
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (1988). PFA implies all automorphisms are trivial. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 104(4), 1220–1225. DOI: 10.2307/2047617 MR: 935111
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  307. Sh:316
    Fuchs, L., & Shelah, S. (1989). Kaplansky’s problem on valuation rings. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 105(1), 25–30. DOI: 10.2307/2046728 MR: 929431
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  308. Sh:317
    Becker, T., Fuchs, L., & Shelah, S. (1989). Whitehead modules over domains. Forum Math., 1(1), 53–68. DOI: 10.1515/form.1989.1.53 MR: 978975
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  309. Sh:318
    Macpherson, D., Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1991). The number of infinite substructures. Math. Proc. Cambridge Philos. Soc., 109(1), 193–209. DOI: 10.1017/S0305004100069668 MR: 1075131
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (nni)
  310. Sh:319
    Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1989). Martin’s axioms, measurability and equiconsistency results. J. Symbolic Logic, 54(1), 78–94. DOI: 10.2307/2275017 MR: 987324
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (leb)
  311. Sh:320
    Juhász, I., Shelah, S., & Soukup, L. (1988). More on countably compact, locally countable spaces. Israel J. Math., 62(3), 302–310. DOI: 10.1007/BF02783299 MR: 955134
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: top, (gt)
  312. Sh:321
    Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1989). \Delta^1_2-sets of reals. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 42(3), 207–223. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(89)90016-X MR: 998607
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: str, S: dst, (set)
  313. Sh:323
    Hart, B. T., & Shelah, S. (1990). Categoricity over P for first order T or categoricity for \phi\in\mathcal L_{\omega_1\omega} can stop at \aleph_k while holding for \aleph_0,\cdots,\aleph_{k-1}. Israel J. Math., 70(2), 219–235. arXiv: math/9201240 DOI: 10.1007/BF02807869 MR: 1070267
    type: article
    abstract: Suppose $L$ is a relational language and $P\in L$ is a unary predicate. If $M$ is an $L$-structure then $P(M)$ is the $L$-structure formed as the substructure of $M$ with domain $\{a: M\models P(a)\}$. Now suppose $T$ is a complete first order theory in $L$ with infinite models. Following Hodges, we say that T is relatively $\lambda$-categorical if whenever $M$, $N\models T$, $P(M)=P(N)$, $|P(M)|=\lambda$ then there is an isomorphism $i:M\rightarrow N$ which is the identity on $P(M)$. $T$ is relatively categorical if it is relatively $\lambda$-categorical for every $\lambda$. The question arises whether the relative $\lambda$-categoricity of $T$ for some $\lambda>|T|$ implies that $T$ is relatively categorical. In this paper, we provide an example, for every $k>0$, of a theory $T_k$ and an $L_{\omega_1\omega}$ sentence $\varphi_k$ so that $T_k$ is relatively $\aleph_n$-categorical for $n < k$ and $\varphi_k$ is $\aleph_n$-categorical for $n<k$ but $T_k$ is not relatively $\beth_k$-categorical and $\varphi_k$ is not $\beth_k$-categorical.
    keywords: M: nec, (mod), (cat)
  314. Sh:324
    Magidor, M., & Shelah, S. (1996). The tree property at successors of singular cardinals. Arch. Math. Logic, 35(5-6), 385–404. arXiv: math/9501220 DOI: 10.1007/s001530050052 MR: 1420265
    type: article
    abstract: Assuming some large cardinals, a model of ZFC is obtained in which $\aleph_{omega+1}$ carries no Aronszajn trees. It is also shown that if $\lambda$ is a singular limit of strongly compact cardinals, then $\lambda^+$ carries no Aronszajn trees.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (large), (aron)
  315. Sh:325
    Dugas, M. H., & Shelah, S. (1989). E-transitive groups in L. In Abelian group theory (Perth, 1987), Vol. 87, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, pp. 191–199. DOI: 10.1090/conm/087/995276 MR: 995276
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (ab)
  316. Sh:326
    Shelah, S. (1992). Vive la différence. I. Nonisomorphism of ultrapowers of countable models. In Set theory of the continuum (Berkeley, CA, 1989), Vol. 26, Springer, New York, pp. 357–405. arXiv: math/9201245 DOI: 10.1007/978-1-4613-9754-0_20 MR: 1233826
    See [Sh:326a]

    type: article
    abstract: We show that it is not provable in ZFC that any two countable elementarily equivalent structures have isomorphic ultrapowers relative to some ultrafilter on $\omega$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (iter), (set-mod), (up), (creatures)
  317. Sh:327
    Shelah, S. (1991). Strong negative partition relations below the continuum. Acta Math. Hungar., 58(1-2), 95–100. DOI: 10.1007/BF01903551 MR: 1152830
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  318. Sh:328
    Shelah, S., & Thomas, R., Simon. (1988). Implausible subgroups of infinite symmetric groups. Bull. London Math. Soc., 20(4), 313–318. DOI: 10.1112/blms/20.4.313 MR: 940283
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico
  319. Sh:329
    Shelah, S. (1988). Primitive recursive bounds for van der Waerden numbers. J. Amer. Math. Soc., 1(3), 683–697. DOI: 10.2307/1990952 MR: 929498
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: fin, (fc)
  320. Sh:330
    Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (1990). The primal framework. I. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 46(3), 235–264. arXiv: math/9201241 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(90)90005-M MR: 1049388
    type: article
    abstract: This the first of a series of articles dealing with abstract classification theory. The apparatus to assign systems of cardinal invariants to models of a first order theory (or determine its impossibility) is developed in [Sh:a]. It is natural to try to extend this theory to classes of models which are described in other ways. Work on the classification theory for nonelementary classes [Sh:88] and for universal classes [Sh:300] led to the conclusion that an axiomatic approach provided the best setting for developing a theory of wider application. In the first chapter we describe the axioms on which the remainder of the article depends and give some examples and context to justify this level of generality. The study of universal classes takes as a primitive the notion of closing a subset under functions to obtain a model. We replace that concept by the notion of a prime model. We begin the detailed discussion of this idea in Chapter II. One of the important contributions of classification theory is the recognition that large models can often be analyzed by means of a family of small models indexed by a tree of height at most $\omega$. More precisely, the analyzed model is prime over such a tree. Chapter III provides sufficient conditions for prime models over such trees to exist.
    keywords: M: nec, (mod)
  321. Sh:332
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1988). Nondeterministic Linear Tasks May Require Substantially Nonlinear Deterministic Time in the Case of Sublinear Work Space. In Proceedings of the Twentieth Annual ACM Symposium on Theory of Computing, New York, NY, USA: ACM, pp. 281–289. DOI: 10.1145/62212.62239
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: fin
  322. Sh:332a
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1990). Nondeterministic linear-time tasks may require substantially nonlinear deterministic time in the case of sublinear work space. J. Assoc. Comput. Mach., 37(3), 674–687. DOI: 10.1145/79147.214070 MR: 1072274
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: fin
  323. Sh:334
    Hrushovski, E., & Shelah, S. (1991). Stability and omitting types. Israel J. Math., 74(2-3), 289–321. DOI: 10.1007/BF02775793 MR: 1135241
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (sta)
  324. Sh:335
    Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1989). MA(\sigma-centered): Cohen reals, strong measure zero sets and strongly meager sets. Israel J. Math., 68(1), 1–17. DOI: 10.1007/BF02764965 MR: 1035877
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (leb), (meag)
  325. Sh:336
    Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1991). Q-sets, Sierpiński sets, and rapid filters. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 111(3), 821–832. DOI: 10.2307/2048420 MR: 1045594
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  326. Sh:337
    Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1993). \boldsymbol{\Delta}^1_3-sets of reals. J. Symbolic Logic, 58(1), 72–80. DOI: 10.2307/2275325 MR: 1217177
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, S: dst, (set)
  327. Sh:338
    Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1991). Forcing minimal degree of constructibility. J. Symbolic Logic, 56(3), 769–782. DOI: 10.2307/2275046 MR: 1129141
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, S: dst, (set)
  328. Sh:339
    Judah, H. I., Shelah, S., & Woodin, W. H. (1990). The Borel conjecture. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 50(3), 255–269. NB: A correction of the third section has appeared in 8.3.B of [Bartoszyński, Judah: Set theory. ISBN 1-56881-044-X] DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(90)90058-A MR: 1086456
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: str, (set)
  329. Sh:340
    Shelah, S., & Stanley, L. J. (1995). A combinatorial forcing for coding the universe by a real when there are no sharps. J. Symbolic Logic, 60(1), 1–35. arXiv: math/9311204 DOI: 10.2307/2275507 MR: 1324499
    type: article
    abstract: Assuming $0^\sharp$ does not exist, we present a combinatorial approach to Jensen's method of coding by a real. The forcing uses combinatorial consequences of fine structure (including the Covering Lemma, in various guises), but makes no direct appeal to fine structure itself.
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  330. Sh:341
    Juhász, I., & Shelah, S. (1989). \pi (X)=\delta(X) for compact X. Topology Appl., 32(3), 289–294. NB: Proof in local case is a mistake DOI: 10.1016/0166-8641(89)90035-7 MR: 1007107
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (gt)
  331. Sh:342
    Hrushovski, E., & Shelah, S. (1989). A dichotomy theorem for regular types. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 45(2), 157–169. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(89)90059-6 MR: 1044122
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (sta)
  332. Sh:343
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1989). Time polynomial in input or output. J. Symbolic Logic, 54(3), 1083–1088. DOI: 10.2307/2274767 MR: 1011194
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: fin
  333. Sh:344
    Gitik, M., & Shelah, S. (1989). On certain indestructibility of strong cardinals and a question of Hajnal. Arch. Math. Logic, 28(1), 35–42. DOI: 10.1007/BF01624081 MR: 987765
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (large)
  334. Sh:345
    Shelah, S. (1990). Products of regular cardinals and cardinal invariants of products of Boolean algebras. Israel J. Math., 70(2), 129–187. DOI: 10.1007/BF02807866 MR: 1070264
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: pcf, (ba)
  335. Sh:346
    Komjáth, P., & Shelah, S. (1996). On Taylor’s problem. Acta Math. Hungar., 70(3), 217–225. arXiv: math/9402213 DOI: 10.1007/BF02188208 MR: 1374388
    type: article
    abstract: We describe some (countably many) classes $K^{n,e}$ of finite graphs and prove that if $\lambda^{\aleph_0}=\lambda$ then every $\lambda^+$-chromatic graph of cardinal $\lambda^+$ contains, for some $n$, $e$, all members of $K^{n,e}$ as subgraphs. On the other hand, it is consistent for every regular infinite cardinal $\kappa$ that there is a $\kappa^+$-chromatic graph on $\kappa^+$ that contains finite subgraphs only from $K^{n,e}$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (graph)
  336. Sh:347
    Shelah, S. (1990). Incompactness for chromatic numbers of graphs. In A tribute to Paul Erdős, Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, pp. 361–371. MR: 1117029
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  337. Sh:348
    Bartoszyński, T., Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1989). The cofinality of cardinal invariants related to measure and category. J. Symbolic Logic, 54(3), 719–726. DOI: 10.2307/2274736 MR: 1011163
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (leb), (inv), (meag)
  338. Sh:349
    Shelah, S. (1989). A consistent counterexample in the theory of collectionwise Hausdorff spaces. Israel J. Math., 65(2), 219–224. DOI: 10.1007/BF02764862 MR: 998672
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (gt)
  339. Sh:350
    Dror Farjoun, E., Orr, K. E., & Shelah, S. (1989). Bousfield localization as an algebraic closure of groups. Israel J. Math., 66(1-3), 143–153. DOI: 10.1007/BF02765889 MR: 1017158
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: top, (grp)
  340. Sh:351
    Shelah, S. (1991). Reflecting stationary sets and successors of singular cardinals. Arch. Math. Logic, 31(1), 25–53. DOI: 10.1007/BF01370693 MR: 1126352
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (ref)
  341. Sh:352
    Eklof, P. C., Fuchs, L., & Shelah, S. (1990). Baer modules over domains. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 322(2), 547–560. DOI: 10.2307/2001714 MR: 974514
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab)
  342. Sh:353
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (1994). Homogeneous almost disjoint families. Algebra Universalis, 31(2), 196–203. DOI: 10.1007/BF01236517 MR: 1259349
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  343. Sh:354
    Perles, M. A., & Shelah, S. (1990). A closed (n+1)-convex set in \mathbf R^2 is a union of n^6 convex sets. Israel J. Math., 70(3), 305–312. DOI: 10.1007/BF02801466 MR: 1074494
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: fin, (fc)
  344. Sh:356
    Milner, E. C., & Shelah, S. (1990). Graphs with no unfriendly partitions. In A tribute to Paul Erdős, Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, pp. 373–384. DOI: 10.1017/cbo9780511983917.031 MR: 1117030
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (graph)
  345. Sh:357
    Gitik, M., & Shelah, S. (1989). Forcings with ideals and simple forcing notions. Israel J. Math., 68(2), 129–160. DOI: 10.1007/BF02772658 MR: 1035887
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: str, (set), (leb), (meag)
  346. Sh:358
    Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1990). Around random algebra. Arch. Math. Logic, 30(3), 129–138. DOI: 10.1007/BF01621466 MR: 1080233
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (leb)
  347. Sh:359
    Bonnet, R., & Shelah, S. (1993). On HCO spaces. An uncountable compact T_2 space, different from \aleph_1+1, which is homeomorphic to each of its uncountable closed subspaces. Israel J. Math., 84(3), 289–332. DOI: 10.1007/BF02760945 MR: 1244672
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (set), (ba), (diam)
  348. Sh:360
    Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (1991). The primal framework. II. Smoothness. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 55(1), 1–34. arXiv: math/9201246 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(91)90095-4 MR: 1134914
    See [Sh:360a]

    type: article
    abstract: This is the second in a series of articles developing abstract classification theory for classes that have a notion of prime models over independent pairs and over chains. It deals with the problem of smoothness and establishing the existence and uniqueness of a `monster model'. We work here with a predicate for a canonically prime model.
    keywords: M: nec, (mod)
  349. Sh:361
    Shelah, S., & Thomas, R., Simon. (1989). Homogeneity of infinite permutation groups. Arch. Math. Logic, 28(2), 143–147. DOI: 10.1007/BF01633987 MR: 996316
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico
  350. Sh:362
    Kolman, O., & Shelah, S. (1996). Categoricity of theories in L_{\kappa\omega}, when \kappa is a measurable cardinal. I. Fund. Math., 151(3), 209–240. arXiv: math/9602216 MR: 1424575
    type: article
    abstract: We assume a theory $T$ in the logic $L_{\kappa \omega}$ is categorical in a cardinal $\lambda\geq \kappa$, and $\kappa$ is a measurable cardinal. Here we prove that the class of model of $T$ of cardinality $< \lambda$ (but $\geq |T|+\kappa$) has the amalgamation property; this is a step toward understanding the character of such classes of models.
    keywords: M: nec, (mod), (nni), (cat)
  351. Sh:364
    Juhász, I., & Shelah, S. (1992). On partitioning the triples of a topological space. Topology Appl., 44(1-3), 203–208. DOI: 10.1016/0166-8641(92)90095-H MR: 1173259
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, O: top, (pc), (gt)
  352. Sh:366
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1995). Almost free algebras. Israel J. Math., 89(1-3), 237–259. arXiv: math/9408213 DOI: 10.1007/BF02808203 MR: 1324464
    type: article
    abstract: The essentially non-free spectrum is the class of uncountable cardinals $\kappa$ in which there is an essentially non-free algebra of cardinality $\kappa$ which is almost free. In L, the essentially non-free spectrum of a variety is entirely determined by whether or not the construction principle holds. In ZFC may be more complicated. For some varieties, such as groups, abelian groups or any variety of modules over a non-left perfect ring, the essentially non-free spectrum contains not only $\aleph_1$ but $\aleph_n$ for all $n>0$. The reason for this being true in ZFC (rather than under some special set theoretic hypotheses) is that these varieties satisfy stronger versions of the construction principle. We conjecture that the hierarchy of construction principles is strict, i.e., that for each $n>0$ there is a variety which satisfies the $n$-construction principle but not the $n+1$-construction principle. In this paper we will show that the $1$-construction principle does not imply the $2$-construction principle. We prove that, assuming the consistency of some large cardinal hypothesis, it is consistent that a variety has an essentially non-free almost free algebra of cardinality $\aleph_n$ if and only if it satisfies the $n$-construction principle.
    keywords: O: alg, (stal), (af)
  353. Sh:367
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1989). The consistency strength of “every stationary set reflects”. Israel J. Math., 67(3), 353–366. DOI: 10.1007/BF02764953 MR: 1029909
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (stal), (ref), (af), (pure(large))
  354. Sh:368
    Bartoszyński, T., Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1993). The Cichoń diagram. J. Symbolic Logic, 58(2), 401–423. arXiv: math/9905122 DOI: 10.2307/2275212 MR: 1233917
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  355. Sh:369
    Goldstern, M., Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1991). A regular topological space having no closed subsets of cardinality \aleph_2. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 111(4), 1151–1159. DOI: 10.2307/2048582 MR: 1052572
    type: article
    abstract: We show in ZFC that there is a regular (even zerodimensional) topological space of size $> \aleph_2$ in which there are no closed sets of size $\aleph_2$. The proof starts by noticing that if $\beta\omega$ does not work, then we can use a $\diamondsuit$.
    keywords: S: ico, (gt)
  356. Sh:370
    Shelah, S., & Soukup, L. (1994). On the number of nonisomorphic subgraphs. Israel J. Math., 86(1-3), 349–371. arXiv: math/9401210 DOI: 10.1007/BF02773686 MR: 1276143
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\mathcal K$ be the family of graphs on $\omega_1$ without cliques or independent subsets of size $\omega_1$. We prove that: 1) it is consistent with CH that every $G\in{\mathcal K}$ has $2^{\omega_1}$ many pairwise non-isomorphic subgraphs, 2) the following proposition holds in L: $(*)$ there is a $G\in{\mathcal K}$ such that for each partition $(A,B)$ of $\omega_1$ either $G\cong G[A]$ or $G\cong G[B]$, 3) the failure of $(*)$ is consistent with ZFC.
    keywords: S: ico, (nni), (graph)
  357. Sh:372
    Judah, H. I., Miller, A. W., & Shelah, S. (1992). Sacks forcing, Laver forcing, and Martin’s axiom. Arch. Math. Logic, 31(3), 145–161. DOI: 10.1007/BF01269943 MR: 1147737
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  358. Sh:373
    Judah, H. I., Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (1994). Examples for Souslin forcing. Fund. Math., 144(1), 23–42. arXiv: math/9310224 DOI: 10.4064/fm-144-1-23-42 MR: 1271476
    type: article
    abstract: We give a model where there is a ccc Souslin forcing which does not satisfy the Knaster condition. Next, we present a model where there is a $\sigma$-linked not $\sigma$-centered Souslin forcing such that all its small subsets are $\sigma$-centered but Martin Axiom fails for this order. Furthermore, we construct a totally nonhomogeneous Souslin forcing and we build a Souslin forcing which is proper but not ccc that does not contain a perfect set of mutually incompatible conditions. Finally we show that ccc $\Sigma^1_2$-notions of forcing may not be indestructible ccc.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  359. Sh:374
    Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1993). Adding dominating reals with the random algebra. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 119(1), 267–273. DOI: 10.2307/2159852 MR: 1152278
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  360. Sh:375
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1993). Some compact logics—results in ZFC. Ann. Of Math. (2), 137(2), 221–248. arXiv: math/9301204 DOI: 10.2307/2946538 MR: 1207207
    type: article
    abstract: We show that if we enrich first order logic by allowing quantification over isomorphisms between definable ordered fields the resulting logic, $L(Q_{\rm Of})$, is fully compact. In this logic, we can give standard compactness proofs of various results. Next, we attempt to get compactness results for some other logics without recourse to $\diamondsuit$, i.e., all our results are in ZFC. We get the full result for the language where we quantify over automorphisms (isomorphisms) of ordered fields in Theorem 6.4. Unfortunately we are not able to show that the language with quantification over automorphisms of Boolean algebras is compact, but will have to settle for a close relative of that logic. This is theorem 5.1. In section 4 we prove we can construct models in which all relevant automorphism are somewhat definable: 4.1, 4.8 for BA, 4.13 for ordered fields. We also give a new proof of the compactness of another logic -- the one which is obtained when a quantifier $Q_{{\rm Brch}}$ is added to first order logic which says that a level tree (definitions will be given later) has an infinite branch. This logic was previously shown to be compact, but our proof yields a somewhat stronger result and provides a nice illustration of one of our methods.
    keywords: M: non, (mod)
  361. Sh:376
    Shelah, S., & Soukup, L. (1995). Some remarks on a problem of J. D. Monk. Period. Math. Hungar., 30(2), 155–163. DOI: 10.1007/BF01876630 MR: 1326777
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (ba)
  362. Sh:377
    Shelah, S., Tuuri, H., & Väänänen, J. A. (1993). On the number of automorphisms of uncountable models. J. Symbolic Logic, 58(4), 1402–1418. arXiv: math/9301205 DOI: 10.2307/2275150 MR: 1253929
    type: article
    abstract: Let $s({\mathcal A})$ denote the number of automorphisms of a model ${\mathcal A}$ of power $\omega_1$. We derive a necessary and sufficient condition in terms of trees for the existence of an ${\mathcal A}$ with $\omega_1 < s({\mathcal A}) < 2^{\omega_1}$. We study the sufficiency of some conditions for $s({\mathcal A})=2^{\omega_1}$. These conditions are analogous to conditions studied by D.Kueker in connection with countable models.
    keywords: M: non, O: alg, (mod)
  363. Sh:378
    Jech, T. J., & Shelah, S. (1989). A note on canonical functions. Israel J. Math., 68(3), 376–380. arXiv: math/9201239 DOI: 10.1007/BF02764992 MR: 1039481
    type: article
    abstract: We construct a generic extension in which the $\aleph_2$ nd canonical function on $\aleph_1$ exists.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (normal), (large)
  364. Sh:379
    Eklof, P. C., & Shelah, S. (1991). On Whitehead modules. J. Algebra, 142(2), 492–510. DOI: 10.1016/0021-8693(91)90321-X MR: 1127077
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  365. Sh:381
    Shelah, S. (1991). Kaplansky test problem for R-modules. Israel J. Math., 74(1), 91–127. DOI: 10.1007/BF02777818 MR: 1135231
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (ab)
  366. Sh:382
    Shelah, S., & Spencer, J. H. (1994). Can you feel the double jump? Random Structures Algorithms, 5(1), 191–204. arXiv: math/9401211 DOI: 10.1002/rsa.3240050118 MR: 1248186
    type: article
    abstract: Paul Erdos and Alfred Renyi considered the evolution of the random graph $G(n,p)$ as $p$ ``evolved'' from $0$ to $1$. At $p=1/n$ a sudden and dramatic change takes place in $G$. When $p=c/n$ with $c<1$ the random $G$ consists of small components, the largest of size $\Theta(\log n)$. But by $p=c/n$ with $c>1$ many of the components have ``congealed'' into a ``giant component'' of size $\Theta (n)$. Erdos and Renyi called this the {\em double jump}, the terms phase transition (from the analogy to percolation) and Big Bang have also been proferred. Now imagine an observer who can only see $G$ through a logical fog. He may refer to graph theoretic properties $A$ within a limited logical language. Will he be able to detect the double jump? The answer depends on the strength of the language. Our rough answer to this rough question is: the double jump is not detectible in the First Order Theory of Graphs but it is detectible in the Second Order Monadic Theory of Graphs.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt), (graph), (mon)
  367. Sh:383
    Jech, T. J., & Shelah, S. (1993). Full reflection of stationary sets at regular cardinals. Amer. J. Math., 115(2), 435–453. arXiv: math/9204218 DOI: 10.2307/2374864 MR: 1216437
    type: article
    abstract: A stationary subset $S$ of a regular uncountable cardinal $\kappa$ reflects fully at regular cardinals if for every stationary set $T\subseteq\kappa$ of higher order consisting of regular cardinals there exists an $\alpha\in T$ such that $S\cap\alpha $ is a stationary subset of $\alpha$. We prove that the Axiom of Full Reflection which states that every stationary set reflects fully at regular cardinals, together with the existence of $n$-Mahlo cardinals is equiconsistent with the existence of $\Pi^1_n$-indescribable cardinals. We also state the appropriate generalization for greatly Mahlo cardinals.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter)
  368. Sh:385
    Jech, T. J., & Shelah, S. (1991). On a conjecture of Tarski on products of cardinals. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 112(4), 1117–1124. arXiv: math/9201247 DOI: 10.2307/2048662 MR: 1070525
    type: article
    abstract: We look at an old conjecture of A. Tarski on cardinal arithmetic and show that if a counterexample exists, then there exists one of length $\omega_1 + \omega$.
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  369. Sh:387
    Jech, T. J., & Shelah, S. (1990). Full reflection of stationary sets below \aleph_\omega. J. Symbolic Logic, 55(2), 822–830. arXiv: math/9201242 DOI: 10.2307/2274667 MR: 1056391
    type: article
    abstract: It is consistent that for every $n \ge 2$, every stationary subset of $\omega_n$ consisting of ordinals of cofinality $\omega_k$ where $k = 0$ or $k \le n -3$ reflects fully in the set of ordinals of cofinality $\omega_{n-1}$. We also show that this result is best possible.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (large), (ref)
  370. Sh:388
    Goldstern, M., & Shelah, S. (1990). Ramsey ultrafilters and the reaping number—Con(\mathfrak r<\mathfrak u). Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 49(2), 121–142. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(90)90063-8 MR: 1077075
    type: article
    abstract: We show that the reaping number $r$ is consistenly smaller than the smallest base of an ultrafilter. We use a forcing notion $P_U$ that destroys a selected ultrafilter $U$ and all ultrafilters below it, but preserves all Ramsey ultrafilters that are not below $U$ in the Rudin-Keisler order.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (inv)
  371. Sh:389
    Shelah, S., & Soukup, L. (1993). The existence of large \omega_1-homogeneous but not \omega-homogeneous permutation groups is consistent with ZFC+GCH. J. London Math. Soc. (2), 48(2), 193–203. DOI: 10.1112/jlms/s2-48.2.193 MR: 1231709
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  372. Sh:390
    Kanamori, A., & Shelah, S. (1995). Complete quotient Boolean algebras. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 347(6), 1963–1979. arXiv: math/9401212 DOI: 10.2307/2154916 MR: 1282888
    type: article
    abstract: For $I$ a proper, countably complete ideal on ${\mathcal P}(X)$ for some set $X$, can the quotient Boolean algebra ${\mathcal P}(X)/I$ be complete? This question was raised by Sikorski in 1949. By a simple projection argument as for measurable cardinals, it can be assumed that $X$ is an uncountable cardinal $\kappa$, and that $I$ is a $\kappa$-complete ideal on ${\mathcal P}(\kappa )$ containing all singletons. In this paper we provide consequences from and consistency results about completeness.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (ba)
  373. Sh:391
    Hodges, W., Hodkinson, I. M., Lascar, D., & Shelah, S. (1993). The small index property for \omega-stable \omega-categorical structures and for the random graph. J. London Math. Soc. (2), 48(2), 204–218. DOI: 10.1112/jlms/s2-48.2.204 MR: 1231710
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, O: alg, (stal), (auto), (sta)
  374. Sh:392
    Jech, T. J., & Shelah, S. (1991). A partition theorem for pairs of finite sets. J. Amer. Math. Soc., 4(4), 647–656. arXiv: math/9201248 DOI: 10.2307/2939283 MR: 1122043
    type: article
    abstract: Every partition of $[[\omega_1]^{<\omega}]^2$ into finitely many pieces has a cofinal homogeneous set. Furthermore, it is consistent that every directed partially ordered set satisfies the partition property if and only if it has finite character.
    keywords: S: ico
  375. Sh:393
    Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (1995). Abstract classes with few models have “homogeneous-universal” models. J. Symbolic Logic, 60(1), 246–265. arXiv: math/9502231 DOI: 10.2307/2275520 MR: 1324512
    type: article
    abstract: This paper is concerned with a class {\bf K} of models and an abstract notion of submodel $\leq$. Experience in first order model theory has shown the desirability of finding a `monster model' to serve as a universal domain for {\bf K}. In the original constructions of Jonsson and Fraisse, {\bf K} was a universal class and ordinary substructure played the role of $\leq$. Working with a cardinal $\lambda$ satisfying $\lambda^{<\lambda}=\lambda$ guarantees appropriate downward Lowenheim-Skolem theorems; the existence and uniqueness of a homogeneous-universal model appears to depend centrally on the amalgamation property. We make this apparent dependence more precise in this paper. The major innovation of this paper is the introduction of weaker notion to replace the natural notion of $({\bf K},\leq)$-homogeneous-universal model. Modulo a weak extension of ZFC (provable if V=L), we show that a class {\bf K} obeying certain minimal restrictions satisfies a fundamental dichotomy: For arbitrarily large $\lambda$, either {\bf K} has the maximal number of models in power $\lambda$ or {\bf K} has a unique chain homogenous-universal model of power $\lambda$. We show that in a class with amalgamation this dichotomy holds for the notion of {\bf K}-homogeneous-universal model in the more normal sense.
    keywords: M: nec, (mod)
  376. Sh:394
    Shelah, S. (1999). Categoricity for abstract classes with amalgamation. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 98(1-3), 261–294. arXiv: math/9809197 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(98)00016-5 MR: 1696853
    type: article
    abstract: Let ${\mathfrak K}$ be an abstract elementary class with amalgamation, and Lowenheim Skolem number LS$({\mathfrak K})$. We prove that for a suitable Hanf number $\chi_0$ if $\chi_0 < \lambda_0\le \lambda_1$, and ${\mathfrak K}$ is categorical in $\lambda^+_1$ then it is categorical in $\lambda_0$.
    keywords: M: nec, (mod), (nni), (cat), (aec)
  377. Sh:396
    Frankiewicz, R., Shelah, S., & Zbierski, P. (1993). On closed P-sets with ccc in the space \omega^*. J. Symbolic Logic, 58(4), 1171–1176. arXiv: math/9303207 DOI: 10.2307/2275135 MR: 1253914
    type: article
    abstract: It is proved that -- consistently -- there can be no ccc closed $P$-sets in the remainder space $\omega^*$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  378. Sh:397
    Shelah, S. (1992). Factor = quotient, uncountable Boolean algebras, number of endomorphism and width. Math. Japon., 37(2), 385–400. arXiv: math/9201250 MR: 1159041
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that assuming suitable cardinal arithmetic, if $B$ is a Boolean algebra every homomorphic image of which is isomorphic to a factor, then $B$ has locally small density. We also prove that for an (infinite) Boolean algebra $B$, the number of subalgebras is not smaller than the number of endomorphisms, and other related inequalities. Lastly we deal with the obtainment of the supremum of the cardinalities of sets of pairwise incomparable elements of a Boolean algebra.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (ba), (inv(ba))
  379. Sh:398
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1993). The canary tree. Canad. Math. Bull., 36(2), 209–215. arXiv: math/9308210 DOI: 10.4153/CMB-1993-030-6 MR: 1222536
    type: article
    abstract: A {\em canary tree} is a tree of cardinality the continuum which has no uncountable branch, but gains a branch whenever a stationary set is destroyed (without adding reals). Canary trees are important in infinitary model theory. The existence of a canary tree is independent of ZFC $+$ GCH.
    keywords: S: for, (iter), (set-mod), (cont)
  380. Sh:399
    Goldstern, M., Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1991). Saturated families. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 111(4), 1095–1104. DOI: 10.2307/2048577 MR: 1052573
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  381. Sh:400a
    Shelah, S. (1992). Cardinal arithmetic for skeptics. Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. (N.S.), 26(2), 197–210. arXiv: math/9201251 DOI: 10.1090/S0273-0979-1992-00261-6 MR: 1112424
    type: article
    abstract: We present a survey of some results of the pcf-theory and their applications to cardinal arithmetic. We review basics notions (in \S1), briefly look at history in \S2 (and some personal history in \S3). We present main results on pcf in \S5 and describe applications to cardinal arithmetic in \S6. The limitations on independence proofs are discussed in \S7, and in \S8 we discuss the status of two axioms that arise in the new setting. Applications to other areas are found in \S9.
    keywords: S: pcf, O: odo
  382. Sh:401
    Shelah, S. (2004). Characterizing an \aleph_\epsilon-saturated model of superstable NDOP theories by its \mathbb L_{\infty,\aleph_\epsilon}-theory. Israel J. Math., 140, 61–111. arXiv: math/9609215 DOI: 10.1007/BF02786627 MR: 2054839
    type: article
    abstract: After the main gap theorem was proved (see [Sh:c]), in discussion, Harrington expressed a desire for a finer structure - of finitary character (when we have a structure theorem at all). I point out that the logic $L_{\infty,\aleph_0}(d.q.)$ (d.q. stands for dimension quantifier) does not suffice: e.g., for $T=Th(\lambda\times {}^\omega 2,E_n)_{n<\omega}$ where $(\alpha,\eta)E_n(\beta,\nu) =: \eta|n=\nu|n$ and for $S\subseteq {}^\omega 2$ we define $M_S = M|\{(\alpha,\eta):[\eta\in S\Rightarrow\alpha<\omega_1]$ and $[\eta\in {}^\omega 2 \backslash S\Rightarrow\alpha<\omega]\}$. Hence, it seems to me we should try $L_{\infty,\aleph_\epsilon}(d.q.)$ (essentially, in ${\mathfrak C}$ we can quantify over sets which are included in the algebraic closure of finite sets), and Harrington accepts this interpretation. Here the conjecture is proved for $\aleph_\epsilon$-saturated models. I.e., the main theorem is $M\equiv_{{\mathcal L}_{\infty,\aleph_\epsilon}(d.q.)}N \Leftrightarrow M \cong N$ for $\aleph_\epsilon$-saturated models of a superstable countable (first order) theory $T$ without dop.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  383. Sh:402
    Shelah, S. (1999). Borel Whitehead groups. Math. Japon., 50(1), 121–130. arXiv: math/9809198 MR: 1710476
    type: article
    abstract: We investigate the Whiteheadness of Borel abelian groups ($\aleph_1$-free, wlog, as otherwise this is trivial). We show that CH (and even WCH) implies any such abelian group is free, and always $\aleph_2$-free.
    keywords: S: dst, O: alg, (stal), (wh)
  384. Sh:403
    Abraham, U., & Shelah, S. (1993). A \Delta^2_2 well-order of the reals and incompactness of L(Q^\mathrm{MM}). Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 59(1), 1–32. arXiv: math/9812115 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(93)90228-6 MR: 1197203
    type: article
    abstract: A forcing poset of size $2^{2^{\aleph_1}}$ which adds no new reals is described and shown to provide a $\Delta^2_2$ definable well-order of the reals (in fact, any given relation of the reals may be so encoded in some generic extension). The encoding of this well-order is obtained by playing with products of Aronszajn trees: Some products are special while other are Suslin trees. The paper also deals with the Magidor-Malitz logic: it is consistent that this logic is highly non compact.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, S: dst, (set)
  385. Sh:404
    Givant, S. R., & Shelah, S. (1994). Universal theories categorical in power and \kappa-generated models. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 69(1), 27–51. arXiv: math/9401213 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(94)90018-3 MR: 1301605
    type: article
    abstract: We investigate a notion called {\it uniqueness in power $\kappa$} that is akin to categoricity in power $\kappa$, but is based on the cardinality of the generating sets of models instead of on the cardinality of their universes. The notion is quite useful for formulating categoricity-like questions regarding powers below the cardinality of a theory. We prove, for (uncountable) universal theories $T$, that if $T$ is $\kappa$-unique for one uncountable $\kappa$, then it is $\kappa$-unique for every uncountable $\kappa$; in particular, it is categorical in powers greater than the cardinality of $T$.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (cat), (ua)
  386. Sh:405
    Shelah, S. (1994). Vive la différence. II. The Ax-Kochen isomorphism theorem. Israel J. Math., 85(1-3), 351–390. arXiv: math/9304207 DOI: 10.1007/BF02758648 MR: 1264351
    type: article
    abstract: We show in \S1 that the Ax-Kochen isomorphism theorem requires the continuum hypothesis. Most of the applications of this theorem are insensitive to set theoretic considerations. (A probable exception is the work of Moloney.) In \S2 we give an unrelated result on cuts in models of Peano arithmetic which answers a question on the ideal structure of countable ultraproducts of ${\mathbb Z}$. In \S1 we also answer a question of Keisler and Schmerl regarding Scott complete ultrapowers of ${\mathbb R}$.
    keywords: S: for, (set-mod), (up)
  387. Sh:406
    Fremlin, D. H., & Shelah, S. (1993). Pointwise compact and stable sets of measurable functions. J. Symbolic Logic, 58(2), 435–455. arXiv: math/9209218 DOI: 10.2307/2275214 MR: 1233919
    See [Sh:406a]

    type: article
    abstract: In a series of papers, M.Talagrand, the second author and others investigated at length the properties and structure of pointwise compact sets of measurable functions. A number of problems, interesting in themselves and important for the theory of Pettis integration, were solved subject to various special axioms. It was left unclear just how far the special axioms were necessary. In particular, several results depended on the fact that it is consistent to suppose that every countable relatively pointwise compact set of Lebesgue measurable functions is `stable' in Talagrand's sense; the point being that stable sets are known to have a variety of properties not shared by all pointwise compact sets. In the present paper we present a model of set theory in which there is a countable relatively pointwise compact set of Lebesgue measurable functions which is not stable, and discuss the significance of this model in relation to the original questions. A feature of our model which may be of independent interest is the following: in it, there is a closed negligible set $Q\subseteq [0,1]^2$ such that whenever $D\subseteq [0,1]$ has outer measure 1 then the set $Q^{-1}[D]=\{x:(\exists y\in D)((x,y)\in Q)\}$ has inner measure 1.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (leb), (creatures)
  388. Sh:407
    Shelah, S. (1992). CON(\mathfrak u>\mathfrak i). Arch. Math. Logic, 31(6), 433–443. DOI: 10.1007/BF01277485 MR: 1175937
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (inv)
  389. Sh:408
    Kojman, M., Perles, M. A., & Shelah, S. (1990). Sets in a Euclidean space which are not a countable union of convex subsets. Israel J. Math., 70(3), 313–342. DOI: 10.1007/BF02801467 MR: 1074495
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: str, O: top
  390. Sh:409
    Kojman, M., & Shelah, S. (1992). Nonexistence of universal orders in many cardinals. J. Symbolic Logic, 57(3), 875–891. arXiv: math/9209201 DOI: 10.2307/2275437 MR: 1187454
    type: article
    abstract: We give an example of a first order theory $T$ with countable $D(T)$ which cannot have a universal model at $\aleph_1$ without CH; we prove in $ZFC$ a covering theorem from the hypothesis of the existence of a universal model for some theory; and we prove -- again in ZFC -- that for a large class of cardinals there is no universal linear order (e.g. in every $\aleph_1< \lambda< 2^{\aleph_0}$). In fact, what we show is that if there is a universal linear order at a regular $\lambda$ and its existence is not a result of a trivial cardinal arithmetical reason, then $\lambda$ ``resembles'' $\aleph_1$ -- a cardinal for which the consistency of having a universal order is known. As for singular cardinals, we show that for many singular cardinals, if they are not strong limits then they have no universal linear order. As a result of the non existence of a universal linear order, we show the non-existence of universal models for all theories possessing the strict order property (for example, ordered fields and groups, Boolean algebras, p-adic rings and fields, partial orders, models of PA and so on).
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (app(pcf)), (univ)
  391. Sh:410
    Shelah, S. (1993). More on cardinal arithmetic. Arch. Math. Logic, 32(6), 399–428. arXiv: math/0406550 DOI: 10.1007/BF01270465 MR: 1245523
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  392. Sh:411
    Lifsches, S., & Shelah, S. (1992). The monadic theory of (\omega_2,<) may be complicated. Arch. Math. Logic, 31(3), 207–213. DOI: 10.1007/BF01269949 MR: 1147743
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (mod), (mon)
  393. Sh:412
    Gitik, M., & Shelah, S. (1993). More on simple forcing notions and forcings with ideals. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 59(3), 219–238. DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(93)90094-T MR: 1213273
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: str, (set), (leb), (meag)
  394. Sh:413
    Shelah, S. (2003). More Jonsson algebras. Arch. Math. Logic, 42(1), 1–44. arXiv: math/9809199 DOI: 10.1007/s001530100119 MR: 1953112
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that on many inaccessible there is a Jonsson algebra, so e.g. the first regular Jonsson cardinal $\lambda$ is $\lambda\times\omega$-Mahlo. We give further restrictions on successor of singulars which are Jonsson cardinals. E.g. there is a Jonsson algebra of cardinality $\beth^+_\omega$. Lastly, we give further information on guessing of clubs.
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  395. Sh:414
    Komjáth, P., & Shelah, S. (1993). A consistent edge partition theorem for infinite graphs. Acta Math. Hungar., 61(1-2), 115–120. DOI: 10.1007/BF01872104 MR: 1200965
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (pc), (graph)
  396. Sh:415
    Koppelberg, S., & Shelah, S. (1995). Densities of ultraproducts of Boolean algebras. Canad. J. Math., 47(1), 132–145. arXiv: math/9404226 DOI: 10.4153/CJM-1995-007-0 MR: 1319693
    type: article
    abstract: We answer three problems by J. D. Monk on cardinal invariants of Boolean algebras. Two of these are whether taking the algebraic density $\pi(A)$ resp. the topological density $d(A)$ of a Boolean algebra $A$ commutes with formation of ultraproducts; the third one compares the number of endomorphisms and of ideals of a Boolean algebra.
    keywords: S: for, (ba), (up)
  397. Sh:416
    Mekler, A. H., Shelah, S., & Väänänen, J. A. (1993). The Ehrenfeucht-Fraïssé-game of length \omega_1. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 339(2), 567–580. arXiv: math/9305204 DOI: 10.2307/2154287 MR: 1191613
    type: article
    abstract: Let $({\mathcal A})$ and $({\mathcal B})$ be two first order structures of the same vocabulary. We shall consider the Ehrenfeucht-Fra{\"\i}ss\'e-game of length $\omega_1$ of ${\mathcal A}$ and ${\mathcal B}$ which we denote by $G_{\omega_1}({\mathcal A},{\mathcal B})$. This game is like the ordinary Ehrenfeucht-Fra{\"\i}ss\'e-game of $L_{\omega\omega}$ except that there are $\omega_1$ moves. It is clear that $G_{\omega_1}({\mathcal A},{\mathcal B})$ is determined if $\mathcal A$ and ${\mathcal B}$ are of cardinality $\leq\aleph_1$. We prove the following results: Theorem A: If V=L, then there are models $\mathcal A$ and $\mathcal B$ of cardinality $\aleph_2$ such that the game $G_{\omega_1}({\mathcal A},{\mathcal B})$ is non-determined. Theorem B: If it is consistent that there is a measurable cardinal, then it is consistent that $G_{\omega_1}({\mathcal A},{\mathcal B})$ is determined for all $\mathcal A$ and $\mathcal B$ of cardinality $\le\aleph_2$. Theorem C: For any $\kappa\geq\aleph_3$ there are $\mathcal A$ and $\mathcal B$ of cardinality $\kappa$ such that the game $G_{\omega_1}({\mathcal A},{\mathcal B})$ is non-determined.
    keywords: M: odm, (set-mod)
  398. Sh:417
    Mekler, A. H., Shelah, S., & Spinas, O. (1996). The essentially free spectrum of a variety. Israel J. Math., 93, 1–8. arXiv: math/9411234 DOI: 10.1007/BF02761091 MR: 1380631
    type: article
    abstract: We partially prove a conjecture from [MkSh:366] which says that the spectrum of almost free, essentially free, non-free algebras in a variety is either empty or consists of the class of all successor cardinals.
    keywords: O: alg, (stal), (af)
  399. Sh:418
    Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1993). Every coseparable group may be free. Israel J. Math., 81(1-2), 161–178. arXiv: math/9305205 DOI: 10.1007/BF02761303 MR: 1231184
    type: article
    abstract: We show that if $2^{\aleph_0}$ Cohen reals are added to the universe, then for every reduced non-free torsion-free abelian group $A$ of cardinality less than the continuum, there is a prime $p$ so that ${\rm Ext}_p(A, {\mathbb Z}) \neq 0$. In particular if it is consistent that there is a supercompact cardinal, then it is consistent (even with weak CH) that every coseparable group is free. The use of some large cardinal hypothesis is needed.
    keywords: S: for, (ab), (wh)
  400. Sh:419
    Shelah, S., & Stanley, L. J. (2000). Filters, Cohen sets and consistent extensions of the Erdős-Dushnik-Miller theorem. J. Symbolic Logic, 65(1), 259–271. arXiv: math/9709228 DOI: 10.2307/2586535 MR: 1782118
    type: article
    abstract: We present two different types of models where, for certain singular cardinals $\lambda$ of uncountable cofinality, $\lambda\rightarrow(\lambda,\omega+1)^2$, although $\lambda$ is not a strong limit cardinal. We announce, here, and will present in a subsequent paper, that, for example, consistently, $\aleph_{\omega_1}\not\rightarrow (\aleph_{\omega_1},\omega+1)^2$ and consistently, $2^{\aleph_0}\not\rightarrow (2^{\aleph_0},\omega+1)^2$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (pc)
  401. Sh:420
    Shelah, S. (1993). Advances in cardinal arithmetic. In Finite and infinite combinatorics in sets and logic (Banff, AB, 1991), Vol. 411, Kluwer Acad. Publ., Dordrecht, pp. 355–383. arXiv: 0708.1979 MR: 1261217
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  402. Sh:422
    Eklof, P. C., & Shelah, S. (1993). On a conjecture regarding nonstandard uniserial modules. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 340(1), 337–351. arXiv: math/9308211 DOI: 10.2307/2154560 MR: 1159192
    type: article
    abstract: We consider the question of which valuation domains (of cardinality $\aleph _1)$ have non-standard uniserial modules. We show that a criterion conjectured by Osofsky is independent of ZFC + GCH.
    keywords: S: for, (ab), (iter)
  403. Sh:424
    Shelah, S. (1993). On CH + 2^{\aleph_1}\to(\alpha)^2_2 for \alpha<\omega_2. In Logic Colloquium ’90 (Helsinki, 1990), Vol. 2, Springer, Berlin, pp. 281–289. arXiv: math/9308212 MR: 1279847
    type: article
    abstract: We prove the consistency of ``CH + $2^{\aleph_1}$ is arbitrarily large + $2^{\aleph_1}\not\rightarrow(\omega_1\times\omega)^2_2$''. If fact, we can get $2^{\aleph_1}\not\rightarrow[\omega_1\times\omega]^2_{\aleph_0}$. In addition to this theorem, we give generalizations to other cardinals.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (pc)
  404. Sh:425
    Shelah, S., & Stanley, L. J. (1995). The combinatorics of combinatorial coding by a real. J. Symbolic Logic, 60(1), 36–57. arXiv: math/9402214 DOI: 10.2307/2275508 MR: 1324500
    type: article
    abstract: We lay the combinatorial foundations for [ShSt:340] by setting up and proving the essential properties of the coding apparatus for singular cardinals. We also prove another result concerning the coding apparatus for inaccessible cardinals.
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  405. Sh:426
    Eklof, P. C., Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1993). On coherent systems of projections for \aleph_1-separable groups. Comm. Algebra, 21(1), 343–353. arXiv: math/9308213 DOI: 10.1080/00927879208824564 MR: 1194564
    type: article
    abstract: It is proved consistent with either CH or the negation of CH that there is an $\aleph_1$-separable group of cardinality $\aleph_1$ which does not have a coherent system of projections. It had previously been shown that it is consistent with $\neg$CH that every $\aleph_1$-separable group of cardinality $\aleph_1$ does have a coherent system of projections.
    keywords: S: for, (ab), (cont)
  406. Sh:427
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (1994). Somewhere trivial autohomeomorphisms. J. London Math. Soc. (2), 49(3), 569–580. arXiv: math/9308214 DOI: 10.1112/jlms/49.3.569 MR: 1271551
    type: article
    abstract: It is shown to be consistent that there is a non-trivial autohomeomorphism of $\beta{\bf N}$ while all such autohomeomorphisms are trivial on some open set. The model used is one due to Velickovic in which, coincidentally, Martin's Axiom also holds.
    keywords: S: str, (set)
  407. Sh:428
    Hyttinen, T., Shelah, S., & Tuuri, H. (1993). Remarks on strong nonstructure theorems. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 34(2), 157–168. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093634649 MR: 1231281
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: non, (set-mod)
  408. Sh:429
    Shelah, S. (1991). Multi-dimensionality. Israel J. Math., 74(2-3), 281–288. DOI: 10.1007/BF02775792 MR: 1135240
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (sta)
  409. Sh:430
    Shelah, S. (1996). Further cardinal arithmetic. Israel J. Math., 95, 61–114. arXiv: math/9610226 DOI: 10.1007/BF02761035 MR: 1418289
    type: article
    abstract: We continue the investigations in the author's book on cardinal arithmetic, assuming some knowledge of it. We deal with the cofinality of $({\mathcal S}_{\le\aleph_0}(\kappa),\subseteq)$ for $\kappa$ real valued measurable (Section 3), densities of box products (Section 5,3), prove the equality $cov(\lambda,\lambda,\theta^+,2)=pp(\lambda)$ in more cases even when $cf(\lambda)=\aleph_0$ (Section 1), deal with bounds of $pp(\lambda)$ for $\lambda$ limit of inaccessible (Section 4) and give proofs to various claims I was sure I had already written but did not find (Section 6).
    keywords: S: pcf
  410. Sh:431
    Komjáth, P., & Shelah, S. (1994). A note on a set-mapping problem of Hajnal and Máté. Period. Math. Hungar., 28(1), 39–42. DOI: 10.1007/BF01876368 MR: 1310757
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set)
  411. Sh:432
    Shelah, S., & Spencer, J. H. (1994). Random sparse unary predicates. Random Structures Algorithms, 5(3), 375–394. arXiv: math/9401214 DOI: 10.1002/rsa.3240050302 MR: 1277609
    type: article
    abstract: The main result is the following Theorem: Let $p=p(n)$ be such that $p(n)\in[0,1]$ for all $n$ and either $p(n)\ll n^{-1}$ or for some positive integer $k$, $n^{-1/k}\ll p(n)\ll n^{-1/(k+1)}$ or for all $\epsilon>0$, $n^{-\epsilon}\ll p(n)$ and $n^{-\epsilon}\ll 1-p(n)$ or for some positive integer $k$, $n^{-1/k}\ll 1-p(n)\ll n^{-1/(k+1)}$ or $1-p(n)\ll n^{-1}$. Then $p(n)$ satisfies the Zero-One Law for circular unary predicates. Inversely, if $p(n)$ falls into none of the above categories then it does not satisfy the Zero-One Law for circular unary predicates.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  412. Sh:433
    Magidor, M., & Shelah, S. (1998). Length of Boolean algebras and ultraproducts. Math. Japon., 48(2), 301–307. arXiv: math/9805145 MR: 1674385
    type: article
    abstract: We prove the consistency with ZFC of ``the length of an ultraproduct of Boolean algebras is smaller than the ultraproduct of the lengths''. Similarly for some other cardinal invariants of Boolean algebras.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (ba), (large), (up)
  413. Sh:434
    Bartoszyński, T., Goldstern, M., Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1993). All meager filters may be null. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 117(2), 515–521. arXiv: math/9301206 DOI: 10.2307/2159190 MR: 1111433
    type: article
    abstract: We show that it is consistent with ZFC that all filters which have the Baire property are Lebesgue measurable. We also show that the existence of a Sierpinski set implies that there exists a nonmeasurable filter which has the Baire property.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (leb), (meag)
  414. Sh:435
    Shelah, S., & Łuczak, T. (1995). Convergence in homogeneous random graphs. Random Structures Algorithms, 6(4), 371–391. arXiv: math/9501221 DOI: 10.1002/rsa.3240060402 MR: 1368840
    type: article
    abstract: For a sequence $\bar{p}=(p(1),p(2),\dots)$ let $G(n,\bar{p})$ denote the random graph with vertex set $\{1,2,\dots,n\}$ in which two vertices $i$, $j$ are adjacent with probability $p(|i-j|)$, independently for each pair. We study how the convergence of probabilities of first order properties of $G(n,\bar{p})$, can be affected by the behaviour of $\bar{p}$ and the strength of the language we use.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt), (graph)
  415. Sh:436
    Bartoszyński, T., & Shelah, S. (1992). Intersection of <2^{\aleph_0} ultrafilters may have measure zero. Arch. Math. Logic, 31(4), 221–226. arXiv: math/9904068 DOI: 10.1007/BF01794979 MR: 1155033
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (leb), (inv)
  416. Sh:437
    Burke, M. R., & Shelah, S. (1992). Linear liftings for noncomplete probability spaces. Israel J. Math., 79(2-3), 289–296. arXiv: math/9201252 DOI: 10.1007/BF02808221 MR: 1248919
    type: article
    abstract: We show that it is consistent with ZFC that $L^\infty(Y,{\mathcal B},\nu)$ has no linear lifting for many non-complete probability spaces $(Y,{\mathcal B},\nu)$, in particular for $Y=[0,1]^A$, ${\mathcal B}=$ Borel subsets of $Y$, $\nu=$ usual Radon measure on ${\mathcal B}$.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (leb)
  417. Sh:438
    Goldstern, M., Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1993). Strong measure zero sets without Cohen reals. J. Symbolic Logic, 58(4), 1323–1341. arXiv: math/9306214 DOI: 10.2307/2275146 MR: 1253925
    type: article
    abstract: If ZFC is consistent, then each of the following are consistent with ZFC + $2^{{\aleph_0}}=\aleph_2$: 1.) $X subseteq R$ is of strong measure zero iff $|X| \leq \aleph_1$ + there is a generalized Sierpinski set. 2.) The union of $\aleph_1$ many strong measure zero sets is a strong measure zero set + there is a strong measure zero set of size $\aleph_2$.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (leb)
  418. Sh:439
    Bartoszyński, T., & Shelah, S. (1992). Closed measure zero sets. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 58(2), 93–110. arXiv: math/9905123 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(92)90001-G MR: 1186905
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: str, (set), (leb)
  419. Sh:440
    Comfort, W. W., Kato, A., & Shelah, S. (1993). Topological partition relations of the form \omega^\ast\to(Y)^1_2. In Papers on general topology and applications (Madison, WI, 1991), Vol. 704, New York Acad. Sci., New York, pp. 70–79. arXiv: math/9305206 DOI: 10.1111/j.1749-6632.1993.tb52510.x MR: 1277844
    type: article
    abstract: Theorem: The topological partition relation $\omega^{*}\rightarrow(Y)^{1}_{2}$ (a) fails for every space $Y$ with $|Y|\geq 2^{\rm \bf c}$; (b) holds for $Y$ discrete if and only if $|Y|\leq$ {\bf c}; (c) holds for certain non-discrete $P$-spaces $Y$; (d) fails for $Y=\omega\cup\{p\}$ with $p\in\omega^{*}$; (e) fails for $Y$ infinite and countably compact.
    keywords: S: ico, O: top, (pc), (gt)
  420. Sh:441
    Eklof, P. C., Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1992). Uniformization and the diversity of Whitehead groups. Israel J. Math., 80(3), 301–321. arXiv: math/9204219 DOI: 10.1007/BF02808073 MR: 1202574
    type: article
    abstract: The connections between Whitehead groups and uniformization properties were investigated by the third author in [Sh:98]. In particular it was essentially shown there that there is a non-free Whitehead (respectively, $\aleph_1$-coseparable) group of cardinality $\aleph_1$ if and only if there is a ladder system on a stationary subset of $\omega_1$ which satisfies $2$-uniformization (respectively, $omega$-uniformization). These techniques allowed also the proof of various independence and consistency results about Whitehead groups, for example that it is consistent that there is a non-free Whitehead group of cardinality $\aleph_1$ but no non-free $\aleph_1$-coseparable group. However, some natural questions remained open, among them the following two: (i) Is it consistent that the class of W-groups of cardinality $\aleph_1$ is exactly the class of strongly $\aleph_1$-free groups of cardinality $\aleph_1$? (ii) If every strongly $\aleph_1$-free group of cardinality $\aleph_1$ is a W-group, are they also all $\aleph_1$-coseparable? In this paper we use the techniques of uniformization to answer the first question in the negative and give a partial affirmative answer to the second question.
    keywords: S: for, O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh), (unif)
  421. Sh:442
    Eklof, P. C., Mekler, A. H., & Shelah, S. (1994). Hereditarily separable groups and monochromatic uniformization. Israel J. Math., 88(1-3), 213–235. arXiv: math/0406552 DOI: 10.1007/BF02937512 MR: 1303496
    type: article
    abstract: We give a combinatorial equivalent to the existence of a non-free hereditarily separable group of cardinality $\aleph_1$. This can be used, together with a known combinatorial equivalent of the existence of a non-free Whitehead group, to prove that it is consistent that every Whitehead group is free but not every hereditarily separable group is free. We also show that the fact that ${\mathbb Z}$ is a p.i.d. with infinitely many primes is essential for this result.
    keywords: S: for, O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh), (unif)
  422. Sh:443
    Diestel, R., Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (1994). Dominating functions and graphs. J. London Math. Soc. (2), 49(1), 16–24. arXiv: math/9308215 DOI: 10.1090/conm/147/01192 MR: 1253008
    type: article
    abstract: A graph is called dominating if its vertices can be labelled with integers in such a way that for every function $f:\omega\to\omega$ the graph contains a ray whose sequence of labels eventually exceeds $f$. We obtain a characterization of these graphs by producing a small family of dominating graphs with the property that every dominating graph must contain some member of the family.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (graph)
  423. Sh:444
    Huck, A., Niedermeyer, F., & Shelah, S. (1994). Large \kappa-preserving sets in infinite graphs. J. Graph Theory, 18(4), 413–426. DOI: 10.1002/jgt.3190180411 MR: 1277518
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (graph)
  424. Sh:445
    Shelah, S. (1995). Every null-additive set is meager-additive. Israel J. Math., 89(1-3), 357–376. arXiv: math/9406228 DOI: 10.1007/BF02808209 MR: 1324470
    type: article
    abstract: We show that every null-additive set is meager-additive, where: (1) a set $X\subseteq 2^\omega$ is null-additive if for every Lebesgue null set $A\subseteq 2^\omega$, $X+A$ is null too; (2) we say that $X\subseteq 2^\omega$ is meager-additive if for every $A\subseteq 2^\omega$ which is meager also $X+A$ is meager.
    keywords: S: ico, S: str, (set), (leb), (meag)
  425. Sh:447
    Kojman, M., & Shelah, S. (1992). The universality spectrum of stable unsuperstable theories. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 58(1), 57–72. arXiv: math/9201253 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(92)90034-W MR: 1169786
    type: article
    abstract: It is shown that if $T$ is stable unsuperstable, and $\aleph_1< \lambda=cf(\lambda)< 2^{\aleph_0}$, or $2^{\aleph_0} < \mu^+< \lambda=cf(\lambda)< \mu^{\aleph_0}$ then $T$ has no universal model in cardinality $\lambda$, and if e.g. $\aleph_\omega < 2^{\aleph_0}$ then $T$ has no universal model in $\aleph_\omega$. These results are generalized to $\kappa=cf(\kappa) < \kappa(T)$ in the place of $\aleph_0$. Also: if there is a universal model in $\lambda>|T|$, $T$ stable and $\kappa< \kappa(T)$ then there is a universal tree of height $\kappa+1$ in cardinality $\lambda$.
    keywords: M: cla, M: non, S: ico, (app(pcf)), (univ), (set-mod)
  426. Sh:448
    Goldstern, M., & Shelah, S. (1993). Many simple cardinal invariants. Arch. Math. Logic, 32(3), 203–221. arXiv: math/9205208 DOI: 10.1007/BF01375552 MR: 1201650
    type: article
    abstract: For $g < f$ in $\omega^\omega$ we define $c(f,g)$ be the least number of uniform trees with $g$-splitting needed to cover a uniform tree with $f$-splitting. We show that we can simultaneously force $\aleph_1$ many different values for different functions $(f,g)$. In the language of Blass: There may be $\aleph_1$ many distinct uniform $\bf\Pi^0_1$ characteristics.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (inv)
  427. Sh:449
    Kojman, M., & Shelah, S. (1993). \mu-complete Souslin trees on \mu^+. Arch. Math. Logic, 32(3), 195–201. arXiv: math/9306215 DOI: 10.1007/BF01375551 MR: 1201649
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that $\mu=\mu^{<\mu}$, $2^\mu=\mu^+$ and ``there is a non reflecting stationary subset of $\mu^+$ composed of ordinals of cofinality $< \mu$'' imply that there is a $\mu$-complete Souslin tree on $\mu^+$.
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  428. Sh:450
    Melles, G., & Shelah, S. (1994). A saturated model of an unsuperstable theory of cardinality greater than its theory has the small index property. Proc. London Math. Soc. (3), 69(3), 449–463. arXiv: math/9308216 DOI: 10.1112/plms/s3-69.3.449 MR: 1289859
    type: article
    abstract: A model $M$ of cardinality $\lambda$ is said to have the small index property if for every $G\subseteq Aut(M)$ such that $[Aut(M):G]\leq\lambda$ there is an $A\subseteq M$ with $|A|< \lambda$ such that $Aut_A(M)\subseteq G$. We show that if $M^*$ is a saturated model of an unsuperstable theory of cardinality $> Th(M)$, then $M^*$ has the small index property.
    keywords: S: ico, (mod), (auto)
  429. Sh:451
    Lascar, D., & Shelah, S. (1993). Uncountable saturated structures have the small index property. Bull. London Math. Soc., 25(2), 125–131. DOI: 10.1112/blms/25.2.125 MR: 1204064
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, (mod), (auto)
  430. Sh:452
    Melles, G., & Shelah, S. (1994). \mathrm{Aut}(M) has a large dense free subgroup for saturated M. Bull. London Math. Soc., 26(4), 339–344. arXiv: math/9304201 DOI: 10.1112/blms/26.4.339 MR: 1302066
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that for a stable theory $T,$ if $M$ is a saturated model of $T$ of cardinality $\lambda$ where $\lambda>|T|,$ then $Aut(M)$ has a dense free subgroup on $2^{\lambda}$ generators. This affirms a conjecture of Hodges.
    keywords: M: odm, (mod), (auto)
  431. Sh:453
    Mekler, A. H., Schipperus, R. J., Shelah, S., & Truss, J. K. (1993). The random graph and automorphisms of the rational world. Bull. London Math. Soc., 25(4), 343–346. DOI: 10.1112/blms/25.4.343 MR: 1222726
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, (auto)
  432. Sh:454
    Shelah, S. (1993). Number of open sets for a topology with a countable basis. Israel J. Math., 83(3), 369–374. arXiv: math/9308217 DOI: 10.1007/BF02784064 MR: 1239070
    type: article
    abstract: Let $T$ be the family of open subsets of a topological space (not necessarily Hausdorff or even $T_0$). We prove that if $T$ has a countable base and is not countable, then $T$ has cardinality at least continuum.
    keywords: S: ico, S: pcf, O: top, (inv), (gt)
  433. Sh:454a
    Shelah, S. (1994). Cardinalities of topologies with small base. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 68(1), 95–113. arXiv: math/9403219 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(94)90049-3 MR: 1278551
    type: article
    abstract: Let $T$ be the family of open subsets of a topological space (not necessarily Hausdorff or even $T_0$). We prove that if $T$ has a base of cardinality $\leq \mu$, $\lambda\leq \mu< 2^\lambda$, $\lambda$ strong limit of cofinality $\aleph_0$, then T has cardinality $\leq \mu$ or $\geq 2^\lambda$. This is our main conclusion. First we prove it under some set theoretic assumption, which is clear when $\lambda=\mu$; then we eliminate the assumption by a theorem on pcf from [Sh 460] motivated originally by this. Next we prove that the simplest examples are the basic ones; they occur in every example (for $\lambda=\aleph_0$ this fulfill a promise from [Sh 454]). The main result for the case $\lambda=\aleph_0$ was proved in [Sh 454].
    keywords: S: pcf
  434. Sh:455
    Kojman, M., & Shelah, S. (1995). Universal abelian groups. Israel J. Math., 92(1-3), 113–124. arXiv: math/9409207 DOI: 10.1007/BF02762072 MR: 1357747
    type: article
    abstract: We examine the existence of universal elements in classes of infinite abelian groups. The main method is using group invariants which are defined relative to club guessing sequences. We prove, for example: Theorem: For $n\ge 2$, there is a purely universal separable $p$-group in $\aleph_n$ if, and only if, ${2^{\aleph_0}}\leq \aleph_n$.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (app(pcf)), (univ)
  435. Sh:456
    Shelah, S. (1996). Universal in (<\lambda)-stable abelian group. Math. Japon., 44(1), 1–9. arXiv: math/9509225 MR: 1402794
    type: article
    abstract: A characteristic result is that if $2^{\aleph_0}< \mu< \mu^+< \lambda= cf(\lambda)< \mu^{\aleph_0}$, then among the separable reduced $p$-groups of cardinality $\lambda$ which are $(< \lambda)$-stable there is no universal one.
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (ab), (stal), (app(pcf)), (univ)
  436. Sh:457
    Shelah, S. (1993). The universality spectrum: consistency for more classes. In Combinatorics, Paul Erdős is eighty, Vol. 1, János Bolyai Math. Soc., Budapest, pp. 403–420. arXiv: math/9412229 MR: 1249724
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with consistency results for the existence of universal models in natural classes of models (more exactly--a somewhat weaker version). We apply a result on quite general family to $T_{\rm feq}$ and to the class of triangle-free graphs.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (graph), (univ), (set-mod)
  437. Sh:458
    Abraham, U., & Shelah, S. (1996). Martin’s axiom and \Delta^2_1 well-ordering of the reals. Arch. Math. Logic, 35(5-6), 287–298. arXiv: math/9408214 DOI: 10.1007/s001530050046 MR: 1420259
    type: article
    abstract: Assuming an inaccessible cardinal $\kappa$, there is a generic extension in which $MA + 2^{\aleph_0} = \kappa$ holds and the reals have a $\Delta^2_1$ well-ordering.
    keywords: S: for, S: dst, (set)
  438. Sh:459
    Baumgartner, J. E., Shelah, S., & Thomas, R., Simon. (1993). Maximal subgroups of infinite symmetric groups. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 34(1), 1–11. DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093634559 MR: 1213842
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico
  439. Sh:460
    Shelah, S. (2000). The generalized continuum hypothesis revisited. Israel J. Math., 116, 285–321. arXiv: math/9809200 DOI: 10.1007/BF02773223 MR: 1759410
    type: article
    abstract: We argue that we solved Hilbert's first problem positively (after reformulating it just to avoid the known consistency results) and give some applications. Let $\lambda$ to the revised power of $\kappa$ be the minimal cardinality of a family of subsets of $\lambda$ each of cardinality $\kappa$ such that any other subset of $\lambda$ of cardinality $\kappa$ is included in the union of $<\kappa$ members of the family. The main theorem says that almost always this revised power is equal to $\lambda$. Our main result is The Revised GCH Theorem: Assume we fix an uncountable strong limit cardinal $\mu$ (i.e., $\mu>\aleph_0$, $(\forall\theta<\mu)(2^\theta<\mu)$), e.g. $\mu= \beth_\omega$. Then for every $\lambda\geq\mu$ for some $\kappa<\mu$ we have: (a) $\kappa\leq\theta<\mu\Rightarrow\lambda^{[\theta]}=\lambda$ and (b) there is a family ${\mathcal P}$ of $\lambda$ subsets of $\lambda$ each of cardinality $<\mu$ such that every subset of $\lambda$ of cardinality $\mu$ is equal to the union of $<\kappa$ members of ${\mathcal P}$.
    keywords: S: pcf
  440. Sh:461
    Eklof, P. C., & Shelah, S. (1993). Explicitly nonstandard uniserial modules. J. Pure Appl. Algebra, 86(1), 35–50. arXiv: math/9301207 DOI: 10.1016/0022-4049(93)90151-I MR: 1213152
    type: article
    abstract: A new construction is given of non-standard uniserial modules over certain valuation domains; the construction resembles that of a special Aronszajn tree in set theory. A consequence is the proof of a sufficient condition for the existence of non-standard uniserial modules; this is a theorem of ZFC which complements an earlier independence result.
    keywords: S: ico, (ab)
  441. Sh:462
    Shelah, S. (1997). \sigma-entangled linear orders and narrowness of products of Boolean algebras. Fund. Math., 153(3), 199–275. arXiv: math/9609216 DOI: 10.4064/fm-153-3-199-275 MR: 1467577
    type: article
    abstract: We investigate $\sigma$-entangled linear orders and narrowness of Boolean algebras. We show existence of $\sigma$-entangled linear orders in many cardinals, and we build Boolean algebras with neither large chains nor large pies. We study the behavior of these notions in ultraproducts.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (app(pcf)), (linear order)
  442. Sh:463
    Shelah, S. (1996). On the very weak 0-1 law for random graphs with orders. J. Logic Comput., 6(1), 137–159. arXiv: math/9507221 DOI: 10.1093/logcom/6.1.137 MR: 1376723
    type: article
    abstract: Let us draw a graph R on {0,1,...,n-1} by having an edge {i,j} with probability $p_(|i-j|)$, where $\sum_i p_i$ is finite and let $M_n=(n,<,R)$. For a first order sentence $\psi$ let $a^n_\psi$ be the probability of "$M_n$ satisfies $\psi$". We prove that the limit of $a^n_\psi-a^{n+1}_\psi$ is 0, as $n$ goes to infinity.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt), (graph)
  443. Sh:464
    Baldwin, J. T., Laskowski, M. C., & Shelah, S. (1993). Forcing isomorphism. J. Symbolic Logic, 58(4), 1291–1301. arXiv: math/9301208 DOI: 10.2307/2275144 MR: 1253923
    type: article
    abstract: A forcing extension may create new isomorphisms between two models of a first order theory. Certain model theoretic constraints on the theory and other constraints on the forcing can prevent this pathology. A countable first order theory is classifiable if it is superstable and does not have either the dimensional order property or the omitting types order property. Shelah [Sh:c] showed that if a theory $T$ is classifiable then each model of cardinality $\lambda$ is described by a sentence of $L_{\infty,\lambda}$. In fact this sentence can be chosen in the $L^*_{\lambda}$. ($L^*_{\lambda}$ is the result of enriching the language $L_{\infty,\beth^+}$ by adding for each $\mu<\lambda$ a quantifier saying the dimension of a dependence structure is greater than $\mu$.) The truth of such sentences will be preserved by any forcing that does not collapse cardinals $\leq\lambda$ and that adds no new countable subsets of $\lambda$. Hence, if two models of a classifiable theory of power $\lambda$ are non-isomorphic, they are non-isomorphic after a $\lambda$-complete forcing. Here we show that the hypothesis of the forcing adding no new countable subsets of $\lambda$ cannot be eliminated. In particular, we show that non-isomorphism of models of a classifiable theory need not be preserved by ccc forcings.
    keywords: M: cla, M: non, S: for, (set-mod), (sta)
  444. Sh:465
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (1993). Maximal chains in ^\omega\omega and ultrapowers of the integers. Arch. Math. Logic, 32(5), 305–319. arXiv: math/9204205 DOI: 10.1007/BF01409965 MR: 1223393
    See [Sh:465a]

    type: article
    abstract: Various questions posed by P. Nyikos concerning ultrafilters on $\omega$ and chains in the partial order $(\omega,< ^*)$ are answered. The main tool is the oracle chain condition and variations of it. (Note: Corrections in [Sh:465a])
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  445. Sh:466
    Jin, R., & Shelah, S. (1993). A model in which there are Jech-Kunen trees but there are no Kurepa trees. Israel J. Math., 84(1-2), 1–16. arXiv: math/9308218 DOI: 10.1007/BF02761687 MR: 1244655
    type: article
    abstract: By an $\omega_1$--tree we mean a tree of power $\omega_1$ and height $\omega_1$. We call an $\omega_1$--tree a Jech--Kunen tree if it has $\kappa$--many branches for some $\kappa$ strictly between $\omega_1$ and $2^{\omega_1}$. In this paper we construct the models of CH plus $2^{\omega_1}>\omega_2$, in which there are Jech--Kunen trees and there are no Kurepa trees.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (trees)
  446. Sh:467
    Shelah, S. (2002). Zero-one laws for graphs with edge probabilities decaying with distance. I. Fund. Math., 175(3), 195–239. arXiv: math/9606226 DOI: 10.4064/fm175-3-1 MR: 1969657
    type: article
    abstract: Let $G_n$ be the random graph on $[n]=\{1,\ldots,n\}$ with the possible edge $\{i,j\}$ having probability being $p_{|i-j|}= 1/|i-j|^\alpha$, $\alpha\in (0,1)$ irrational. We prove that the zero one law (for first order logic) holds. The paper is continued in [Sh:517]
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt), (graph)
  447. Sh:468
    Shelah, S., & Spinas, O. (1996). Gross spaces. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 348(10), 4257–4277. arXiv: math/9510215 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-96-01658-3 MR: 1357403
    type: article
    abstract: A Gross space is a vector space $E$ of infinite dimension over some field $F$, which is endowed with a symmetric bilinear form $\Phi:E^2 \rightarrow F$ and has the property that every infinite dimensional subspace $U\subseteq E$ satisfies dim$U^\perp < $ dim$E$. Gross spaces over uncountable fields exist (in certain dimensions). The existence of a Gross space over countable or finite fields (in a fixed dimension not above the continuum) is independent of the axioms of ZFC. Here we continue the investigation of Gross spaces. Among other things we show that if the cardinal invariant {\bf b} equals $\omega _1$ a Gross space in dimension $\omega _1$ exists over every infinite field, and that it is consistent that Gross spaces exist over every infinite field but not over any finite field. We also generalize the notion of a Gross space and construct generalized Gross spaces in ZFC.
    keywords: S: for, (stal), (app(pcf))
  448. Sh:469
    Jin, R., & Shelah, S. (1992). Planting Kurepa trees and killing Jech-Kunen trees in a model by using one inaccessible cardinal. Fund. Math., 141(3), 287–296. arXiv: math/9211214 DOI: 10.4064/fm-141-3-287-296 MR: 1199241
    type: article
    abstract: By an $\omega_1$--tree we mean a tree of power $\omega_1$ and height $\omega_1$. Under CH and $2^{\omega_1}>\omega_2$ we call an $\omega_1$--tree a Jech--Kunen tree if it has $\kappa$ many branches for some $\kappa$ strictly between $\omega_1$ and $2^{\omega_1}$. In this paper we prove that, assuming the existence of one inaccessible cardinal, (1) it is consistent with CH plus $2^{\omega_1}>\omega_2$ that there exist Kurepa trees and there are no Jech--Kunen trees, (2) it is consistent with CH plus $2^{\omega_1}=\omega_4$ that only Kurepa trees with $\omega_3$ many branches exist.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (trees)
  449. Sh:470
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (1999). Norms on possibilities. I. Forcing with trees and creatures. Mem. Amer. Math. Soc., 141(671), xii+167. arXiv: math/9807172 DOI: 10.1090/memo/0671 MR: 1613600
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper we present a systematic study of the method of {\em norms on possibilities} of building forcing notions with keeping their properties under full control. This technique allows us to answer several open problems, but on our way to get the solutions we develop various ideas interesting per se. These include a new iterable condition for ``not adding Cohen reals'' (which has a flavour of preserving special properties of $p$-points), new intriguing properties of ultrafilters (weaker than being Ramsey but stronger than $p$--point) and some new applications of variants of the PP--property.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (creatures)
  450. Sh:471
    Lifsches, S., & Shelah, S. (1997). Peano arithmetic may not be interpretable in the monadic theory of linear orders. J. Symbolic Logic, 62(3), 848–872. arXiv: math/9308219 DOI: 10.2307/2275575 MR: 1472126
    type: article
    abstract: Gurevich and Shelah have shown that Peano Arithmetic cannot be interpreted in the monadic second-order theory of short chains (hence, in the monadic second-order theory of the real line). We show here that it is consistent that there is no interpretation even in the monadic second-order theory of all chains.
    keywords: S: for, (mod), (iter), (mon)
  451. Sh:472
    Shelah, S. (2001). Categoricity of theories in L_{\kappa^\ast,\omega}, when \kappa^\ast is a measurable cardinal. II. Fund. Math., 170(1-2), 165–196. arXiv: math/9604241 DOI: 10.4064/fm170-1-10 MR: 1881375
    type: article
    abstract: We continue the work of [KlSh:362] and prove that for $\lambda$successor, a $\lambda$-categorical theory $T$ in $L_{\kappa^*,\omega}$ is $\mu$-categorical for every $\mu$, $\mu\leq\lambda$ which is above the $(2^{LS(T)})^+$-beth cardinal.
    keywords: M: nec
  452. Sh:473
    Shelah, S. (1995). Possibly every real function is continuous on a non-meagre set. Publ. Inst. Math. (Beograd) (N.S.), 57(71), 47–60. arXiv: math/9511220 MR: 1387353
    type: article
    abstract: We prove consistency of the following sentence: ``ZFC + every real function is continuous on a non-meagre set'', answering a question of Fremlin.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (meag)
  453. Sh:474
    Hyttinen, T., & Shelah, S. (1994). Constructing strongly equivalent nonisomorphic models for unsuperstable theories. Part A. J. Symbolic Logic, 59(3), 984–996. arXiv: math/0406587 DOI: 10.2307/2275922 MR: 1295983
    type: article
    abstract: We study how equivalent nonisomorphic models an unsuperstable theory can have. We measure the equivalence by Ehrenfeucht-Fraisse games.
    keywords: M: non, (mod)
  454. Sh:475
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (1996). More forcing notions imply diamond. Arch. Math. Logic, 35(5-6), 299–313. arXiv: math/9408215 DOI: 10.1007/s001530050047 MR: 1420260
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that the Sacks forcing collapses the continuum onto the dominating number ${\mathfrak d}$, answering the question of Carlson and Laver. Next we prove that if a proper forcing of the size at most continuum collapses $\omega_2$ then it forces $\diamondsuit_{\omega_1}$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (diam)
  455. Sh:476
    Jech, T. J., & Shelah, S. (1996). Possible PCF algebras. J. Symbolic Logic, 61(1), 313–317. arXiv: math/9412208 DOI: 10.2307/2275613 MR: 1380692
    type: article
    abstract: There exists a family $\{B_{\alpha}\}_{\alpha<\omega_1}$ of sets of countable ordinals such that 1) $\max B_{\alpha}=\alpha$, 2) if $\alpha\in B_{\beta}$ then $B_{\alpha}\subseteq B_{\beta}$, 3) if $\lambda\leq \alpha$ and $\lambda$ is a limit ordinal then $B_{\alpha}\cap\lambda$ is not in the ideal generated by the $B_{\beta}$, 4) $\beta< \alpha$, and by the bounded subsets of $\lambda$, 5) there is a partition $\{A_n\}_{n=0}^{\infty}$ of $\omega_1$ such that for every $\alpha$ and every $n,$ $B_{\alpha}\cap A_n$ is finite.
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  456. Sh:477
    Brendle, J., Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1992). Combinatorial properties of Hechler forcing. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 58(3), 185–199. arXiv: math/9211202 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(92)90027-W MR: 1191940
    type: article
    abstract: Using a notion of rank for Hechler forcing we show: 1) assuming $\omega_1^V = \omega_1^L$, there is no real in $V[d]$ which is eventually different from the reals in $L[d]$, where $d$ is Hechler over $V$; 2) adding one Hechler real makes the invariants on the left-hand side of Cicho\'n's diagram equal $\omega_1$ and those on the right-hand side equal $2^\omega$ and produces a maximal almost disjoint family of subsets of $\omega$ of size $\omega_1$; 3) there is no perfect set of random reals over $V$ in $V[r][d]$, where $r$ is random over $V$ and $d$ Hechler over $V[r]$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  457. Sh:478
    Judah, H. I., & Shelah, S. (1994). Killing Luzin and Sierpiński sets. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 120(3), 917–920. arXiv: math/9401215 DOI: 10.2307/2160487 MR: 1164145
    type: article
    abstract: We will kill the old Luzin and Sierpinski sets in order to build a model where $U(Meager) = U(Null)=\aleph_1$ and there are neither Luzin nor Sierpinski sets. Thus we answer a question of J. Steprans, communicated by S. Todorcevic on route from Evans to MSRI.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (leb), (meag)
  458. Sh:479
    Shelah, S. (1996). On Monk’s questions. Fund. Math., 151(1), 1–19. arXiv: math/9601218 MR: 1405517
    type: article
    abstract: Monk asks (problems 13, 15 in his list; $\pi$ is the algebraic density): "For a Boolean algebra $B$, $\aleph_0\le\theta\le\pi(B)$, does $B$ have a subalgebra $B'$ with $\pi(B')=\theta$?" If $\theta$ is regular the answer is easily positive, we show that in general it may be negative, but for quite many singular cardinals - it is positive; the theorems are quite complementary. Next we deal with $\pi\chi$ and we show that the $\pi\chi$ of an ultraproduct of Boolean algebras is not necessarily the ultraproduct of the $\pi\chi$'s. We also prove that for infinite Boolean algebras $A_i$ ($i<\kappa$) and a non-principal ultrafilter $D$ on $\kappa$: if $n_i<\aleph_0$ for $i<\kappa$ and $\mu=\prod_{i<\kappa} n_i/D$ is regular, then $\pi\chi(A)\ge \mu$. Here $A=\prod_{i<\kappa}A_i/D$. By a theorem of Peterson the regularity of $\mu$ is needed.
    keywords: S: ico, (ba)
  459. Sh:480
    Shelah, S. (1994). How special are Cohen and random forcings, i.e. Boolean algebras of the family of subsets of reals modulo meagre or null. Israel J. Math., 88(1-3), 159–174. arXiv: math/9303208 DOI: 10.1007/BF02937509 MR: 1303493
    type: article
    abstract: The feeling that those two forcing notions -Cohen and Random-(equivalently the corresponding Boolean algebras Borel(R)/(meager sets), Borel(R)/(null sets)) are special, was probably old and widespread. A reasonable interpretation is to show them unique, or ``minimal'' or at least characteristic in a family of ``nice forcing'' like Borel. We shall interpret ``nice'' as Souslin as suggested by Judah Shelah [JdSh 292]. We divide the family of Souslin forcing to two, and expect that: among the first part, i.e. those adding some non-dominated real, Cohen is minimal (=is below every one), while among the rest random is quite characteristic even unique. Concerning the second class we have weak results, concerning the first class, our results look satisfactory. We have two main results: one (1.14) says that Cohen forcing is ``minimal'' in the first class, the other (1.10) says that all c.c.c. Souslin forcing have a property shared by Cohen forcing and Random real forcing, so it gives a weak answer to the problem on how special is random forcing, but says much on all c.c.c. Souslin forcing.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (pure(for))
  460. Sh:481
    Shelah, S. (1996). Was Sierpiński right? III. Can continuum-c.c. times c.c.c. be continuum-c.c.? Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 78(1-3), 259–269. arXiv: math/9509226 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(95)00036-4 MR: 1395402
    type: article
    abstract: We prove the consistency of: if $B_1$, $B_2$ are Boolean algebra satisfying the c.c.c. and the $2^{\aleph_0}$-c.c. respectively then $B_1 \times B_2$ satisfies the $2^{\aleph_0}$-c.c.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (pc)
  461. Sh:483
    Louveau, A., Shelah, S., & Veličković, B. (1993). Borel partitions of infinite subtrees of a perfect tree. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 63(3), 271–281. arXiv: math/9301209 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(93)90151-3 MR: 1237234
    type: article
    abstract: A theorem of Galvin asserts that if the unordered pairs of reals are partitioned into finitely many Borel classes then there is a perfect set $P$ such that all pairs from $P$ lie in the same class. The generalization to $n$-tuples for $n\geq 3$ is false. Let us identify the reals with $2^\omega$ ordered by the lexicographical ordering and define for distinct $x,y\in 2^\omega$, $D(x,y)$ to be the least $n$ such that $x(n)\neq y(n)$. Let the type of an increasing $n$-tuple $\{x_0,\ldots x_{n-1}\}_<$ be the ordering $<^*$ on $\{0,\ldots,n-2\}$ defined by $i<^*j$ iff $D(x_i,x_{i+1})< D(x_j,x_{j+1})$. Galvin proved that for any Borel coloring of triples of reals there is a perfect set $P$ such that the color of any triple from $P$ depends only on its type. Blass proved an analogous result is true for any $n$. As a corollary it follows that if the unordered $n$-tuples of reals are colored into finitely many Borel classes there is a perfect set $P$ such that the $n$-tuples from $P$ meet at most $(n-1)!$ classes. We consider extensions of this result to partitions of infinite increasing sequences of reals. We show, that for any Borel or even analytic partition of all increasing sequences of reals there is a perfect set $P$ such that all strongly increasing sequences from $P$ lie in the same class.
    keywords: S: str, (set)
  462. Sh:484
    Liu, K., & Shelah, S. (1997). Cofinalities of elementary substructures of structures on \aleph_\omega. Israel J. Math., 99, 189–205. arXiv: math/9604242 DOI: 10.1007/BF02760682 MR: 1469093
    type: article
    abstract: Let $0<n^*<\omega$ and $f:X\to n^*+1$ be a function where $X\subseteq\omega\backslash (n^*+1)$ is infinite. Consider the following set $S_f=\{x\subset\aleph_\omega: |x|\le\aleph_{n^*}\ \& \ (\forall n\in X)cf(x\cap\alpha_n)=\aleph_{f(n)}\}$. The question, first posed by Baumgartner, is whether $S_f$ is stationary in $[\alpha_\omega]^{<\aleph_{n^*+1}}$. By a standard result, the above question can also be rephrased as certain transfer property. Namely, $S_f$ is stationary iff for any structure $A=\langle\aleph_\omega, \ldots\rangle$ there's a $B\prec A$ such that $|B|=\aleph_{n^*}$ and for all $n\in X$ we have $cf(B\cap\aleph_n)=\aleph_{f(n)}$. In this paper, we are going to prove a few results concerning the above question.
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  463. Sh:485
    Abraham, U., & Shelah, S. (2002). Coding with ladders a well ordering of the reals. J. Symbolic Logic, 67(2), 579–597. arXiv: math/0104195 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1190150099 MR: 1905156
    type: article
    abstract: Any model of ZFC + GCH has a generic extension (made with a poset of size $\aleph_2$) in which the following hold: $MA + 2^{\aleph_0}=\aleph_2+$ {\em there exists a} $\Delta^2_1$-{\em well ordering of the reals.} The proof consists in iterating posets designed to change at will the guessing properties of ladder systems on $\omega_1$. Therefore, the study of such ladders is a main concern of this article.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, S: dst, (set)
  464. Sh:487
    Goldstern, M., Repický, M., Shelah, S., & Spinas, O. (1995). On tree ideals. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 123(5), 1573–1581. arXiv: math/9311212 DOI: 10.2307/2161150 MR: 1233972
    type: article
    abstract: Let $l^0$ and $m^0$ be the ideals associated with Laver and Miller forcing, respectively. We show that ${\bf add }(l^0) < {\bf cov}(l^0)$ and ${\bf add }(m^0) < {\bf cov}(m^0)$ are consistent. We also show that both Laver and Miller forcing collapse the continuum to a cardinal $\le {\bf h}$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  465. Sh:488
    Halbeisen, L. J., & Shelah, S. (1994). Consequences of arithmetic for set theory. J. Symbolic Logic, 59(1), 30–40. arXiv: math/9308220 DOI: 10.2307/2275247 MR: 1264961
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper, we consider certain cardinals in ZF (set theory without AC, the Axiom of Choice). In ZFC (set theory with AC), given any cardinals $\mathcal{C}$ and $\mathcal{D},$ either $\mathcal{C} \leq \mathcal{D}$ or $\mathcal{D} \leq \mathcal{C}.$ However, in ZF this is no longer so. For a given infinite set $A$ consider $Seq (A)$, the set of all sequences of $A$ without repetition. We compare $|Seq (A)|$, the cardinality of this set, to $|{\mathcal {P}}(A)|$, the cardinality of the power set of $A$. What is provable about these two cardinals in ZF? The main result of this paper is that ZF$\vdash\forall A: |Seq(A)|\neq|{\mathcal{P}}(A)|$ and we show that this is the best possible result. Furthermore, it is provable in ZF that if $B$ is an infinite set, then $|fin(B)|<|{\mathcal{P}}(B)|$, even though the existence for some infinite set $B^*$ of a function $f$ from $fin(B^*)$ onto ${\mathcal{P}}(B^*)$ is consistent with ZF.
    keywords: S: ico, (AC)
  466. Sh:489
    Laskowski, M. C., & Shelah, S. (1993). On the existence of atomic models. J. Symbolic Logic, 58(4), 1189–1194. arXiv: math/9301210 DOI: 10.2307/2275137 MR: 1253916
    type: article
    abstract: We give an example of a countable theory $T$ such that for every cardinal $\lambda\ge\aleph_2$ there is a fully indiscernible set $A$ of power $\lambda$ such that the principal types are dense over $A$, yet there is no atomic model of $T$ over $A$. In particular, $T(A)$ is a theory of size $\lambda$ where the principal types are dense, yet $T(A)$ has no atomic model.
    keywords: M: odm, (mod)
  467. Sh:490
    Bartoszyński, T., Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (1996). Adding one random real. J. Symbolic Logic, 61(1), 80–90. arXiv: math/9406229 DOI: 10.2307/2275599 MR: 1380678
    type: article
    abstract: We study the cardinal invariants of measure and category after adding one random real. In particular, we show that the number of measure zero subsets of the plane which are necessary to cover graphs of all continuous functions maybe large while the covering for measure is small.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (leb)
  468. Sh:491
    Gilchrist, M., & Shelah, S. (1996). Identities on cardinals less than \aleph_\omega. J. Symbolic Logic, 61(3), 780–787. arXiv: math/9505215 DOI: 10.2307/2275784 MR: 1412509
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\kappa$ be an uncountable cardinal and the edges of a complete graph with $\kappa$ vertices be colored with $\aleph_0$ colors. For $\kappa>2^{\aleph_0}$ the Erd\H{o}s-Rado theorem implies that there is an infinite monochromatic subgraph. However, if $\kappa\leq 2^{\aleph_0}$, then it may be impossible to find a monochromatic triangle. This paper is concerned with the latter situation. We consider the types of colorings of finite subgraphs that must occur when $\kappa\leq 2^{\aleph_0}$. In particular, we are concerned with the case $\aleph_1\leq\kappa\leq\aleph_\omega$
    keywords: S: for, (set-mod)
  469. Sh:492
    Komjáth, P., & Shelah, S. (1995). Universal graphs without large cliques. J. Combin. Theory Ser. B, 63(1), 125–135. arXiv: math/9308221 DOI: 10.1006/jctb.1995.1008 MR: 1309360
    type: article
    abstract: We give some existence/nonexistence statements on universal graphs, which under GCH give a necessary and sufficient condition for the existence of a universal graph of size $\lambda$ with no $K(\kappa)$, namely, if either $\kappa$ is finite or $cf(\kappa)>cf(\lambda)$. (Here $K(\kappa)$ denotes the complete graph on $\kappa$ vertices.) The special case when $\lambda^{<\kappa}=\lambda$ was first proved by F. Galvin. Next, we investigate the question that if there is no universal $K(\kappa)$-free graph of size $\lambda$ then how many of these graphs embed all the other. It was known, that if $\lambda^{<\lambda}= \lambda$ (e.g., if $\lambda$ is regular and the GCH holds below $\lambda$), and $\kappa=\omega$, then this number is $\lambda^+$. We show that this holds for every $\kappa\leq\lambda$ of countable cofinality. On the other hand, even for $\kappa=\omega_1$, and any regular $\lambda\geq\omega_1$ it is consistent that the GCH holds below $\lambda$, $2^{\lambda}$ is as large as we wish, and the above number is either $\lambda^+$ or $2^{\lambda}$, so both extremes can actually occur.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (graph), (univ)
  470. Sh:493
    Jin, R., & Shelah, S. (1994). The strength of the isomorphism property. J. Symbolic Logic, 59(1), 292–301. arXiv: math/9401216 DOI: 10.2307/2275266 MR: 1264980
    type: article
    abstract: In \S 1 of this paper, we characterize the isomorphism property of nonstandard universes in terms of the realization of some second--order types in model theory. In \S 2, several applications are given. One of the applications answers a question of D. Ross about infinite Loeb measure spaces
    keywords: M: odm
  471. Sh:494
    Shelah, S., & Spinas, O. (2000). The distributivity numbers of \mathcal P(\omega)/\mathrm{fin} and its square. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 352(5), 2023–2047. arXiv: math/9606227 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-99-02270-9 MR: 1751223
    type: article
    abstract: We show that in a model obtained by forcing with a countable support iteration of length $\omega_2$ of Mathias forcing ${\bf h}(2)$, the distributivity number of r.o.$({\mathcal P}(\omega)$/fin)$^2$, is $\omega_1$ but ${\bf h}$, the one of ${\mathcal P}(\omega)$/fin, is $\omega_2$.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (inv)
  472. Sh:495
    Apter, A. W., & Shelah, S. (1997). On the strong equality between supercompactness and strong compactness. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 349(1), 103–128. arXiv: math/9502232 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-97-01531-6 MR: 1333385
    type: article
    abstract: We show that supercompactness and strong compactness can be equivalent even as properties of pairs of regular cardinals. Specifically, we show that if $V \models$ ZFC + GCH is a given model (which in interesting cases contains instances of supercompactness), then there is some cardinal and cofinality preserving generic extension $V[G]\models$ ZFC + GCH in which, (a) (preservation) for $\kappa \le \lambda$ regular, if $V \models ``\kappa$ is $\lambda$ supercompact'', then $V[G] \models ``\kappa$ is $\lambda$ supercompact'' and so that, (b) (equivalence) for $\kappa \le \lambda$ regular, $V[G] \models ``\kappa$ is $\lambda$ strongly compact'' iff $V[G] \models ``\kappa$ is $\lambda$ supercompact'', except possibly if $\kappa$ is a measurable limit of cardinals which are $\lambda $ supercompact.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (pure(large))
  473. Sh:496
    Apter, A. W., & Shelah, S. (1997). Menas’ result is best possible. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 349(5), 2007–2034. arXiv: math/9512226 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-97-01691-7 MR: 1370634
    type: article
    abstract: Generalizing some earlier techniques due to the second author, we show that Menas' theorem which states that the least cardinal $\kappa$ which is a measurable limit of supercompact or strongly compact cardinals is strongly compact but not $2^\kappa$ supercompact is best possible. Using these same techniques, we also extend and give a new proof of a theorem of Woodin and extend and give a new proof of an unpublished theorem due to the first author.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (pure(large))
  474. Sh:497
    Shelah, S. (1997). Set theory without choice: not everything on cofinality is possible. Arch. Math. Logic, 36(2), 81–125. arXiv: math/9512227 DOI: 10.1007/s001530050057 MR: 1462202
    type: article
    abstract: We prove (ZF+DC) e.g. : if $\mu=|H(\mu)|$ then $\mu ^+$ is regular non measurable. This is in contrast with the results for $\mu=\aleph_{\omega}$ on measurability see Apter Magidor [ApMg]
    keywords: S: pcf, (set), (AC)
  475. Sh:498
    Jin, R., & Shelah, S. (1994). Essential Kurepa trees versus essential Jech-Kunen trees. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 69(1), 107–131. arXiv: math/9401217 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(94)90021-3 MR: 1301608
    type: article
    abstract: By an $\omega_1$--tree we mean a tree of size $\omega_1$ and height $\omega_1$. An $\omega_1$--tree is called a Kurepa tree if all its levels are countable and it has more than $\omega_1$ branches. An $\omega_1$--tree is called a Jech--Kunen tree if it has $\kappa$ branches for some $\kappa$ strictly between $\omega_1$ and $2^{\omega_1}$. A Kurepa tree is called an essential Kurepa tree if it contains no Jech--Kunen subtrees. A Jech--Kunen tree is called an essential Jech--Kunen tree if it contains no Kurepa subtrees. In this paper we prove that (1) it is consistent with CH and $2^{\omega_1}>\omega_2$ that there exist essential Kurepa trees and there are no essential Jech--Kunen trees, (2) it is consistent with CH and $2^{\omega_1}>\omega_2$ plus the existence of a Kurepa tree with $2^{\omega_1}$ branches that there exist essential Jech--Kunen trees and there are no essential Kurepa trees. In the second result we require the existence of a Kurepa tree with $2^{\omega_1}$ branches in order to avoid triviality.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (trees)
  476. Sh:499
    Kojman, M., & Shelah, S. (1995). Homogeneous families and their automorphism groups. J. London Math. Soc. (2), 52(2), 303–317. arXiv: math/9409205 DOI: 10.1112/jlms/52.2.303 MR: 1356144
    type: article
    abstract: A homogeneous family of subsets over a given set is one with a very ``rich'' automorphism group. We prove the existence of a bi-universal element in the class of homogeneous families over a given infinite set and give an explicit construction of $2^{\bf c}$ isomorphism types of homogeneous families over a countable set.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (auto)
  477. Sh:500
    Shelah, S. (1996). Toward classifying unstable theories. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 80(3), 229–255. arXiv: math/9508205 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(95)00066-6 MR: 1402297
    type: article
    abstract: The paper deals with two issues: the existence of universal models of a theory $T$ and related properties when cardinal arithmetic does not give this existence offhand. In the first section we prove that simple theories (e.g., theories without the tree property, a class properly containing the stable theories) behaves ``better'' than theories with the strict order property, by criterion from [Sh:457]. In the second section we introduce properties $SOP_n$ such that the strict order property implies $SOP_{n+1}$, which implies $SOP_n$, which in turn implies the tree property. Now $SOP_4$ already implies non-existence of universal models in cases where earlier the strict order property was needed, and $SOP_3$ implies maximality in the Keisler order, again improving an earlier result which had used the strict order property.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (univ), (up)
  478. Sh:501
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (1996). Localizations of infinite subsets of \omega. Arch. Math. Logic, 35(5-6), 315–339. arXiv: math/9506222 DOI: 10.1007/s001530050048 MR: 1420261
    type: article
    abstract: In the present paper we are interested in properties of forcing notions which measure in a sense the distance between the ground model reals and the reals in the extension. We look at the ways the ``new'' reals can be aproximated by ``old'' reals. We consider localizations for infinite subsets of $\omega$. Though each member of $[\omega]^\omega$ can be identified with its increasing enumeration, the (standard) localizations of the enumeration does not provide satisfactory information on successive points of the set. They give us ``candidates'' for the $n$-th point of the set but the same candidates can appear several times for distinct $n$. That led to a suggestion that we should consider disjoint subsets of $\omega$ as sets of ``candidates'' for successive points of the localized set. We have two possibilities. Either we can demand that each set from the localization contains a limited number of members of the localized set or we can postulate that each intersection of that kind is large. Localizations of this kind are studied in section 1. In the second section we investigate localizations of infinite subsets of $\omega$ by sets of integers from the ground model. These localizations might be thought as localizations by partitions of $\omega$ into successive intervals.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (creatures)
  479. Sh:502
    Komjáth, P., & Shelah, S. On uniformly antisymmetric functions. Real Anal. Exchange, 19(1), 218–225. arXiv: math/9308222 MR: 1268847
    type: article
    abstract: We show that there is always a uniformly antisymmetric $f:A\to\{0,1\}$ if $A\subset R$ is countable. We prove that the continuum hypothesis is equivalent to the statement that there is an $f:R\to\omega$ with $|S_x|\leq 1$ for every $x\in R$. If the continuum is at least $\aleph_n$ then there exists a point $x$ such that $S_x$ has at least $2^n-1$ elements. We also show that there is a function $f:Q\to\{0,1,2,3\}$ such that $S_x$ is always finite, but no such function with finite range on $R$ exists
    keywords: S: ico
  480. Sh:503
    Shelah, S. (1994). The number of independent elements in the product of interval Boolean algebras. Math. Japon., 39(1), 1–5. arXiv: math/9312212 MR: 1261328
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that in the product of $\kappa$ many Boolean algebras we cannot find an independent set of more than $2^\kappa$ elements solving a problem of Monk (earlier it was known that we cannot find more than $2^{2^\kappa}$ but can find $2^\kappa$).
    keywords: S: ico, (ba), (inv)
  481. Sh:504
    Koppelberg, S., & Shelah, S. (1996). Subalgebras of Cohen algebras need not be Cohen. In Logic: from foundations to applications (Staffordshire, 1993), Oxford Univ. Press, New York, pp. 261–275. arXiv: math/9610227 MR: 1428008
    type: article
    abstract: We give an example of a regular and complete subalgebra of a Cohen algebra which is not Cohen.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (ba), (pure(for))
  482. Sh:505
    Eklof, P. C., & Shelah, S. (1994). A combinatorial principle equivalent to the existence of non-free Whitehead groups. In Abelian group theory and related topics (Oberwolfach, 1993), Vol. 171, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, pp. 79–98. arXiv: math/9403220 DOI: 10.1090/conm/171/01765 MR: 1293134
    type: article
    abstract: As a consequence of identifying the principle described in the title, we prove that for any uncountable cardinal $\lambda $, if there is a $\lambda $-free Whitehead group of cardinality $\lambda $ which is not free, then there are many ``nice'' Whitehead groups of cardinality $\lambda $ which are not free.
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (ab), (wh), (unif)
  483. Sh:506
    Shelah, S. (1997). The pcf theorem revisited. In The mathematics of Paul Erdős, II, Vol. 14, Springer, Berlin, pp. 420–459. arXiv: math/9502233 DOI: 10.1007/978-3-642-60406-5_36 MR: 1425231
    type: article
    abstract: The $\textrm{pcf}$ theorem (of the possible cofinality theory) was proved for reduced products $\prod_{i< \kappa} \lambda_i/I$, where $\kappa< \min_{i< \kappa} \lambda_i$. Here we prove this theorem under weaker assumptions such as $wsat(I)< \min_{i< \kappa} \lambda_i$, where $wsat(I)$ is the minimal $\theta$ such that $\kappa$ cannot be delivered to $\theta$ sets $\notin I$ (or even slightly weaker condition). We also look at the existence of exact upper bounds relative to $< _I$ ($< _I$-eub) as well as cardinalities of reduced products and the cardinals $T_D(\lambda)$. Finally we apply this to the problem of the depth of ultraproducts (and reduced products) of Boolean algebras
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  484. Sh:507
    Goldstern, M., & Shelah, S. (1995). The bounded proper forcing axiom. J. Symbolic Logic, 60(1), 58–73. arXiv: math/9501222 DOI: 10.2307/2275509 MR: 1324501
    type: article
    abstract: The bounded proper forcing axiom BPFA is the statement that for any family of $\aleph_1$ many maximal antichains of a proper forcing notion, each of size $\aleph_1$, there is a directed set meeting all these antichains. A regular cardinal $\kappa$ is called ${\Sigma}_1$-reflecting, if for any regular cardinal $\chi$, for all formulas $\varphi$, ``$H(\chi)\models `\varphi$'\,'' implies ``$\exists\delta<\kappa$, $H(\delta)\models `\varphi$'\,'' We show that BPFA is equivalent to the statement that two nonisomorphic models of size $\aleph_1 $ cannot be made isomorphic by a proper forcing notion, and we show that the consistency strength of the bounded proper forcing axiom is exactly the existence of a $\Sigma_1$-reflecting cardinal (which is less than the existence of a Mahlo cardinal). We also show that the question of the existence of isomorphisms between two structures can be reduced to the question of rigidity of a structure.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter)
  485. Sh:508
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (1997). Simple forcing notions and forcing axioms. J. Symbolic Logic, 62(4), 1297–1314. arXiv: math/9606228 DOI: 10.2307/2275644 MR: 1617945
    type: article
    abstract: In the present paper we are interested in simple forcing notions and Forcing Axioms. A starting point for our investigations was the article [JR1] in which several problems were posed. We answer some of those problems here.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  486. Sh:509
    Shelah, S. (2008). Vive la différence. III. Israel J. Math., 166, 61–96. arXiv: math/0112237 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-008-1020-3 MR: 2430425
    type: article
    abstract: We show that, consistently, there is an ultrafilter ${\mathcal F}$ on $\omega$ such that if $N^\ell_n=(P^\ell_n\cup Q^\ell_n, P^\ell_n,Q^\ell_n,R^\ell_n)$ (for $\ell=1,2$, $n<\omega$), $P^\ell_n \cup Q^\ell_n \subseteq\omega$, and $\prod\limits_{n<\omega} N^1_n/ {\mathcal F}\equiv\prod\limits_{n<\omega}N^2_n/{\mathcal F}$ are models of the canonical theory $t^{\rm ind}$ of the strong independence property, then every isomorphism from $\prod\limits_{n<\omega} N^1_n/{\mathcal F}$ onto $\prod\limits_{n< \omega} N^2_n/{\mathcal F}$ is a product isomorphism.
    keywords: M: odm, S: for
  487. Sh:510
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (1994). Decomposing Baire class 1 functions into continuous functions. Fund. Math., 145(2), 171–180. arXiv: math/9401218 MR: 1297403
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\mathfrak{dec}$ be the least cardinal $\kappa$ such that every function of first Baire class can be decomposed into $\kappa$ continuous functions. Cichon, Morayne, Pawlikowski and Solecki proved that $cov(Meager)\leq \mathfrak{dec}\leq \mathfrak{d}$ and asked whether these inequalities could, consistently, be strict. By $cov(Meager)$ is meant the least number of closed nowhere dense sets required to cover the real line and by $\mathfrak{d}$ is denoted the least cardinal of a dominating family in $\omega^\omega$. Steprans showed that it is consistent that $cov(Meager)\neq \mathfrak{dec}$. In this paper we show that the second inequality can also be made strict. The model where $\mathfrak{dec}$ is different from $\mathfrak{d}$ is the one obtained by adding $\omega_2$ Miller - sometimes known as super-perfect or rational-perfect - reals to a model of the Continuum Hypothesis. It is somewhat surprising that the model used to establish the consistency of the other inequality, $cov(Meager)\neq\mathfrak{dec}$, is a slight modification of the iteration of super-perfect forcing.
    keywords: S: str, (set)
  488. Sh:512
    Balcerzak, M., Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (1998). Ideals without ccc. J. Symbolic Logic, 63(1), 128–148. arXiv: math/9610219 DOI: 10.2307/2586592 MR: 1610790
    type: article
    abstract: Let $I$ be an ideal of subsets of a Polish space $X$, containing all singletons and possessing a Borel basis. Assuming that $I$ does not satisfy ccc, we consider the following conditions (B), (M) and (D). Condition (B) states that there is a disjoint family $F\subseteq P(X)$ of size ${\bf c}$, consisting of Borel sets which are not in $I$. Condition (M) states that there is a function $f:X\rightarrow X$ with $f^{-1}[\{x\}]\notin I$ for each $x\in X$. Provided that $X$ is a group and $I$ is invariant, condition (D) states that there exist a Borel set $B\notin I$ and a perfect set $P\subseteq X$ for which the family $\{ B+x: x\in P\} $ is disjoint. The aim of the paper is to study whether the reverse implications in the chain $(D)\Rightarrow (M)\Rightarrow (B)\Rightarrow not-ccc$ can hold. We build a $\sigma $-ideal on the Cantor group witnessing "(M) and not (D)" (Section 2). A modified version of that $\sigma$-ideal contains the whole space (Section 3). Some consistency results deriving (M) from (B) for "nicely" defined ideals are established (Section 4). We show that both ccc and (M) can fail (Theorems 1.3 and 4.2). Finally, some sharp versions of (M) for invariant ideals on Polish groups are investigated (Section 5).
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  489. Sh:513
    Shelah, S. (2002). PCF and infinite free subsets in an algebra. Arch. Math. Logic, 41(4), 321–359. arXiv: math/9807177 DOI: 10.1007/s001530100101 MR: 1906504
    type: article
    abstract: We give another proof that for every $\lambda\geq\beth_\omega$ for every large enough regular $\kappa<\beth_\omega$ we have $\lambda^{[\kappa]}=\lambda$, dealing with sufficient conditions for replacing $\beth_\omega$ by $\aleph_\omega$. In \S2 we show that large pcf$(\mathfrak{a})$ implies existence of free sets. An example is that if pp$(\aleph_\omega)>\aleph_{\omega_1}$ then for every algebra $M$ of cardinality $\aleph_\omega$ with countably many functions, for some $a_n\in M$ (for $n<\omega$) we have $a_n\notin cl_M(\{a_l: l\neq n, l<\omega\})$. Then we present results complementary to those of section 2 (but not close enough): if IND$(\mu,\sigma)$ (in every algebra with universe $\lambda$ and $\le\sigma$ functions there is an infinite independent subset) then for no distinct regular $\lambda_i\in {\rm Reg}\backslash\mu^+$ (for $i<\kappa$) does $\prod_{i<\kappa}\lambda_i/[\kappa]^{\le\sigma}$ have true cofinality. We look at IND$(\langle J^{bd}_{\kappa_n}: n<\omega\rangle)$ and more general version, and from assumptions as in \S2 get results even for the non stationary ideal. Lastly, we deal with some other measurements of $[\lambda]^{\ge \theta}$ and give an application by a construction of a Boolean Algebra.
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  490. Sh:514
    Magidor, M., & Shelah, S. (1994). \mathrm{Bext}^2(G,T) can be nontrivial, even assuming GCH. In Abelian group theory and related topics (Oberwolfach, 1993), Vol. 171, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, pp. 287–294. arXiv: math/9405214 DOI: 10.1090/conm/171/01778 MR: 1293148
    type: article
    abstract: Using the consistency of some large cardinals we produce a model of Set Theory in which the generalized continuum hypothesis holds and for some torsion-free abelian group $G$ of cardinality $\aleph_{\omega+1}$ and for some torsion group $T$, $Bext^2(G,T)\not=0$.
    keywords: S: for, (ab)
  491. Sh:515
    Shelah, S. (1997). A finite partition theorem with double exponential bound. In The mathematics of Paul Erdős, II, Vol. 14, Springer, Berlin, pp. 240–246. arXiv: math/9502234 DOI: 10.1007/978-3-642-60406-5_21 MR: 1425218
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that double exponentiation is an upper bound to Ramsey theorem for colouring of pairs when we want to predetermine the order of the differences of successive members of the homogeneous set.
    keywords: O: fin, (pc), (fc)
  492. Sh:516
    Komjáth, P., & Shelah, S. (1996). Coloring finite subsets of uncountable sets. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 124(11), 3501–3505. arXiv: math/9505216 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-96-03450-8 MR: 1342032
    type: article
    abstract: It is consistent for every \(1\leq n< \omega\) that \(2^\omega=\omega_n\) and there is a function \(F:[\omega_n]^{< \omega}\to\omega \) such that every finite set can be written at most \(2^n-1\) ways as the union of two distinct monocolored sets. If GCH holds, for every such coloring there is a finite set that can be written at least \(\sum^n_{i=1}{n+i\choose n}{n\choose i}\) ways as the union of two sets with the same color.
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  493. Sh:517
    Shelah, S. (2005). Zero-one laws for graphs with edge probabilities decaying with distance. II. Fund. Math., 185(3), 211–245. arXiv: math/0404239 DOI: 10.4064/fm185-3-2 MR: 2161404
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  494. Sh:518
    Laskowski, M. C., & Shelah, S. (1996). Forcing isomorphism. II. J. Symbolic Logic, 61(4), 1305–1320. arXiv: math/0011169 DOI: 10.2307/2275818 MR: 1456109
    type: article
    abstract: If $T$ has only countably many complete types, yet has a type of infinite multiplicity then there is a ccc forcing notion $Q$ such that, in any $Q$--generic extension of the universe, there are non-isomorphic models $M_1$ and $M_2$ of $T$ that can be forced isomorphic by a ccc forcing. We give examples showing that the hypothesis on the number of complete types is necessary and what happens if ``ccc'' is replaced other cardinal-preserving adjectives. We also give an example showing that membership in a pseudo-elementary class can be altered by very simple cardinal-preserving forcings.
    keywords: S: for, (mod), (sta)
  495. Sh:519
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (1995). On the existence of rigid \aleph_1-free abelian groups of cardinality \aleph_1. In Abelian groups and modules (Padova, 1994), Vol. 343, Kluwer Acad. Publ., Dordrecht, pp. 227–237. arXiv: math/0104194 MR: 1378201
    type: article
    abstract: An abelian group is said to be $\aleph_1$--free if all its countable subgroups are free. Our main result is: If $R$ is a ring with $R^+$ free and $|R|<\lambda\leq 2^{\aleph_0}$, then there exists an $\aleph_1$--free abelian group $G$ of cardinality $\lambda $ with ${\rm End} G = R$. A corollary to this theorem is: Indecomposable $\aleph_1$--free abelian groups of cardinality $\aleph_1$ do exist.
    keywords: S: ico, (ab)
  496. Sh:520
    Eklof, P. C., Foreman, M. D., & Shelah, S. (1995). On invariants for \omega_1-separable groups. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 347(11), 4385–4402. arXiv: math/9501223 DOI: 10.2307/2155042 MR: 1316849
    type: article
    abstract: We study the classification of $\omega_1$-separable groups using Ehrenfeucht-Fra{\"\i}ss\'e games and prove a strong classification result assuming PFA, and a strong non-structure theorem assuming $\diamondsuit$.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (diam)
  497. Sh:521
    Shelah, S. (1996). If there is an exactly \lambda-free abelian group then there is an exactly \lambda-separable one in \lambda. J. Symbolic Logic, 61(4), 1261–1278. arXiv: math/9503226 DOI: 10.2307/2275815 MR: 1456106
    type: article
    abstract: We give a solution stated in the title to problem 3 of part 1 of the problems listed in the book of Eklof and Mekler [EM],(p.453). There, in pp. 241-242, this is discussed and proved in some cases. The existence of strongly $\lambda$-free ones was proved earlier by the criteria in [Sh:161] in [MkSh:251]. We can apply a similar proof to a large class of other varieties in particular to the variety of (non-commutative) groups.
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (ab), (stal), (af)
  498. Sh:522
    Shelah, S. (1999). Borel sets with large squares. Fund. Math., 159(1), 1–50. arXiv: math/9802134 MR: 1669643
    type: article
    abstract: For a cardinal $\mu$ we give a sufficient condition $(*)_\mu$ (involving ranks measuring existence of independent sets) for: [$(**)_\mu$] if a Borel set $B\subseteq R\times R$ contains a $\mu$-square (i.e. a set of the form $A \times A$, $|A|=\mu)$ then it contains a $2^{\aleph_0}$-square and even a perfect square, and also for [$(***)_\mu$] if $\psi\in L_{\omega_1,\omega}$ has a model of cardinality $\mu$ then it has a model of cardinality continuum generated in a nice, absolute way. Assuming MA$ + 2^{\aleph_0}>\mu$ for transparency, those three conditions ($(*)_\mu$, $(**)_\mu$ and $(***)_\mu$) are equivalent, and by this we get e.g. $(\forall\alpha<\omega_1)(2^{\aleph_0}\geq \aleph_\alpha \Rightarrow \neg (**)_{\aleph_\alpha})$, and also $\min\{\mu:(*)_\mu\}$, if $<2^{\aleph_0}$, has cofinality $\aleph_1$. We deal also with Borel rectangles and related model theoretic problems.
    keywords: S: for, S: dst, (mod), (inf-log)
  499. Sh:523
    Shelah, S. (1997). Existence of almost free abelian groups and reflection of stationary set. Math. Japon., 45(1), 1–14. arXiv: math/9606229 MR: 1434949
    type: article
    abstract: \S2: We answer a question of Mekler Eklof on the closure operations of the incompactness spectrum. We answer a question of Foreman and Magidor on reflection of stationary subsets of ${\mathcal S}_{< \aleph_2}(\lambda) = \{ a \subseteq \lambda: |a| < \aleph_2 \}$]. \S3 - $NPT$ is not transitive. We prove $NPT(\lambda,\mu) + NPT(\mu,\kappa) \not\Rightarrow NPT(\lambda,\kappa)$
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (ab), (stal), (app(pcf)), (ref), (af)
  500. Sh:524
    Shelah, S., & Thomas, R., Simon. (1997). The cofinality spectrum of the infinite symmetric group. J. Symbolic Logic, 62(3), 902–916. arXiv: math/9412230 DOI: 10.2307/2275578 MR: 1472129
    type: article
    abstract: A group $G$ that is not finitely generated can be written as the union of a chain of proper subgroups. The cofinality spectrum of $G$, written $CF(S)$, is the set of regular cardinals $\lambda$ such that $G$ can be expressed as the union of a chain of $\lambda$ proper subgroups. The cofinality of $G$, written $c(G)$, is the least element of $CF(G)$. We show that it is consistent that $CF(S)$ is quite a bizarre set of cardinals. For example, we prove Theorem (A): Let $T$ be any subset of $\omega\setminus \{0\}$. Then it is consistent that $\aleph_n \in CF(S)$ if and only if $n\in T$. One might suspect that it is consistent that $CF(S)$ is an arbitrarily prescribed set of regular uncountable cardinals, subject only to the above mentioned constraint. This is not the case. Theorem (B): If $\aleph_n \in CF(S)$ for all $n\in \omega\setminus \{0\}$, then $\aleph_{\omega+1} \in CF(S)$.
    keywords: S: for, (iter), (stal), (app(pcf))
  501. Sh:525
    Gurevich, Y., Immerman, N., & Shelah, S. (1994). McColm’s conjecture [positive elementary inductions]. In Proceedings Ninth Annual IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, IEEE Computer Society Press, pp. 10–19. arXiv: math/9411235 DOI: 10.1109/LICS.1994.316091
    type: article
    abstract: Gregory McColm conjectured that positive elementary inductions are bounded in a class $K$ of finite structures if every $(FO + LFP)$ formula is equivalent to a first-order formula in $K$. Here $(FO + LFP)$ is the extension of first-order logic with the least fixed point operator. We disprove the conjecture. Our main results are two model-theoretic constructions, one deterministic and the other randomized, each of which refutes McColm's conjecture.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  502. Sh:526
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1996). On finite rigid structures. J. Symbolic Logic, 61(2), 549–562. arXiv: math/9411236 DOI: 10.2307/2275675 MR: 1394614
    type: article
    abstract: The main result of this paper is a probabilistic construction of finite rigid structures. It yields a finitely axiomatizable class of finite rigid structures where no $L^\omega_{\infty,\omega}$ formula with counting quantifiers defines a linear order.
    keywords: M: smt, O: fin, (fmt)
  503. Sh:527
    Lifsches, S., & Shelah, S. (1999). Random graphs in the monadic theory of order. Arch. Math. Logic, 38(4-5), 273–312. arXiv: math/9701219 DOI: 10.1007/s001530050129 MR: 1697962
    type: article
    abstract: We continue the works of Gurevich-Shelah and Lifsches-Shelah by showing that it is consistent with ZFC that the first-order theory of random graphs is not interpretable in the monadic theory of all chains. It is provable from ZFC that the theory of random graphs is not interpretable in the monadic second order theory of short chains (hence, in the monadic theory of the real line).
    keywords: M: smt, O: fin, (mod), (mon)
  504. Sh:528
    Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (1997). Randomness and semigenericity. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 349(4), 1359–1376. arXiv: math/9607226 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-97-01869-2 MR: 1407480
    type: article
    abstract: Let $L$ contain only the equality symbol and let $L^+$ be an arbitrary finite symmetric relational language containing $L$. Suppose probabilities are defined on finite $L^+$ structures with "edge probability" $n^{-\alpha}$. By $T^\alpha$, the almost sure theory of random $L^+$-structures we mean the collection of $L^+$-sentences which have limit probability 1. $T_\alpha$ denotes the theory of the generic structures for $K_\alpha$, (the collection of finite graphs $G$ with $\delta_{\alpha}(G)=|G|-\alpha\cdot |\text{edges of $ G$}|$ hereditarily nonnegative.) THEOREM: $T_\alpha$, the almost sure theory of random $L^+$-structures is the same as the theory $T_\alpha$ of the $K_\alpha$-generic model. This theory is complete, stable, and nearly model complete. Moreover, it has the finite model property and has only infinite models so is not finitely axiomatizable.
    keywords: M: cla, O: fin, (mod), (fmt)
  505. Sh:529
    Hyttinen, T., & Shelah, S. (1995). Constructing strongly equivalent nonisomorphic models for unsuperstable theories. Part B. J. Symbolic Logic, 60(4), 1260–1272. arXiv: math/9202205 DOI: 10.2307/2275887 MR: 1367209
    type: article
    abstract: We study how equivalent nonisomorphic models of unsuperstable theories can be. We measure the equivalence by Ehrenfeucht-Fraisse games. This paper continues [HySh:474].
    keywords: M: non, (mod)
  506. Sh:530
    Cummings, J., & Shelah, S. (1995). A model in which every Boolean algebra has many subalgebras. J. Symbolic Logic, 60(3), 992–1004. arXiv: math/9509227 DOI: 10.2307/2275769 MR: 1349006
    type: article
    abstract: We show that it is consistent with ZFC (relative to large cardinals) that every infinite Boolean algebra $B$ has an irredundant subset $A$ such that $2^{|A|} = 2^{|B|}$. This implies in particular that $B$ has $2^{|B|}$ subalgebras. We also discuss some more general problems about subalgebras and free subsets of an algebra. The result on the number of subalgebras in a Boolean algebra solves a question of Monk. The paper is intended to be accessible as far as possible to a general audience, in particular we have confined the more technical material to a ``black box'' at the end. The proof involves a variation on Foreman and Woodin's model in which GCH fails everywhere.
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  507. Sh:531
    Shelah, S., & Spinas, O. (1998). The distributivity numbers of finite products of {\mathcal P}(\omega)/\mathrm{fin}. Fund. Math., 158(1), 81–93. arXiv: math/9801151 MR: 1641157
    type: article
    abstract: Generalizing [ShSi:494], for every $n<\omega $ we construct a ZFC-model where the distributivity number of r.o.$({\mathcal P}(\omega)/\textrm{fin})^{n+1}$, ${\bf h}(n+1)$, is smaller than the one of r.o.$({\mathcal P}(\omega)/\textrm{fin})^{n}$. This answers an old problem of Balcar, Pelant and Simon. We also show that Laver and Miller forcing collapse the continuum to ${\bf h}(n)$ for every $n< \omega $, hence by the first result, consistently they collapse it below ${\bf h}(n)$
    keywords: S: str, (set), (inv)
  508. Sh:533
    Blass, A. R., Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (1999). Choiceless polynomial time. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 100(1-3), 141–187. arXiv: math/9705225 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(99)00005-6 MR: 1711992
    See [Sh:533a]

    type: article
    abstract: Turing machines define polynomial time (PTime) on strings but cannot deal with structures like graphs directly, and there is no known, easily computable string encoding of isomorphism classes of structures. Is there a computation model whose machines do not distinguish between isomorphic structures and compute exactly PTime properties? This question can be recast as follows: Does there exist a logic that captures polynomial time (without presuming the presence of a linear order)? Earlier, one of us conjectured the negative answer. The problem motivated a quest for stronger and stronger PTime logics. All these logics avoid arbitrary choice. Here we attempt to capture the choiceless fragment of PTime. Our computation model is a version of abstract state machines (formerly called evolving algebras). The idea is to replace arbitrary choice with parallel execution. The resulting logic is more expressive than other PTime logics in the literature. A more difficult theorem shows that the logic does not capture all PTime.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  509. Sh:534
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (1998). Cardinal invariants of ultraproducts of Boolean algebras. Fund. Math., 155(2), 101–151. arXiv: math/9703218 MR: 1606511
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with some of problems posed by Monk and related to cardinal invariant of ultraproducts of Boolean algebras. We also introduce and investigate some new cardinal invariants.
    keywords: S: ico, (ba), (up), (inv(ba))
  510. Sh:535
    Eisworth, T., & Shelah, S. (2005). Successors of singular cardinals and coloring theorems. I. Arch. Math. Logic, 44(5), 597–618. arXiv: math/9808138 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-004-0258-7 MR: 2210148
    type: article
    abstract: We investigate the existence of strong colorings on successors of singular cardinals. This work continues Section 2 of [Sh:413], but now our emphasis is on finding colorings of pairs of ordinals, rather than colorings of finite sets of ordinals.
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  511. Sh:536
    Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (2003). Spectra of Monadic Second-Order Formulas with One Unary Function. In 18th Annual IEEE Symposium of Logic in Computer Science, 2003. Proceedings., pp. 291–300. arXiv: math/0404150 DOI: 10.1109/LICS.2003.1210069
    type: article
    abstract: We establish the eventual periodicity of the spectrum of any monadic second-order formula where: (i) all relation symbols, except equality, are unary, and (ii) there is only one function symbol and that symbol is unary.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  512. Sh:537
    Abraham, U., & Shelah, S. (2001). Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin’s axiom. Fund. Math., 169(2), 97–103. arXiv: math/9807178 DOI: 10.4064/fm169-2-1 MR: 1852375
    type: article
    abstract: Assuming the continuum hypothesis there is an inseparable sequence of length $\omega_1$ that contains no Lusin subsequence, while if Martin's Axiom and the negation of CH is assumed then every inseparable sequence (of length $\omega_1$) is a union of countably many Lusin subsequences.
    keywords: S: str, (set)
  513. Sh:539
    Lifsches, S., & Shelah, S. (1996). Uniformization, choice functions and well orders in the class of trees. J. Symbolic Logic, 61(4), 1206–1227. arXiv: math/9404227 DOI: 10.2307/2275812 MR: 1456103
    type: article
    abstract: The monadic second-order theory of trees allows quantification over elements and over arbitrary subsets. We classify the class of trees with respect to the question: does a tree $T$ have a definable choice function (by a monadic formula with parameters)? A natural dichotomy arises where the trees that fall in the first class don't have a definable choice function and the trees in the second class have even a definable well ordering of their elements. This has a close connection to the uniformization problem.
    keywords: M: odm, (set-mod), (mon)
  514. Sh:540
    Brendle, J., & Shelah, S. (1996). Evasion and prediction. II. J. London Math. Soc. (2), 53(1), 19–27. arXiv: math/9407207 DOI: 10.1112/jlms/53.1.19 MR: 1362683
    type: article
    abstract: A subgroup $G\leq {\mathbb Z}^\omega$ exhibits the Specker phenomenon if every homomorphism $G \to {\mathbb Z}$ maps almost all unit vectors to $0$. We give several combinatorial characterizations of the cardinal $\mathfrak{se}$, the size of the smallest $G\leq {\mathbb Z}^\omega$ exhibiting the Specker phenomenon. We also prove the consistency of ${\bf b}< {\bf e}$, where ${\bf b}$ is the unbounding number and ${\bf e}$ the evasion number. Our results answer several questions addressed by Blass.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (inv)
  515. Sh:541
    Cummings, J., & Shelah, S. (1995). Cardinal invariants above the continuum. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 75(3), 251–268. arXiv: math/9509228 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(95)00003-Y MR: 1355135
    type: article
    abstract: We prove some consistency results about ${\bf b}(\lambda)$ and ${\bf d}(\lambda)$, which are natural generalisations of the cardinal invariants of the continuum ${\bf b}$ and ${\bf d}$. We also define invariants ${\bf b}_{\rm cl}(\lambda)$ and ${\bf d}_{\rm cl}(\lambda)$, and prove that almost always ${\bf b}(\lambda) = {\bf b}_{\rm cl}(\lambda)$ and ${\bf d}(\lambda)={\bf d}_{\rm cl}(\lambda)$
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  516. Sh:542
    Shelah, S. (1996). Large normal ideals concentrating on a fixed small cardinality. Arch. Math. Logic, 35(5-6), 341–347. arXiv: math/9406219 DOI: 10.1007/s001530050049 MR: 1420262
    type: article
    abstract: A property of a filter, a kind of large cardinal property, suffices for the proof in Liu Shelah [LiSh:484] and is proved consistent as required there. A natural property which looks better, not only is not obtained here, but is shown to be false. On earlier related theorems see Gitik Shelah [GiSh310].
    keywords: S: for, (set), (normal), (large)
  517. Sh:543
    Fuchino, S., Shelah, S., & Soukup, L. (1994). On a theorem of Shapiro. Math. Japon., 40(2), 199–206. arXiv: math/9405215 MR: 1297233
    type: article
    abstract: We show that a theorem of Leonid B.\ Shapiro which was proved under MA, is actually independent from ZFC. We also give a direct proof of the Boolean algebra version of the theorem under MA({\it Cohen}).
    keywords: S: ico, (ba)
  518. Sh:544
    Fuchino, S., Shelah, S., & Soukup, L. (1997). Sticks and clubs. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 90(1-3), 57–77. arXiv: math/9804153 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(97)00030-4 MR: 1489304
    type: article
    abstract: We study combinatorial principles known as stick and club. Several variants of these principles and cardinal invariants connected to them are also considered. We introduce a new kind of side-by-side product of partial orders which we call pseudo-product. Using such products, we give several generic extensions where some of these principles hold together with $\neg CH$ and Martin's Axiom for countable p.o.-sets. An iterative version of the pseudo-product is used under an inaccessible cardinal to show the consistency of the club principle for every stationary subset of limits of $\omega_1$ together with $\neg CH$ and Martin's Axiom for countable p.o.-sets.
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  519. Sh:545
    Džamonja, M., & Shelah, S. (1996). Saturated filters at successors of singular, weak reflection and yet another weak club principle. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 79(3), 289–316. arXiv: math/9601219 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(95)00040-2 MR: 1395679
    type: article
    abstract: Suppose that $\lambda$ is the successor of a singular cardinal $\mu$ whose cofinality is an uncountable cardinal $\kappa$. We give a sufficient condition that the club filter of $\lambda$ concentrating on the points of cofinality $\kappa$ is not $\lambda^+$-saturated. The condition is phrased in terms of a notion that we call weak reflection. We discuss various properties of weak reflection
    keywords: S: pcf, (set), (ref)
  520. Sh:546
    Shelah, S. (2000). Was Sierpiński right? IV. J. Symbolic Logic, 65(3), 1031–1054. arXiv: math/9712282 DOI: 10.2307/2586687 MR: 1791363
    type: article
    abstract: We prove for any $\mu=\mu^{<\mu}<\theta<\lambda,\lambda$ large enough (just strongly inaccessible Mahlo) the consistency of $2^\mu=\lambda\rightarrow [\theta]^2_3$ and even $2^\mu=\lambda\rightarrow [\theta]^2_{\sigma,2}$ for $\sigma<\mu$. The new point is that possibly $\theta>\mu^+$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (pc)
  521. Sh:547
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (1998). Endomorphism rings of modules whose cardinality is cofinal to omega. In Abelian groups, module theory, and topology (Padua, 1997), Vol. 201, Dekker, New York, pp. 235–248. arXiv: math/0011186 MR: 1651170
    type: article
    abstract: The main result is Theorem: Let $A$ be an $R$-algebra, $\mu,\lambda$ be cardinals such that $|A|\leq\mu=\mu^{\aleph_0}<\lambda\leq 2^\mu$. If $A$ is $\aleph_0$-cotorsion-free or $A$ is countably free, respectively, then there exists an $\aleph_0$-cotorsion-free or a separable (reduced, torsion-free) $R$-module $G$ respectively of cardinality $|G|=\lambda$ with ${\rm End}_R G=A\oplus{\rm Fin} G$.
    keywords: S: ico, (ab)
  522. Sh:548
    Shelah, S. (1996). Very weak zero one law for random graphs with order and random binary functions. Random Structures Algorithms, 9(4), 351–358. arXiv: math/9606230 DOI: 10.1002/(SICI)1098-2418(199612)9:4<351::AID-RSA1>3.3.CO;2-D MR: 1605415
    type: article
    abstract: Let $G_<(n,p)$ denote the usual random graph $G(n,p)$ on a totally ordered set of $n$ vertices. We will fix $p=\frac{1}{2}$ for definiteness. Let $L^<$ denote the first order language with predicates equality $(x=y)$, adjacency $(x\sim y)$ and less than $(x<y)$. For any sentence $A$ in $L^<$ let $f_A(n)$ denote the probability that the random $G_<(n,p)$ has property $A$. It is known Compton, Henson and Shelah [CHSh:245] that there are $A$ for which $f_A(n)$ does not converge. Here we show what is called a very weak zero-one law (from [Sh 463]): THEOREM: For every $A$ in language $L^<$, $\lim_{n\rightarrow\infty}(f_A(n+1)-f_A(n))=0.$
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt), (graph)
  523. Sh:549
    Fuchino, S., Koppelberg, S., & Shelah, S. (1996). Partial orderings with the weak Freese-Nation property. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 80(1), 35–54. arXiv: math/9508220 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(95)00047-X MR: 1395682
    type: article
    abstract: A partial ordering $P$ is said to have the weak Freese-Nation property (WFN) if there is a mapping $f:P\longrightarrow [P]^{\leq\aleph_0}$ such that, for any $a$, $b\in P$, if $a\leq b$ then there exists $c\in f(a)\cap f(b)$ such that $a\leq c\leq b$. In this note, we study the WFN and some of its generalizations. Some features of the class of BAs with the WFN seem to be quite sensitive to additional axioms of set theory: e.g., under CH, every ccc cBA has this property while, under ${\bf b}\geq\aleph_2$, there exists no cBA with the WFN.
    keywords: S: ico, (ba)
  524. Sh:551
    Shelah, S. (1996). In the random graph G(n,p), p=n^{-a}: if \psi has probability O(n^{-\epsilon}) for every \epsilon>0 then it has probability O(e^{-n^\epsilon}) for some \epsilon>0. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 82(1), 97–102. arXiv: math/9512228 DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(95)00071-2 MR: 1416640
    type: article
    abstract: Shelah Spencer [ShSp:304] proved the $0-1$ law for the random graphs $G(n,p_n)$, $p_n=n^{-\alpha}$, $\alpha\in (0,1)$ irrational (set of nodes in $[n]=\{1,\ldots,n\}$, the edges are drawn independently, probability of edge is $p_n$). One may wonder what can we say on sentences $\psi$ for which Prob$(G(n,p_n)\models\psi)$ converge to zero, Lynch asked the question and did the analysis, getting (for every $\psi$): EITHER [$(\alpha)$] Prob$[G(n,p_n)\models\psi]=cn^{-\beta} + O(n^{-\beta-\varepsilon})$ for some $\varepsilon$ such that $\beta>\varepsilon>0$ OR [$(\beta)$] Prob$(G(n,p_n)\models\psi)= O(n^{-\varepsilon})$ for every $\varepsilon>0$. Lynch conjectured that in case $(\beta)$ we have [$(\beta^+)$] Prob$(G(n,p_n)\models\psi)= O(e^{-n^\varepsilon})$ for some $\varepsilon>0$. We prove it here.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  525. Sh:552
    Shelah, S. (1997). Non-existence of universals for classes like reduced torsion free abelian groups under embeddings which are not necessarily pure. In Advances in algebra and model theory (Essen, 1994; Dresden, 1995), Vol. 9, Gordon; Breach, Amsterdam, pp. 229–286. arXiv: math/9609217 MR: 1683540
    type: article
    abstract: We consider a class $K$ of structures e.g. trees with $\omega+1$ levels, metric spaces and mainly, classes of Abelian groups like the one mentioned in the title and the class of reduced separable (Abelian) $p$-groups. We say $M\in K$ is universal for $K$ if any member $N$ of $K$ of cardinality not bigger than the cardinality of $M$ can be embedded into $M$. This is a natural, often raised, problem. We try to draw consequences of cardinal arithmetic to non--existence of universal members for such natural classes.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (app(pcf)), (univ)
  526. Sh:553
    Shafir, O., & Shelah, S. (2000). More on entangled orders. J. Symbolic Logic, 65(4), 1823–1832. arXiv: math/9711220 DOI: 10.2307/2695077 MR: 1812182
    type: article
    abstract: This paper grew as a continuation of [Sh462] but in the present form it can serve as a motivation for it as well. We deal with the same notions, and use just one simple lemma from there. Originally entangledness was introduced in order to get narrow Boolean algebras and examples of the nonmultiplicativity of c.c-ness. These applications became marginal when the hope to extract new such objects or strong colourings were not materialized, but after the pcf constructions which made their debut in [Sh:g] it seems that this notion gained independence. Generally we aim at characterizing the existence strong and weak entangled orders in cardinal arithmetic terms. In [Sh462] necessary conditions were shown for strong entangledness which in a previous version was erroneously proved to be equivalent to plain entangledness. In section 1 we give a forcing counterexample to this equivalence and in section 2 we get those results for entangledness (certainly the most interesting case). In \S3 we get weaker results for positively entangledness, especially when supplemented with the existence of a separating point. An antipodal case is defined and completely characterized. Lastly we outline a forcing example showing that these two subcases of positive entangledness comprise no dichotomy.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set)
  527. Sh:554
    Goldstern, M., & Shelah, S. (1997). A partial order where all monotone maps are definable. Fund. Math., 152(3), 255–265. arXiv: math/9707202 MR: 1444716
    type: article
    abstract: We show the consistency of ``There is a p.o.\ of size continuum on which all monotone maps are first order definable''. The continuum can be $aleph_1$ or larger, and we may even have Martin's axiom.
    keywords: M: non, S: ico, (ua)
  528. Sh:556
    Fuchino, S., Koppelberg, S., & Shelah, S. (1996). A game on partial orderings. Topology Appl., 74(1-3), 141–148. arXiv: math/9505212 DOI: 10.1016/S0166-8641(96)00051-X MR: 1425933
    type: article
    abstract: We study the determinacy of the game $G_\kappa(A)$ introduced in [FKSh:549] for uncountable regular $\kappa$ and several classes of partial orderings $A$. Among trees or Boolean algebras, we can always find an $A$ such that $G_\kappa(A)$ is undetermined. For the class of linear orders, the existence of such $A$ depends on the size of $\kappa^{< \kappa}$. In particular we obtain a characterization of $\kappa^{< \kappa}=\kappa$ in terms of determinacy of the game $G_\kappa(L)$ for linear orders $L$.
    keywords: S: ico
  529. Sh:557
    Niedermeyer, F., Shelah, S., & Steffens, K. (2006). The f-factor problem for graphs and the hereditary property. Arch. Math. Logic, 45(6), 665–672. arXiv: math/0404179 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-006-0009-z MR: 2252248
    type: article
    abstract: If $P$ is a hereditary property then we show that, for the existence of a perfect $f$-factor, $P$ is a sufficient condition for countable graphs and yields a sufficient condition for graphs of size $\aleph_1$. Further we give two examples of a hereditary property which is even necessary for the existence of a perfect $f$-factor. We also discuss the $\aleph_2$-case.
    keywords: S: ico, (ba), (inf-log)
  530. Sh:558
    Geschke, S., & Shelah, S. (2008). The number of openly generated Boolean algebras. J. Symbolic Logic, 73(1), 151–164. arXiv: math/0702600 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1208358746 MR: 2387936
    type: article
    abstract: This article is devoted to two different generalizations of projective Boolean algebras: openly generated Boolean algebras and tightly $\sigma$-filtered Boolean algebras. We show that for every uncountable regular cardinal $\kappa$ there are $2^\kappa$ pairwise non-isomorphic openly generated Boolean algebras of size $\kappa>\aleph_1$ provided there is an almost free non-free abelian group of size $\kappa$. The openly generated Boolean algebras constructed here are almost free. Moreover, for every infinite regular cardinal $\kappa$ we construct $2^\kappa$ pairwise non-isomorphic Boolean algebras of size $\kappa$ that are tightly $\sigma$-filtered and c.c.c. These two results contrast nicely with Koppelberg's theorem hat for every uncountable regular cardinal $\kappa$ there are only $2^{<\kappa}$ isomorphism types of projective Boolean algebras of size $\kappa$.
    keywords: M: non, S: ico, (ba), (nni)
  531. Sh:559
    Eklof, P. C., & Shelah, S. (1996). New nonfree Whitehead groups by coloring. In Abelian groups and modules (Colorado Springs, CO, 1995), Vol. 182, Dekker, New York, pp. 15–22. MR: 1415620
    See [Sh:559a]

    type: article
    abstract: We show that it is consistent that there is a strongly $\aleph_{1}$-free $\aleph_{1}$-coseparable group of cardinality $\aleph_{1}$ which is not $\aleph_{1}$-separable.
    keywords: S: for, O: alg, (ab), (iter), (stal), (wh), (unif)
  532. Sh:560
    Laskowski, M. C., & Shelah, S. (2001). The Karp complexity of unstable classes. Arch. Math. Logic, 40(2), 69–88. arXiv: math/0011167 DOI: 10.1007/s001530000047 MR: 1816478
    type: article
    abstract: A class ${\bf K}$ of structures is controlled if, for all cardinals $\lambda$, the relation of $L_{\infty,\lambda}$-equivalence partitions ${\bf K}$ into a set of equivalence classes (as opposed to a proper class). We prove that the class of doubly transitive linear orders is controlled, while any pseudo-elementary class with the $\omega$-independence property is not controlled.
    keywords: M: cla, M: non, (mod), (inf-log)
  533. Sh:561
    Shelah, S., & Zapletal, J. (1997). Embeddings of Cohen algebras. Adv. Math., 126(2), 93–118. arXiv: math/9502230 DOI: 10.1006/aima.1996.1597 MR: 1442306
    type: article
    abstract: Complete Boolean algebras proved to be an important tool in topology and set theory. Two of the most prominent examples are $B(\kappa)$, the algebra of Borel sets modulo measure zero ideal in the generalized Cantor space $\{0,1\}^\kappa$ equipped with product measure, and $C(\kappa),$ the algebra of regular open sets in the space $\{0,1\}^\kappa$, for $\kappa$ an infinite cardinal. $C(\kappa)$ is much easier to analyse than $B(\kappa)$: $C(\kappa)$ has a dense subset of size $\kappa$, while the density of $B(\kappa)$ depends on the cardinal characteristics of the real line; and the definition of $C(\kappa)$ is simpler. Indeed, $C(\kappa)$ seems to have the simplest definition among all algebras of its size. In the Main Theorem of this paper we show that in a certain precise sense, $C(\aleph_1)$ has the simplest structure among all algebras of its size, too. MAIN THEOREM: If ZFC is consistent then so is ZFC + $2^{\aleph_0}=\aleph_2$ +``for every complete Boolean algebra $B$ of uniform density $\aleph_1$, $C(\aleph_1)$ is isomorphic to a complete subalgebra of $B$''.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (app(pcf))
  534. Sh:562
    Džamonja, M., & Shelah, S. (1995). On squares, outside guessing of clubs and I_{<f}[\lambda]. Fund. Math., 148(2), 165–198. arXiv: math/9510216 DOI: 10.4064/fm-148-2-165-198 MR: 1360144
    type: article
    abstract: Suppose that $\lambda=\mu^+$. We consider two aspects of the square property on subsets of $\lambda$. First, we have results which show e.g. that for $\aleph_0\le\kappa=cf (\kappa)< \mu$, the equality $cf([\mu]^{\le\kappa},\subseteq)=\mu$ is a sufficient condition for the set of elements of $\lambda$ whose cofinality is bounded by $\kappa$, to be split into the union of $\mu$ sets with squares. Secondly, we introduce a certain weak version of the square property and prove that if $\mu$ is a strong limit, then this weak square property holds on $\lambda$ without any additional assumptions
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  535. Sh:563
    Jin, R., & Shelah, S. (1997). Can a small forcing create Kurepa trees. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 85(1), 47–68. arXiv: math/9504220 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(96)00018-8 MR: 1443275
    type: article
    abstract: In the paper we probe the possibilities of creating a Kurepa tree in a generic extension of a model of CH plus no Kurepa trees by an $\omega_1$-preserving forcing notion of size at most $\omega_1$. In the first section we show that in the Levy model obtained by collapsing all cardinals between $\omega_1$ and a strongly inaccessible cardinal by forcing with a countable support Levy collapsing order many $\omega_1$-preserving forcing notions of size at most $\omega_1$ including all $\omega$-proper forcing notions and some proper but not $\omega$-proper forcing notions of size at most $\omega_1$ do not create Kurepa trees. In the second section we construct a model of CH plus no Kurepa trees, in which there is an $\omega$-distributive Aronszajn tree such that forcing with that Aronszajn tree does create a Kurepa tree in the generic extension. At the end of the paper we ask three questions.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (trees)
  536. Sh:564
    Shelah, S. (1996). Finite canonization. Comment. Math. Univ. Carolin., 37(3), 445–456. arXiv: math/9509229 MR: 1426909
    type: article
    abstract: The canonization theorem says that for given $m,n$ for some $m^*$ (the first one is called $ER(n;m)$) we have: for every function $f$ with domain $[{1,\ldots,m^*}]^n$, for some $A\in [{1,\ldots,m^*}]^m$, the question of when the equality $f({i_1,\ldots,i_n})=f({j_1,\ldots,j_n})$ (where $i_1<\ldots<i_n$ and $j_1 <\ldots< j_n$ are from $A$) holds has the simplest answer: for some $v \subseteq \{1,\ldots,n\}$ the equality holds iff $(\forall\ell\in v)(i_\ell = j_\ell)$. In this paper we improve the bound on $ER(n,m)$ so that fixing $n$ the number of exponentiation needed to calculate $ER(n,m)$ is best possible.
    keywords: O: fin, (pc), (fc)
  537. Sh:565
    Jech, T. J., & Shelah, S. (1996). On countably closed complete Boolean algebras. J. Symbolic Logic, 61(4), 1380–1386. arXiv: math/9502203 DOI: 10.2307/2275822 MR: 1456113
    type: article
    abstract: It is unprovable that every complete subalgebra of a countably closed complete Boolean algebra is countably closed.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (ba), (pure(for))
  538. Sh:566
    Jech, T. J., & Shelah, S. (1996). A complete Boolean algebra that has no proper atomless complete subalgebra. J. Algebra, 182(3), 748–755. arXiv: math/9501206 DOI: 10.1006/jabr.1996.0199 MR: 1398120
    type: article
    abstract: There exists a complete atomless Boolean algebra that has no proper atomless complete subalgebra.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (ba), (pure(for))
  539. Sh:567
    Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (1998). DOP and FCP in generic structures. J. Symbolic Logic, 63(2), 427–438. arXiv: math/9607228 DOI: 10.2307/2586841 MR: 1625876
    type: article
    abstract: Spencer and Shelah [ShSp:304] constructed for each irrational $\alpha$ between $0$ and $1$ the theory $T^\alpha$ as the almost sure theory of random graphs with edge probability $n^{-\alpha}$. In [BlSh:528] we proved that this was the same theory as the theory $T_\alpha$ built by constructing a generic model in Baldwin and Shi. In this paper we explore some of the more subtle model theoretic properties of this theory. We show that $T^\alpha$ has the dimensional order property and does not have the finite cover property.
    keywords: M: cla, O: fin, (mod), (fmt), (sta)
  540. Sh:568
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2001). Some nasty reflexive groups. Math. Z., 237(3), 547–559. arXiv: math/0003164 DOI: 10.1007/PL00004879 MR: 1845337
    type: article
    abstract: In {\it Almost Free Modules, Set-theoretic Methods}, p. 455, Problem 12, Eklof and Mekler raised the question about the existence of dual abelian groups $G$ which are not isomorphic to ${\mathbb Z} \oplus G$. Recall that $G$ is a dual group if $G \cong D^*$ for some group $D$ with $D^*={\rm Hom}(D,{\mathbb Z})$. The existence of such groups is not obvious because dual groups are subgroups of cartesian products ${\mathbb Z}^D$ and therefore have very many homomorphisms into ${\mathbb Z}$. If $\pi$ is such a homomorphism arising from a projection of the cartesian product, then $D^*\cong{\rm ker}\pi \oplus {\mathbb Z}$. In all ``classical cases'' of groups $D$ of infinite rank it turns out that $D^*\cong{\rm ker}\pi$. Is this always the case? Also note that reflexive groups $G$ in the sense of H.~Bass are dual groups because by definition the evaluation map $\sigma:G\longrightarrow G^{**}$ is an isomorphism, hence $G$ is the dual of $G^*$. Assuming the diamond axiom for $\aleph_1$ we will construct a reflexive torsion-free abelian group of cardinality $\aleph_1$ which is not isomorphic to ${\mathbb Z}\oplus G$. The result is formulated for modules over countable principal ideal domains which are not field.
    keywords: M: non, (ab)
  541. Sh:569
    Shami, Z., & Shelah, S. (1999). Rigid \aleph_\epsilon-saturated models of superstable theories. Fund. Math., 162(1), 37–46. arXiv: math/9908158 MR: 1734816
    type: article
    abstract: We look naturally at models with: no two dimensions are equal, so if such a model is not rigid it has an automorphism (non trivial) then it maps every regular type to one not orthogonal to it; here comes the main point: if some $\aleph_\epsilon$ saturated model of $T$ has such an automorphism and NDOP then every one has an automorphism; by the analysis from [Sh 401] to be completed: this automorphism share this property, imitating [Sh-c X] also in other cardinlas there are rigid models even when teh model is not with all dimensions distinct (use levels of the tree decomposition); generally if $T$ has an $\aleph_\epsilon$ saturated rigid model then it is strongly deep (every type has depth infinity (enough has depth $>0$)) for them we have NDOP when one side comes from this type, then use a decomposion theorem with zero and two successors
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  542. Sh:570
    Baldwin, J. T., Grossberg, R. P., & Shelah, S. (1999). Transfering saturation, the finite cover property, and stability. J. Symbolic Logic, 64(2), 678–684. arXiv: math/9511205 DOI: 10.2307/2586492 MR: 1777778
    type: article
    abstract: Saturation is $(\mu,\kappa)$-transferable in $T$ if and only if there is an expansion $T_1$ of $T$ with $|T_1|=|T|$ such that if $M$ is a $\mu$-saturated model of $T_1$ and $|M|\geq\kappa$ then the reduct $M\restriction L(T)$ is $\kappa$-saturated. We characterize theories which are superstable without f.c.p., or without f.c.p. as, respectively those where saturation is $(\aleph_0,\lambda)$-transferable or $(\kappa(T),\lambda)$-transferable for all $\lambda$. Further if for some $\mu\geq |T|$, $2^\mu>\mu^+$, stability is equivalent to for all $\mu\geq |T|$, saturation is $(\mu,2^\mu)$-transferable.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (sta)
  543. Sh:571
    Cummings, J., Džamonja, M., & Shelah, S. (1995). A consistency result on weak reflection. Fund. Math., 148(1), 91–100. arXiv: math/9504221 DOI: 10.4064/fm-148-1-91-100 MR: 1354940
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper we study the notion of strong non-reflection, and its contrapositive weak reflection. We say $\theta$ strongly non-reflects at $\lambda$ iff there is a function $F:\theta\longrightarrow\lambda$ such that for all $\alpha<\theta$ with $cf(\alpha)=\lambda$ there is $C$ club in $\alpha$ such that $F\restriction C$ is strictly increasing. We prove that it is consistent to have a cardinal $\theta$ such that strong non-reflection and weak reflection each hold on an unbounded set of cardinals less than $\theta$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (large), (ref)
  544. Sh:572
    Shelah, S. (1997). Colouring and non-productivity of \aleph_2-c.c. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 84(2), 153–174. arXiv: math/9609218 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(96)00020-6 MR: 1437644
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that colouring of pairs from $\aleph_2$ with strong properties exists. The easiest to state (and quite a well known problem) it solves: there are two topological spaces with cellularity $\aleph_1$ whose product has cellularity $\aleph_2$; equivalently we can speak on cellularity of Boolean algebras or on Boolean algebras satisfying the $\aleph_2$-c.c. whose product fails the $\aleph_2$-c.c. We also deal more with guessing of clubs.
    keywords: S: ico, S: pcf, (set)
  545. Sh:573
    Lifsches, S., & Shelah, S. (1998). Uniformization and Skolem functions in the class of trees. J. Symbolic Logic, 63(1), 103–127. arXiv: math/9412231 DOI: 10.2307/2586591 MR: 1610786
    type: article
    abstract: The monadic second-order theory of trees allows quantification over elements and over arbitrary subsets. We classify the class of trees with respect to the question: does a tree T have definable Skolem functions (by a monadic formula with parameters)? This continues [LiSh539] where the question was asked only with respect to choice functions. Here we define a subclass of the class of tame trees (trees with a definable choice function) and prove that this is exactly the class (actually set) of trees with definable Skolem functions.
    keywords: M: odm, (mod), (mon)
  546. Sh:574
    Džamonja, M., & Shelah, S. (1999). Similar but not the same: various versions of \clubsuit do not coincide. J. Symbolic Logic, 64(1), 180–198. arXiv: math/9710215 DOI: 10.2307/2586758 MR: 1683902
    type: article
    abstract: We consider various versions of the $\clubsuit$ principle. This principle is a known consequence of $\diamondsuit$. It is well known that $\diamondsuit$ is not sensitive to minor changes in its definition, e.g. changing the guessing requirement form ``guessing exactly'' to ``guessing modulo a finite set''. We show however, that this is not true for $\clubsuit$. We consider some other variants of $\clubsuit$ as well.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter)
  547. Sh:575
    Shelah, S. (2000). Cellularity of free products of Boolean algebras (or topologies). Fund. Math., 166(1-2), 153–208. arXiv: math/9508221 MR: 1804709
    type: article
    abstract: We answer Problem 1 of Monk if there are Boolean algebras $B_1,B_2$ such that $c(B_i)\leq\lambda_i$ but $c(B_1\times B_2)> \lambda_1+\lambda_2$ where $\lambda_1=\mu$ is singular and $\mu>\lambda_2=\theta>cf(\mu)$
    keywords: S: ico, S: pcf, (set), (ba), (app(pcf))
  548. Sh:576
    Shelah, S. (2001). Categoricity of an abstract elementary class in two successive cardinals. Israel J. Math., 126, 29–128. arXiv: math/9805146 DOI: 10.1007/BF02784150 MR: 1882033
    type: article
    abstract: We investigate categoricity of abstract elementary classes without any remnants of compactness (like non-definability of well ordering, existence of E.M. models or existence of large cardinals). We prove (assuming a weak version of GCH around $\lambda$) that if $\mathfrak{K}$ is categorical in $\lambda,\lambda^+$, $LS(\mathfrak{K}) \le\lambda$ and $1\le I(\lambda^{++},\mathfrak{K})< 2^{\lambda^{++}}$ then $\mathfrak{K}$ has a model in $\lambda^{+++}$.
    keywords: M: nec, M: non, (mod), (nni), (cat), (wd)
  549. Sh:577
    Gitik, M., & Shelah, S. (1997). Less saturated ideals. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 125(5), 1523–1530. arXiv: math/9503203 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-97-03702-7 MR: 1363421
    type: article
    abstract: We prove the following: (1) If $\kappa$ is weakly inaccessible then $NS_\kappa$ is not $\kappa^+$-saturated. (2) If $\kappa$ is weakly inaccessible and $\theta<\kappa$ is regular then $NS^\theta_\kappa$ is not $\kappa^+$-saturated. (3) If $\kappa$ is singular then $NS^{cf(\kappa)}_{\kappa^+}$ is not $\kappa^{++}$-saturated. Combining this with previous results of Shelah, one obtains the following: (A) If $\kappa>\aleph_1$ then $NS_\kappa$ is not $\kappa^+$-saturated. (B) If $\theta^+<\kappa$ then $NS^\theta_\kappa$ is not $\kappa^+$-saturated.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (normal)
  550. Sh:578
    Milner, E. C., & Shelah, S. (1998). A tree-arrowing graph. In Set theory (Curaçao, 1995; Barcelona, 1996), Kluwer Acad. Publ., Dordrecht, pp. 175–182. arXiv: math/9708210 MR: 1602000
    type: article
    abstract: We answer a variant of a question of R\"odl and Voigt by showing that, for a given infinite cardinal $\lambda$, there is a graph $G$ of cardinality $\kappa=(2^\lambda)^+$ such that for any colouring of the edges of $G$ with $\lambda$ colours, there is an induced copy of the $\kappa$-tree in $G$ in the set theoretic sense with all edges having the same colour.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (pc), (graph)
  551. Sh:579
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (1996). GCH implies existence of many rigid almost free abelian groups. In Abelian groups and modules (Colorado Springs, CO, 1995), Vol. 182, Dekker, New York, pp. 253–271. arXiv: math/0011185 MR: 1415638
    type: article
    abstract: We begin with the existence of groups with trivial duals for cardinals $\aleph_n$ ($n\in \omega$). Then we derive results about strongly $\aleph_n$-free abelian groups of cardinality $\aleph_n$ ($n\in\omega$) with prescribed free, countable endomorphism ring. Finally we use combinatorial results of [Sh:108], [Sh:141] to give similar answers for cardinals $>\aleph_\omega$. As in Magidor and Shelah [MgSh:204], a paper concerned with the existence of $\kappa $-free, non-free abelian groups of cardinality $\kappa$, the induction argument breaks down at $\aleph_\omega$. Recall that $\aleph_\omega$ is the first singular cardinal and such groups of cardinality $\aleph_\omega$ do not exist by the well-known Singular Compactness Theorem (see [Sh:52]).
    keywords: M: non, (ab)
  552. Sh:580
    Shelah, S. (2000). Strong covering without squares. Fund. Math., 166(1-2), 87–107. arXiv: math/9604243 MR: 1804706
    type: article
    abstract: We continue [Sh:b, Ch XIII] and [Sh:410]. Let $W$ be an inner model of ZFC. Let $\kappa$ be a cardinal in $V$. We say that $\kappa$-covering holds between $V$ and $W$ iff for all $X\in V$ with $X\subseteq ON$ and $V\models|X|<\kappa$, there exists $Y\in W$ such that $X\subseteq Y\subseteq ON$ and $V\models |Y|<\kappa$. Strong $\kappa$-covering holds between $V$ and $W$ iff for every structure ${\mathcal M} \in V$ for some countable first-order language whose underlying set is some ordinal $\lambda$, and every $X \in V$ with $X\subseteq\lambda$ and $V\models |X|<\kappa$, there is $Y\in W$ such that $X\subseteq Y \prec M$ and $V\models |Y|<\kappa$. We prove that if $\kappa$ is $V$-regular, $\kappa^+_V=\kappa^+_W$, and we have both $\kappa$-covering and $\kappa^+$-covering between $W$ and $V$, then strong $\kappa$-covering holds. Next we show that we can drop the assumption of $\kappa^+$-covering at the expense of assuming some more absoluteness of cardinals and cofinalities between $W$ and $V$, and that we can drop the assumption that $\kappa^+_W =\kappa^+_V$ and weaken the $\kappa^+$-covering assumption at the expense of assuming some structural facts about $W$ (the existence of certain square sequences).
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  553. Sh:582
    Gitik, M., & Shelah, S. (2001). More on real-valued measurable cardinals and forcing with ideals. Israel J. Math., 124, 221–242. arXiv: math/9507208 DOI: 10.1007/BF02772619 MR: 1856516
    type: article
    abstract: (1) It is shown that if $c$ is real-valued measurable then the Maharam type of $(c, {\mathcal P}(c),\sigma)$ is $2^c$. This answers a question of D. Fremlin. (2) A different construction of a model with a real-valued measurable cardinal is given from that of R. Solovay. This answers a question of D. Fremlin. (3) The forcing with a $\kappa$-complete ideal over a set $X$, $|X|\geq\kappa$ cannot be isomorphic to Random$\times$Cohen or Cohen$\times$Random. The result for $X=\kappa$ was proved in [GiSh:357] but as was pointed out to us by M. Burke the application of it in [GiSh:412] requires dealing with any $X$.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (leb), (meag)
  554. Sh:583
    Gilchrist, M., & Shelah, S. (1997). The consistency of ZFC + 2^{\aleph_0}>\aleph_\omega+\mathcal I(\aleph_2)=\mathcal I(\aleph_\omega). J. Symbolic Logic, 62(4), 1151–1160. arXiv: math/9603219 DOI: 10.2307/2275632 MR: 1617993
    type: article
    abstract: An $\omega$-coloring is a pair $\langle f,B\rangle$ where $f:[B]^{2}\longrightarrow\omega$. The set $B$ is the field of $f$ and denoted $Fld(f)$. Let $f,g$ be $\omega$-colorings. We say that $f$ realizes the coloring $g$ if there is a one-one function $k:Fld(g)\longrightarrow Fld(f)$ such that for all $\{x,y\}$, $\{u,v\}\in dom(g)$ we have $f(\{k(x),k(y)\})\neq f(\{k(u),k(v)\}) \Rightarrow g(\{x,y\})\neq g(\{u,v\})$. We write $f\sim g$ if $f$ realizes $g$ and $g$ realizes $f$. We call the $\sim$-classes of $\omega$-colorings with finite fields identities. We say that an identity $I$ is of size $r$ if $|Fld(f)|=r$ for some/all $f\in I$. For a cardinal $\kappa$ and $f:[\kappa]^2\longrightarrow\omega$ we define ${\mathcal I}(f)$ to be the collection of identities realized by $f$ and ${\mathcal I }(\kappa)$ to be $\bigcap\{{\mathcal I}(f)| f:[\kappa]^2\longrightarrow\omega\}$. We show that, if ZFC is consistent then ZFC + $2^{\aleph_0}>\aleph_\omega + {\mathcal I}(\aleph_2)={\mathcal I}(\aleph_\omega)$ is consistent.
    keywords: S: for, (set-mod)
  555. Sh:584
    Saxl, J., Shelah, S., & Thomas, R., Simon. (1996). Infinite products of finite simple groups. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 348(11), 4611–4641. arXiv: math/9605202 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-96-01746-1 MR: 1376555
    type: article
    abstract: We classify the sequences $\langle S_{n}: n\in N\rangle$ of finite simple nonabelian groups such that $\prod_n S_n$ has uncountable cofinality.
    keywords: O: alg, (stal), (auto)
  556. Sh:585
    Rabus, M., & Shelah, S. (2000). Covering a function on the plane by two continuous functions on an uncountable square—the consistency. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 103(1-3), 229–240. arXiv: math/9706223 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(98)00053-0 MR: 1756147
    type: article
    abstract: It is consistent that for every function $f:{\mathbb R}\times {\mathbb R}\rightarrow {\mathbb R}$ there is an uncountable set $A\subseteq {\mathbb R}$ and two continuous functions $f_0,f_1:D(A)\rightarrow {\mathbb R}$ such that $f(\alpha,\beta)\in \{f_0(\alpha,\beta),f_1(\alpha,\beta)\}$ for every $(\alpha,\beta) \in A^2$, $\alpha\not =\beta$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (meag)
  557. Sh:586
    Shelah, S. (1998). A polarized partition relation and failure of GCH at singular strong limit. Fund. Math., 155(2), 153–160. arXiv: math/9706224 MR: 1606515
    type: article
    abstract: The main result is that for $\lambda$ strong limit singular failing the continuum hypothesis (i.e. $2^\lambda> \lambda^+$), a polarized partition theorem holds.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (pc), (app(pcf))
  558. Sh:587
    Shelah, S. (2003). Not collapsing cardinals \leq\kappa in (<\kappa)-support iterations. Israel J. Math., 136, 29–115. arXiv: math/9707225 DOI: 10.1007/BF02807192 MR: 1998104
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with the problem of preserving various versions of completeness in $(<\kappa)$--support iterations of forcing notions, generalizing the case ``$S$--complete proper is preserved by CS iterations for a stationary co-stationary $S\subseteq\omega_1$''. We give applications to Uniformization and the Whitehead problem. In particular, for a strongly inaccessible cardinal $\kappa$ and a stationary set $S\subseteq\kappa$ with fat complement we can have uniformization for $\langle A_\delta:\delta\in S'\rangle$, $A_\delta \subseteq\delta=\sup A_\delta$, $cf(\delta)=otp(A_\delta)$ and a stationary non-reflecting set $S'\subseteq S$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (unif)
  559. Sh:588
    Shelah, S. (2013). Large weight does not yield an irreducible base. Period. Math. Hungar., 66(2), 131–137. arXiv: 1007.2693 DOI: 10.1007/s10998-013-1031-7 MR: 3090811
    type: article
    abstract: Answering a question of Juh\'asz, Soukup and Szentmikl\'ossy we show that it is consistent that some first countable space of uncountable weight does not contain an uncountable subspace which has an irreducible base.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (pc)
  560. Sh:589
    Shelah, S. (2000). Applications of PCF theory. J. Symbolic Logic, 65(4), 1624–1674. arXiv: math/9804155 DOI: 10.2307/2695067 MR: 1812172
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with several pcf problems; we characterize another version of exponentiation: number of $\kappa$-branches in a tree with $\lambda$ nodes, deal with existence of independent sets in stable theories, possible cardinality of ultraproduct, the depth of ultraproducts of Boolean Algebras. Also we give cardinal invariant for each $\lambda$ with pcf restriction and investigate further $T_D(f)$.
    keywords: S: pcf, (set), (ba), (app(pcf)), (up)
  561. Sh:590
    Shelah, S. (2000). On a problem of Steve Kalikow. Fund. Math., 166(1-2), 137–151. arXiv: math/9705226 MR: 1804708
    type: article
    abstract: The Kalikow problem for a pair $(\lambda,\kappa)$ of cardinal numbers, $\lambda >\kappa$ (in particular $\kappa=2$) is whether we can map the family of $\omega$--sequences from $\lambda$ to the family of $\omega$--sequences from $\kappa$ in a very continuous manner. Namely, we demand that for $\eta,\nu\in\lambda^\omega$ we have: $\eta,\nu$ are almost equal if and only if their images are. We show consistency of the negative answer e.g. for $\aleph_\omega$ but we prove it for smaller cardinals. We indicate a close connection with the free subset property and its variants.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (cont), (large)
  562. Sh:591
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (1998). Indecomposable almost free modules—the local case. Canad. J. Math., 50(4), 719–738. arXiv: math/0011182 DOI: 10.4153/CJM-1998-039-7 MR: 1638607
    type: article
    abstract: Let $R$ be a countable, principal ideal domain which is not a field and $A$ be a countable $R$-algebra which is free as an $R$-module. Then we will construct an $\aleph_1$-free $R$-module $G$ of rank $\aleph_1$ with endomorphism algebra End$_RG=A$. Clearly the result does not hold for fields. Recall that an $R$-module is $\aleph_1$-free if all its countable submodules are free, a condition closely related to Pontryagin's theorem. This result has many consequences, depending on the algebra $A$ in use. For instance, if we choose $A=R$, then clearly $G$ is an indecomposable `almost free' module. The existence of such modules was unknown for rings with only finitely many primes like $R={\mathbb Z}_{(p)}$, the integers localized at some prime $p$. The result complements a classical realization theorem of Corner's showing that any such algebra is an endomorphism algebra of some torsion-free, reduced $R$-module $G$ of countable rank. Its proof is based on new combinatorial-algebraic techniques related with what we call rigid tree-elements coming from a module generated over a forest of trees.
    keywords: M: non, (ab), (af)
  563. Sh:592
    Shelah, S. (2000). Covering of the null ideal may have countable cofinality. Fund. Math., 166(1-2), 109–136. arXiv: math/9810181 MR: 1804707
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that it is consistent that the covering of the ideal of measure zero sets has countable cofinality.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (leb), (inv), (pure(for))
  564. Sh:593
    Fuchino, S., Mildenberger, H., Shelah, S., & Vojtáš, P. (1999). On absolutely divergent series. Fund. Math., 160(3), 255–268. arXiv: math/9903114 MR: 1708990
    type: article
    abstract: We show that in the $\aleph_2$-stage countable support iteration of Mathias forcing over a model of CH the complete Boolean algebra generated by absolutely divergent series under eventual dominance is not isomorphic to the completion of $P(\omega)/$fin. This complements Vojtas' result, that under $cf(c)=p$ the two algebras are isomorphic.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (inv)
  565. Sh:594
    Shelah, S. (1998). There may be no nowhere dense ultrafilter. In Logic Colloquium ’95 (Haifa), Vol. 11, Springer, Berlin, pp. 305–324. arXiv: math/9611221 DOI: 10.1007/978-3-662-22108-2_17 MR: 1690694
    type: article
    abstract: We show the consistency of ZFC + "there is no NWD-ultrafilter on $\omega$", which means: for every non principle ultrafilter $D$ on the set of natural numbers, there is a function $f$ from the set of natural numbers to the reals, such that for some nowhere dense set $A$ of reals, the set $\{n: f(n)\in A\}$ is not in $D$. This answers a question of van Douwen, which was put in more general context by Baumgartner
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  566. Sh:595
    Shelah, S. (2000). Embedding Cohen algebras using pcf theory. Fund. Math., 166(1-2), 83–86. arXiv: math/9508201 MR: 1804705
    type: article
    abstract: Using a theorem from pcf theory, we show that for any singular cardinal $\nu$, the product of the Cohen forcing notions on $\kappa$, $\kappa<\nu$ adds a generic for the Cohen forcing notion on $\nu^+$. This solves Problem 5.1 in Miller's list (attributed to Rene David and Sy Friedman).
    keywords: S: pcf, (set), (app(pcf)), (pure(for))
  567. Sh:596
    Cummings, J., & Shelah, S. (1999). Some independence results on reflection. J. London Math. Soc. (2), 59(1), 37–49. arXiv: math/9703219 DOI: 10.1112/S0024610798006863 MR: 1688487
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that there is a certain degree of independence between stationary reflection phenomena at different cofinalities; e.g. it is consistent that every stationary subset of $S_1^3$ reflects at a point of cofinality $\aleph_2$ while every stationary subset of $S^3_0$ has a non-reflecting stationary subset
    keywords: S: for, (set), (large), (ref)
  568. Sh:597
    Gitik, M., & Shelah, S. (1998). On densities of box products. Topology Appl., 88(3), 219–237. arXiv: math/9603206 DOI: 10.1016/S0166-8641(97)00176-4 MR: 1632081
    type: article
    abstract: We construct two universes $V_1, V_2$ satisfying the following: GCH below $\aleph_\omega$, $2^{\aleph_\omega}=\aleph_{\omega+2}$ and the topological density of the space ${}^{\aleph_\omega} 2$ with $\aleph_0$ box product topology $d_{<\aleph_1}(\aleph_\omega)$ is $\aleph_{\omega+1}$ in $V_1$ and $\aleph_{\omega+2}$ in $V_2$. Further related results are discussed as well.
    keywords: S: for, S: pcf, (set), (large)
  569. Sh:598
    Abraham, U., & Shelah, S. (2004). Ladder gaps over stationary sets. J. Symbolic Logic, 69(2), 518–532. arXiv: math/0404151 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1082418541 MR: 2058187
    type: article
    abstract: For a stationary set $S\subseteq \omega_1$ and a ladder system $C$ over $S$, a new type of gaps called $C$-Hausdorff is introduced and investigated. We describe a forcing model of ZFC in which, for some stationary set $S$, for every ladder $C$ over $S$, every gap contains a subgap that is $C$-Hausdorff. But for every ladder $E$ over $\omega_1\setminus S$ there exists a gap with no subgap that is $E$-Hausdorff. A new type of chain condition, called polarized chain condition, is introduced. We prove that the iteration with finite support of polarized c.c.c posets is again a polarized c.c.c poset.
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  570. Sh:599
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2000). More on cardinal invariants of Boolean algebras. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 103(1-3), 1–37. arXiv: math/9808056 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(98)00066-9 MR: 1756140
    type: article
    abstract: We address several questions of Donald Monk related to irredundance and spread of Boolean algebras, gaining both some ZFC knowledge and consistency results. We show in ZFC that $irr(B_0\times B_1)=\max\{irr(B_0),irr(B_1)\}$. We prove consistency of the statement ``there is a Boolean algebra $B$ such that $irr(B)< s(B\otimes B)$'' and we force a superatomic Boolean algebra $B_*$ such that $s(B_*)=inc(B_*)=\kappa$, $irr(B_*)=Id(B_*)=\kappa^+$ and $Sub(B_*)=2^{\kappa^+}$. Next we force a superatomic algebra $B_0$ such that $irr(B_0)< inc(B_0)$ and a superatomic algebra $B_1$ such that $t(B_1)> {\rm Aut}(B_1)$. Finally we show that consistently there is a Boolean algebra $B$ of size $\lambda$ such that there is no free sequence in $B$ of length $\lambda$, there is an ultrafilter of tightness $\lambda$ (so $t(B)=\lambda$) and $\lambda\notin{\rm Depth}_{\rm Hs}(B)$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (inv(ba))
  571. Sh:601
    Kuhlmann, F.-V., Kuhlmann, S., & Shelah, S. (1997). Exponentiation in power series fields. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 125(11), 3177–3183. arXiv: math/9608214 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-97-03964-6 MR: 1402868
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that for no nontrivial ordered abelian group $G$, the ordered power series field $R((G))$ admits an exponential, i.e. an isomorphism between its ordered additive group and its ordered multiplicative group of positive elements, but that there is a non-surjective logarithm. For an arbitrary ordered field $k$, no exponential on $k((G))$ is compatible, that is, induces an exponential on $k$ through the residue map. This is proved by showing that certain functional equations for lexicographic powers of ordered sets are not solvable.
    keywords: S: ico, (stal)
  572. Sh:602
    Hyttinen, T., & Shelah, S. (1999). Constructing strongly equivalent nonisomorphic models for unsuperstable theories. Part C. J. Symbolic Logic, 64(2), 634–642. arXiv: math/9709229 DOI: 10.2307/2586489 MR: 1777775
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper we prove a strong nonstructure theorem for $\kappa(T)$-saturated models of a stable theory $T$ with dop.
    keywords: M: non, (mod)
  573. Sh:603
    Shelah, S. (2002). Few non minimal types on non structure. In In the Scope of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science . Volume One of the 11th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Cracow, August 1999, Vol. 1, Springer Netherlands, pp. 29–53. arXiv: math/9906023
    type: article
    abstract: We pay two debts from [Sh:576]. The main demands little knowledge from [Sh:576], just quoting a model theoretic consequence of the weak diamond. We assume that $\mathfrak{K}$ has amalgamation in $\lambda$, and that the minimal types are not dense to get many non-isomorphic models in $\lambda^+$. For this also pcf considerations are relevant. The minor debt was the use in one point of [Sh:576] of $\lambda \ne \aleph_0$, it is minor as for this case by [Sh:88] we ``usually'' know more.
    keywords: M: nec, (nni), (app(pcf)), (set-mod)
  574. Sh:604
    Shelah, S. (2005). The pair (\aleph_n,\aleph_0) may fail \aleph_0-compactness. In Logic Colloquium ’01, Vol. 20, Assoc. Symbol. Logic, Urbana, IL, pp. 402–433. arXiv: math/0404240 MR: 2143906
    type: article
    abstract: Let $P$ be a distinguished unary predicate and $K=\{M:$ $M$ a model of cardinality $\aleph_n$ with $P^M$ of cardinality $\aleph_0\}$. We prove that consistently for $n=4$, for some countable first order theory $T$ we have: $T$ has no model in $K$ whereas every finite subset of $T$ has a model in $K$. We then show how we prove it also for $n=2$, too.
    keywords: S: for, (set-mod)
  575. Sh:605
    Shelah, S., & Truss, J. K. (1999). On distinguishing quotients of symmetric groups. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 97(1-3), 47–83. arXiv: math/9805147 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(98)00023-2 MR: 1682068
    type: article
    abstract: A study is carried out of the elementary theory of quotients of symmetric groups in a similar spirit to [Sh:24]. Apart from the trivial and alternating subgroups, the normal subgroups of the full symmetric group $S(\mu)$ on an infinite cardinal $\mu$ are all of the form $S_\kappa(\mu)=$ the subgroup consisting of elements whose support has cardinality $<\kappa$ for some $\kappa\le\mu^+$. A many-sorted structure ${\mathcal M}_{\kappa\lambda\mu}$ is defined which, it is shown, encapsulates the first order properties of the group $S_\lambda(\mu)/S_\kappa(\mu)$. Specifically, these two structures are (uniformly) bi-interpretable, where the interpretation of ${\mathcal M}_{\kappa\lambda\mu}$ in $S_\lambda(\mu)/S_\kappa(\mu)$ is in the usual sense, but in the other direction is in a weaker sense, which is nevertheless sufficient to transfer elementary equivalence. By considering separately the cases $cf(\kappa) > 2^{\aleph_0}, cf(\kappa)\le 2^{\aleph_0}<\kappa, \aleph_0<\kappa< 2^{\aleph_0}$, and $\kappa = \aleph_0$, we make a further analysis of the first order theory of $S_\lambda(\mu)/S_\kappa(\mu)$, introducing many-sorted second order structures ${\mathcal N}^2_{\kappa \lambda \mu}$, all of whose sorts have cardinality at most $2^{\aleph_0}$.
    keywords: O: alg, (mod)
  576. Sh:606
    Shelah, S. (1999). On T_3-topological space omitting many cardinals. Period. Math. Hungar., 38(1-2), 87–98. arXiv: math/9811177 DOI: 10.1023/A:1004707417470 MR: 1721480
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that for every (infinite cardinal) $\lambda$ there is a $T_3$-space $X$ with clopen basis, $2^\mu$ points where $\mu = 2^\lambda$, such that every closed subspace of cardinality $<|X|$ has cardinality $<\lambda$.
    keywords: S: ico, (gt)
  577. Sh:607
    Bartoszyński, T., & Shelah, S. (2001). Strongly meager sets do not form an ideal. J. Math. Log., 1(1), 1–34. arXiv: math/9805148 DOI: 10.1142/S0219061301000028 MR: 1838340
    type: article
    abstract: A set $X \subseteq {\bf R}$ is strongly meager if for every measure zero set $H$, $X+H \neq {\bf R}$. Let SM denote the collection of strongly meager sets. We show that assuming CH, SM is not an ideal.
    keywords: S: str, (set)
  578. Sh:608
    Shelah, S., & Stanley, L. J. (2001). Forcing many positive polarized partition relations between a cardinal and its powerset. J. Symbolic Logic, 66(3), 1359–1370. arXiv: math/9710216 DOI: 10.2307/2695112 MR: 1856747
    type: article
    abstract: Corrected in [918]. We present a forcing for blowing up $2^\lambda$ and making ``many positive polarized partition relations'' (in a sense made precise in (c) of our main theorem) hold in the interval $[\lambda,\ 2^\lambda]$. This generalizes results of [276], Section 1, and the forcing is a \lq\lq many cardinals'' version of the forcing there.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (pc)
  579. Sh:609
    Kojman, M., & Shelah, S. (1998). A ZFC Dowker space in \aleph_{\omega+1}: an application of PCF theory to topology. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 126(8), 2459–2465. arXiv: math/9512202 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-98-04884-9 MR: 1605988
    type: article
    abstract: A Dowker space is a normal Hausdorff topological space whose product with the unit interval is not normal. Using pcf theory we construct a Dowker space of cardinality $\aleph_{\omega+1}$.
    keywords: S: pcf, O: top, (gt), (app(pcf))
  580. Sh:610
    Shelah, S., & Zapletal, J. (1999). Canonical models for \aleph_1-combinatorics. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 98(1-3), 217–259. arXiv: math/9806166 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(98)00022-0 MR: 1696852
    type: article
    abstract: We define the property of $\Pi_2$-compactness of a statement $\phi$ of set theory, meaning roughly that the hard core of the impact of $\phi$ on combinatorics of $\aleph_1$ can be isolated in a canonical model for the statement $\phi$. We show that the following statements are $\Pi_2$-compact: ``dominating number$=\aleph_1,$'' ``cofinality of the meager ideal$=\aleph_1$'', ``cofinality of the null ideal$=\aleph_1$'', existence of various types of Souslin trees and variations on uniformity of measure and category $=\aleph_1$. Several important new metamathematical patterns among classical statements of set theory are pointed out.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, S: dst, (set)
  581. Sh:611
    Rosen, E., Shelah, S., & Weinstein, S. (1997). k-universal finite graphs. In Logic and random structures (New Brunswick, NJ, 1995), Vol. 33, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, pp. 65–77. arXiv: math/9604244 MR: 1465469
    type: article
    abstract: This paper investigates the class of $k$-universal finite graphs, a local analog of the class of universal graphs, which arises naturally in the study of finite variable logics. The main results of the paper, which are due to Shelah, establish that the class of $k$-universal graphs is not definable by an infinite disjunction of first-order existential sentences with a finite number of variables and that there exist $k$-universal graphs with no $k$-extendible induced subgraphs.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt), (graph), (univ)
  582. Sh:612
    Juhász, I., & Shelah, S. (1998). On the cardinality and weight spectra of compact spaces. II. Fund. Math., 155(1), 91–94. arXiv: math/9703220 MR: 1487990
    type: article
    abstract: Let $B(\kappa,\lambda)$ be the subalgebra of ${\mathcal P}(\kappa)$ generated by $[\kappa]^{\le\lambda}$. It is shown that if $B$ is any homomorphic image of $B(\kappa,\lambda)$ then either $|B|< 2^\lambda$ or $|B|=|B|^\lambda$, moreover if $X$ is the Stone space of $B$ then either $|X|\le 2^{2^\lambda}$ or $|X|=|B|=|B|^\lambda$. This implies the existence of 0-dimensional compact $T_2$ spaces whose cardinality and weight spectra omit lots of singular cardinals of ``small'' cofinality.
    keywords: S: ico, (gt)
  583. Sh:613
    Jin, R., & Shelah, S. (1998). Compactness of Loeb spaces. J. Symbolic Logic, 63(4), 1371–1392. arXiv: math/9604211 DOI: 10.2307/2586655 MR: 1665731
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper we show that the compactness of a Loeb space depends on its cardinality, the nonstandard universe it belongs to and the underlying model of set theory we live in. In \S 1 we prove that Loeb spaces are compact under various assumptions, and in \S 2 we prove that Loeb spaces are not compact under various other assumptions. The results in \S 1 and \S 2 give a quite complete answer to a question of D. Ross.
    keywords: M: odm
  584. Sh:614
    Džamonja, M., & Shelah, S. (2004). On the existence of universal models. Arch. Math. Logic, 43(7), 901–936. arXiv: math/9805149 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-004-0235-1 MR: 2096141
    type: article
    abstract: Suppose that $\lambda=\lambda^{<\lambda}\ge\aleph_0$, and we are considering a theory $T$. We give a criterion on $T$ which is sufficient for the consistent existence of $\lambda^{++}$ universal models of $T$ of size $\lambda^+$ for models of $T$ of size $\le\lambda^+$, and is meaningful when $2^{\lambda^+}>\lambda^{++}$. In fact, we work more generally with abstract elementary classes. The criterion for the consistent existence of universals applies to various well known theories, such as triangle-free graphs and simple theories. Having in mind possible aplpications in analysis, we further observe that for such $\lambda$, for any fixed $\mu>\lambda^+$ regular with $\mu=\mu^{\lambda^+}$, it is consistent that $2^\lambda=\mu$ and there is no normed vector space over ${\mathbb Q}$ of size $<\mu$ which is universal for normed vector spaces over ${\mathbb Q}$ of dimension $\lambda^+$ under the notion of embedding $h$ which specifies $(a,b)$ such that $\|h(x)\|/\|x\|\in (a,b)$ for all $x$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (univ)
  585. Sh:615
    Kuhlmann, F.-V., Kuhlmann, S., & Shelah, S. (2003). Functorial equations for lexicographic products. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 131(10), 2969–2976. arXiv: math/0107206 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-03-06830-8 MR: 1993201
    type: article
    abstract: We generalize the main result of [KKSh:601] concerning the convex embeddings of a chain $\Gamma$ in a lexicographic power $\Delta^\Gamma$. For a fixed nonempty chain $\Delta$, we derive necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of nonempty solutions $\Gamma$ to each of the lexicographic functional equations $(\Delta^\Gamma)^{\leq 0}\simeq \Gamma$, $(\Delta^\Gamma)\simeq \Gamma$, and $(\Delta^\Gamma)^{<0}\simeq\Gamma$.
    keywords: S: ico, (stal)
  586. Sh:616
    Bartoszyński, T., Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2000). After all, there are some inequalities which are provable in ZFC. J. Symbolic Logic, 65(2), 803–816. arXiv: math/9711222 DOI: 10.2307/2586571 MR: 1771087
    type: article
    abstract: We address ZFC inequalities between some cardinal invariants of the continuum, which turned to be true in spite of strong expectations given by [RoSh:470].
    keywords: S: ico, S: str, (set), (pure(for))
  587. Sh:617
    Eklof, P. C., Huisgen-Zimmermann, B., & Shelah, S. (1997). Torsion modules, lattices and p-points. Bull. London Math. Soc., 29(5), 547–555. arXiv: math/9703221 DOI: 10.1112/S0024609397003329 MR: 1458714
    type: article
    abstract: Answering a long-standing question in the theory of torsion modules, we show that weakly productively bounded domains are necessarily productively bounded. Moreover, we prove a twin result for the ideal lattice $L$ of a domain equating weak and strong global intersection conditions for families $(X_i)_{i\in I}$ of subsets of $L$ with the property that $\bigcap_{i\in I} A_i\ne 0$ whenever $A_i\in X_i$. Finally, we show that, for domains with Krull dimension (and countably generated extensions thereof), these lattice-theoretic conditions are equivalent to productive boundedness.
    keywords: O: top, (ab)
  588. Sh:618
    Hamkins, J. D., & Shelah, S. (1998). Superdestructibility: a dual to Laver’s indestructibility. J. Symbolic Logic, 63(2), 549–554. arXiv: math/9612227 DOI: 10.2307/2586848 MR: 1625927
    type: article
    abstract: After small forcing, any $<\kappa$-closed forcing will destroy the supercompactness, even the strong compactness, of $\kappa$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (pure(large))
  589. Sh:619
    Shelah, S. (2003). The null ideal restricted to some non-null set may be \aleph_1-saturated. Fund. Math., 179(2), 97–129. arXiv: math/9705213 DOI: 10.4064/fm179-2-1 MR: 2029228
    type: article
    abstract: Our main result is that possibly some non-null set of reals cannot be divided to uncountably many non-null sets. We deal also with a non-null set of reals, the graph of any function from it is null and deal with our iterations somewhat more generally.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (leb)
  590. Sh:620
    Shelah, S. (1999). Special subsets of ^{\mathrm{cf}(\mu)}\mu, Boolean algebras and Maharam measure algebras. Topology Appl., 99(2-3), 135–235. arXiv: math/9804156 DOI: 10.1016/S0166-8641(99)00138-8 MR: 1728851
    type: article
    abstract: The original theme of the paper is the existence proof of ``there is $\bar{\eta}=\langle\eta_\alpha:\alpha<\lambda\rangle$ which is a $(\lambda,J)$-sequence for $\bar{I}=\langle I_i:i< \delta\rangle$, a sequence of ideals. This can be thought of as in a generalization to Luzin sets and Sierpinski sets, but for the product $\prod_{i< \delta} Dom(I_i)$, the existence proofs are related to pcf . The second theme is when does a Boolean algebra $B$ has free caliber $\lambda$ (i.e. if $X\subseteq B$ and $|X|=\lambda$, then for some $Y\subseteq X$ with $|Y|=\lambda$ and $Y$ is independent). We consider it for $B$ being a Maharam measure algebra, or $B$ a (small) product of free Boolean algebras, and $\kappa$-cc Boolean algebras. A central case $\lambda= (\beth_\omega)^+$ or more generally, $\lambda=\mu^+$ for $\mu$ strong limit singular of ``small'' cofinality. A second one is $\mu=\mu^{<\kappa}<\lambda< 2^\mu$; the main case is $\lambda$ regular but we also have things to say on the singular case. Lastly, we deal with ultraproducts of Boolean algebras in relation to irr(-) and s(-) Length, etc.
    keywords: S: pcf, (set), (ba), (leb), (inv(ba))
  591. Sh:621
    Eklof, P. C., & Shelah, S. (2001). A non-reflexive Whitehead group. J. Pure Appl. Algebra, 156(2-3), 199–214. arXiv: math/9908157 DOI: 10.1016/S0022-4049(99)00152-8 MR: 1808823
    type: article
    abstract: It is proved, via an iterated forcing construction with finite support, that it is consistent that there is a strongly $\aleph_1$-free Whitehead group of cardinality $\aleph_1$ which is strongly non-reflexive. It is also proved consistent that there is a group $A$ satisfying Ext$(A, Z)$ is torsion and Hom$(A,Z)=0$.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  592. Sh:622
    Shelah, S. (2001). Non-existence of universal members in classes of abelian groups. J. Group Theory, 4(2), 169–191. arXiv: math/9808139 DOI: 10.1515/jgth.2001.014 MR: 1812323
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that if $\mu^+<\lambda=cf(\lambda)<\mu^{\aleph_0}$, then there is no universal reduced torsion free abelian group. Similarly if $\aleph_0<\lambda< 2^{\aleph_0}$. We also prove that if $2^{\aleph_0}<\mu^+<\lambda=cf(\lambda)< \mu^{\aleph_0}$, then there is no universal reduced separable abelian $p$-group in $\lambda$. (Note: both results fail if $\lambda = \lambda^{\aleph_0}$ or if $\lambda$ is strong limit, cf$(\mu)=\aleph_0<\mu$).
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (ab), (app(pcf)), (univ)
  593. Sh:623
    Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (2000). On the classifiability of cellular automata. Theoret. Comput. Sci., 230(1-2), 117–129. arXiv: math/9801152 DOI: 10.1016/S0304-3975(99)00042-0 MR: 1725633
    type: article
    abstract: Based on computer simulations Wolfram presented in several papers conjectured classifications of cellular automata into 4 types. He distinguishes the 4 classes of cellular automata by the evolution of the pattern generated by applying a cellular automaton to a finite input. Wolfram's qualitative classification is based on the examination of a large number of simulations. In addition to this classification based on the rate of growth, he conjectured a similar classification according to the eventual pattern. We consider here one formalization of his rate of growth suggestion. After completing our major results (based only on Wolfram's work), we investigated other contributions to the area and we report the relation of some them to our discoveries.
    keywords: O: fin
  594. Sh:624
    Shelah, S. (1999). On full Suslin trees. Colloq. Math., 79(1), 1–7. arXiv: math/9608215 DOI: 10.4064/cm-79-1-1-7 MR: 1665618
    type: article
    abstract: In this note we answer a question of Kunen (15.13 [Mi91]) showing that it is consistent that there are full Souslin trees
    keywords: S: for, (set), (trees)
  595. Sh:625
    Eklof, P. C., & Shelah, S. (1998). The Kaplansky test problems for \aleph_1-separable groups. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 126(7), 1901–1907. arXiv: math/9709230 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-98-04749-2 MR: 1485469
    type: article
    abstract: We answer a long-standing open question by proving in ordinary set theory, ZFC, that the Kaplansky test problems have negative answers for $\aleph_1$-separable abelian groups of cardinality $\aleph_1$. In fact, there is an $\aleph_1$-separable abelian group $M$ such that $M$ is isomorphic to $M\oplus M\oplus M$ but not to $M\oplus M$.
    keywords: M: non, (ab)
  596. Sh:626
    Jin, R., & Shelah, S. (1999). Possible size of an ultrapower of \omega. Arch. Math. Logic, 38(1), 61–77. arXiv: math/9801153 DOI: 10.1007/s001530050115 MR: 1667288
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\omega$ be the first infinite ordinal (or the set of all natural numbers) with the usual order $<$. In \S 1 we show that, assuming the consistency of a supercompact cardinal, there may exist an ultrapower of $\omega$, whose cardinality is (1) a singular strong limit cardinal, (2) a strongly inaccessible cardinal. This answers two questions in [CK], modulo the assumption of supercompactness. In \S 2 we construct several $\lambda$-Archimedean ultrapowers of $\omega$ under some large cardinal assumptions. For example, we show that, assuming the consistency of a measurable cardinal, there may exist a $\lambda$-Archimedean ultrapower of $\omega$ for some uncountable cardinal $\lambda$. This answers a question in [KS], modulo the assumption of measurability.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (up)
  597. Sh:627
    Shelah, S. (1998). Erdős and Rényi conjecture. J. Combin. Theory Ser. A, 82(2), 179–185. arXiv: math/9707226 DOI: 10.1006/jcta.1997.2845 MR: 1620869
    type: article
    abstract: Affirming a conjecture of Erd\"os and R\'enyi we prove that for any (real number) $c_1>0$ for some $c_2>0$, if a graph $G$ has no $c_1(\log n)$ nodes on which the graph is complete or edgeless (i.e. $G$ exemplifies $|G|\not\rightarrow (c_1\log n)^2_2$) then $G$ has at least $2^{c_2n}$ non-isomorphic (induced) subgraphs.
    keywords: O: fin, (nni), (graph), (fc)
  598. Sh:628
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (1997). Norms on possibilities. II. More ccc ideals on 2^\omega. J. Appl. Anal., 3(1), 103–127. arXiv: math/9703222 DOI: 10.1515/JAA.1997.103 MR: 1618851
    type: article
    abstract: We use the method of {\it norms on possibilities} to answer a question of Kunen and construct a ccc $\sigma$--ideal on $2^\omega$ with various closure properties and distinct from the ideal of null sets, the ideal of meager sets and their intersection.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (creatures)
  599. Sh:629
    Hyttinen, T., & Shelah, S. (2000). Strong splitting in stable homogeneous models. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 103(1-3), 201–228. arXiv: math/9911229 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(99)00044-5 MR: 1756146
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper we study elementary submodels of a stable homogeneous structure. We improve the independence relation defined in [Hy1]. We apply this to prove a structure theorem. We also solve a question from [Hy3]: We show that dop and sdop are essentially equivalent, where the negation of dop is a property used to get structure theorems and sdop implies nonstructure.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  600. Sh:630
    Shelah, S. (2004). Properness without elementaricity. J. Appl. Anal., 10(2), 169–289. arXiv: math/9712283 DOI: 10.1515/JAA.2004.169 MR: 2115943
    type: article
    abstract: We present reasons for developing a theory of forcing notions which satisfy the properness demand for countable models which are not necessarily elementary submodels of some $({\mathcal H}(\chi),\in)$. This leads to forcing notions which are ``reasonably" definable. We present two specific properties materializing this intuition: nep (non-elementary properness) and snep (Souslin non-elementary properness). For this we consider candidates (countable models to which the definition applies), and the older Souslin proper. A major theme here is ``preservation by iteration'', but we also show a dichotomy: if such forcing notions preserve the positiveness of the set of old reals for some naturally define c.c.c.\ ideals, then they preserve the positiveness of any old positive set. We also prove that (among such forcing notions) the only one commuting with Cohen is Cohen itself.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (iter)
  601. Sh:631
    Rabus, M., & Shelah, S. (1999). Topological density of ccc Boolean algebras—every cardinality occurs. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 127(9), 2573–2581. arXiv: math/9709231 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-99-04813-3 MR: 1486748
    type: article
    abstract: For every uncountable cardinal $\mu$ there is a ccc Boolean algebra whose topological density is $\mu$.
    keywords: S: ico, O: top, (set), (ba)
  602. Sh:632
    Hyttinen, T., & Shelah, S. (1998). On the number of elementary submodels of an unsuperstable homogeneous structure. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 44(3), 354–358. arXiv: math/9702228 DOI: 10.1002/malq.19980440307 MR: 1645490
    type: article
    abstract: We show that if $M$ is a stable unsuperstable homogeneous structure, then for most $\kappa< |M|$, the number of elementary submodels of $ M$ of power $\kappa$ is $2^\kappa$.
    keywords: M: cla, M: non, (mod), (nni)
  603. Sh:633
    Goldstern, M., & Shelah, S. (1998). Order polynomially complete lattices must be large. Algebra Universalis, 39(3-4), 197–209. arXiv: math/9707203 DOI: 10.1007/s000120050075 MR: 1636999
    type: article
    abstract: If $L$ is an order-polynomially complete lattice, then the cardinality of $L$ must be a strongly inaccessible cardinal
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, O: fin, (ua)
  604. Sh:634
    Shelah, S. (2000). Choiceless Polynomial Time Logic: Inability to express. In P. G. Clote & H. Schwichtenberg, eds., Computer Science Logic, 14th International Workshop, CSL 2000, Annual Conference of the EACSL, Fischbachau, Germany, August 21–26, 2000, Proceedings, Vol. 1862, Springer, pp. 72–125. arXiv: math/9807179
    type: article
    abstract: We prove for the logic CPTime (the logic from the title) a sufficient condition for two models to be equivalent for any set of sentences which is ``small'' (certainly any finite set ), parallel to the Ehrenfeucht Fra{\"i}ss{\'e} games. This enables us to show that sentences cannot express some properties in the logic CPTime and prove 0-1 laws for it.
    keywords: M: smt, O: fin, (fmt)
  605. Sh:635
    Shelah, S., & Villaveces, A. (1999). Toward categoricity for classes with no maximal models. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 97(1-3), 1–25. arXiv: math/9707227 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(98)00015-3 MR: 1682066
    type: article
    abstract: We provide here the first steps toward Classification Theory of Abstract Elementary Classes with no maximal models, plus some mild set theoretical assumptions, when the class is categorical in some $\lambda$ greater than its L\"owenheim-Skolem number. We study the degree to which amalgamation may be recovered, the behaviour of non $\mu$-splitting types. Most importantly, the existence of saturated models in a strong enough sense is proved, as a first step toward a complete solution to the Los Conjecture for these classes.
    keywords: M: nec, (mod), (cat)
  606. Sh:636
    Shelah, S. (1998). The lifting problem with the full ideal. J. Appl. Anal., 4(1), 1–17. arXiv: math/9712284 DOI: 10.1515/JAA.1998.1 MR: 1648938
    type: article
    abstract: We prove in ZFC that for $\mu\geq\aleph_2$ there is a $\sigma$--ideal $I$ on $\mu$ and a Boolean $\sigma$--subalgebra $B$ of the family of subsets of $\mu$ which includes $I$ such that the natural homomorphism from $B$ onto $B/I$ cannot be lifted.
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  607. Sh:639
    Shelah, S. (2000). On quantification with a finite universe. J. Symbolic Logic, 65(3), 1055–1075. arXiv: math/9809201 DOI: 10.2307/2586688 MR: 1791364
    type: article
    abstract: We consider a finite universe ${\mathcal U}$ (more exactly - a family $\mathfrak{U}$ of them). Can second order quantifier $Q_K$, where for each ${\mathcal U}$ this means quantifying over a family of $n(K)$-place relations closed under permuting ${\mathcal U}$. We define some natural orders and shed some light on the classification problem of those quantifiers.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  608. Sh:640
    Błaszczyk, A., & Shelah, S. (2001). Regular subalgebras of complete Boolean algebras. J. Symbolic Logic, 66(2), 792–800. arXiv: math/9712285 DOI: 10.2307/2695044 MR: 1833478
    type: article
    abstract: It is shown that there exists a complete, atomless, $\sigma$-centered Boolean algebra, which does not contain any regular countable subalgebra if and only if there exist a nowhere dense ultrafilter. Therefore the existence of such algebras is undecidable in ZFC.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (pure(for))
  609. Sh:641
    Shelah, S. (2001). Constructing Boolean algebras for cardinal invariants. Algebra Universalis, 45(4), 353–373. arXiv: math/9712286 DOI: 10.1007/s000120050219 MR: 1816973
    type: article
    abstract: We construct Boolean Algebras answering questions of Monk on cardinal invariants. The results are proved in ZFC (rather than giving consistency results). We deal with the existence of superatomic Boolean Algebras with ``few automorphisms", with entangled sequences of linear orders, and with semi-ZFC examples of the non-attainment of the spread (and hL, hd).
    keywords: S: ico, (ba), (app(pcf)), (auto), (linear order), (inv(ba))
  610. Sh:642
    Brendle, J., & Shelah, S. (1999). Ultrafilters on \omega—their ideals and their cardinal characteristics. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 351(7), 2643–2674. arXiv: math/9710217 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-99-02257-6 MR: 1686797
    type: article
    abstract: For a free ultrafilter $\mathcal U$ on $\omega$ we study several cardinal characteristics which describe part of the combinatorial structure of $\mathcal U$. We provide various consistency results; e.g. we show how to force simultaneously many characters and many $\pi$--characters. We also investigate two ideals on the Baire space $\omega^\omega$ naturally related to $\mathcal U$ and calculate cardinal coefficients of these ideals in terms of cardinal characteristics of the underlying ultrafilter.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (inv)
  611. Sh:643
    Shelah, S., & Spasojević, Z. (2002). Cardinal invariants \mathfrak b_\kappa and \mathfrak t_\kappa. Publ. Inst. Math. (Beograd) (N.S.), 72(86), 1–9. arXiv: math/0003141 DOI: 10.2298/PIM0272001S MR: 1997605
    type: article
    abstract: This paper studies cardinal invariants $\mathfrak{b}_\kappa$ and $\mathfrak{t}_\kappa$, the natural generalizations of the invariants $\mathfrak{b}$ and $\mathfrak{t}$ to a regular cardinal $\kappa$.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (iter)
  612. Sh:644
    Shelah, S., & Väisänen, P. (2000). On inverse \gamma-systems and the number of L_{\infty\lambda}-equivalent, non-isomorphic models for \lambda singular. J. Symbolic Logic, 65(1), 272–284. arXiv: math/9807181 DOI: 10.2307/2586536 MR: 1782119
    type: article
    abstract: Suppose $\lambda$ is a singular cardinal of uncountable cofinality $\kappa$. For a model $M$ of cardinality $\lambda$, let $No(M)$ denote the number of isomorphism types of models $N$ of cardinality $\lambda$ which are $L_{\infty\lambda}$-equivalent to $M$. In [Sh:189] inverse $\kappa$-systems $A$ of abelian groups and their certain kind of quotient limits $Gr(A)/Fact(A)$ were considered. It was proved that for every cardinal $\mu$ there exists an inverse $\kappa$-system $A$ such that $A$ consists of abelian groups having cardinality at most $\mu^\kappa$ and $card(Gr(A)/Fact(A))=\mu$. In [Sh:228] a strict connection between inverse $\kappa$-systems and possible values of $No$ was proved. In this paper we show: for every nonzero $\mu\leq\lambda^\kappa$ there is an inverse $\kappa$-system $A$ of abelian groups having cardinality $<\lambda$ such that $card(Gr(A)/Fact(A))= \mu$ (under the assumptions $2^\kappa<\lambda$ and $\theta^{<\kappa}<\lambda$ for all $\theta<\lambda$ when $\mu>\lambda$), with the obvious new consequence concerning the possible value of $No$. Specifically, the case $No(M)=\lambda$ is possible when $\theta^\kappa<\lambda$ for every $\theta<\lambda$.
    keywords: M: non, O: alg, (nni), (inf-log), (set-mod)
  613. Sh:645
    Komjáth, P., & Shelah, S. (2000). Two consistency results on set mappings. J. Symbolic Logic, 65(1), 333–338. arXiv: math/9807182 DOI: 10.2307/2586540 MR: 1782123
    type: article
    abstract: It is consistent that there is a set mapping from the four-tuples of $\omega_n$ into the finite subsets with no free subsets of size $t_n$ for some natural number $t_n$. For any $n<\omega$ it is consistent that there is a set mapping from the pairs of $\omega_n$ into the finite subsets with no infinite free sets.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set)
  614. Sh:646
    Shelah, S., & Väisänen, P. (2001). On the number of L_{\infty\omega_1}-equivalent non-isomorphic models. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 353(5), 1781–1817. arXiv: math/9908160 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-00-02604-0 MR: 1707477
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that if ZF is consistent then ZFC + GCH is consistent with the following statement: There is for every $k < \omega$ a model of cardinality $\aleph_1$ which is $L_{\infty,\omega_1}$-equivalent to exactly $k$ non-isomorphic models of cardinality $\aleph_1$. In order to get this result we introduce ladder systems and colourings different from the "standard" counterparts, and prove the following purely combinatorial result: For each prime number $p$ and positive integer $m$ it is consistent with $ZFC + GCH$ that there is a ``good'' ladder system having exactly $p^m$ pairwise nonequivalent colourings.
    keywords: M: non, (nni), (inf-log), (set-mod)
  615. Sh:647
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2000). Cotorsion theories and splitters. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 352(11), 5357–5379. arXiv: math/9910159 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-00-02475-2 MR: 1661246
    type: article
    abstract: Let $R$ be a subring of the rationals. We want to investigate self splitting $R$-modules $G$ that is ${\rm Ext}_R(G,G)=0$ holds and follow Schultz to call such modules splitters. Free modules and torsion-free cotorsion modules are classical examples for splitters. Are there others? Answering an open problem by Schultz we will show that there are more splitters, in fact we are able to prescribe their endomorphism $R$-algebras with a free $R$-module structure. As a byproduct we are able to answer a problem of Salce showing that all rational cotorsion theories have enough injectives and enough projectives.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  616. Sh:649
    Kojman, M., & Shelah, S. (1999). Regressive Ramsey numbers are Ackermannian. J. Combin. Theory Ser. A, 86(1), 177–181. arXiv: math/9805150 DOI: 10.1006/jcta.1998.2906 MR: 1682971
    type: article
    abstract: We give an elementary proof of the fact that regressive Ramsey numbers are Ackermannian. This fact was first proved by Kanamori and McAloon with mathematical logic techniques.
    keywords: O: fin, (pc), (fc)
  617. Sh:650
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2004). Uniquely transitive torsion-free abelian groups. In Rings, modules, algebras, and abelian groups, Vol. 236, Dekker, New York, pp. 271–290. arXiv: math/0404259 MR: 2050717
    type: article
    abstract: We will answer a question raised by Farjoun concerning the existence of torsion-free abelian groups $G$ such that for any ordered pair of pure elements there is a unique automorphism mapping the first element onto the second one. We will show the existence of many such groups in the constructible universe L.
    keywords: M: non, (ab)
  618. Sh:651
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2001). Forcing for hL and hd. Colloq. Math., 88(2), 273–310. arXiv: math/9808104 DOI: 10.4064/cm88-2-9 MR: 1852911
    type: article
    abstract: The present paper addresses the problem of attainment of the supremums in various equivalent definitions of hereditary density ${\rm hd}$ and hereditary Lindel\"of degree ${\rm hL}$ of Boolean algebras. We partially answer two problems of J.~Donald Monk, Problems 50, 54, showing consistency of different attainment behaviour and proving that (for the considered variants) this is the best result we can expect.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (ba), (inv(ba))
  619. Sh:652
    Shelah, S. (2002). More constructions for Boolean algebras. Arch. Math. Logic, 41(5), 401–441. arXiv: math/9605235 DOI: 10.1007/s001530100099 MR: 1918108
    type: article
    abstract: We address a number of problems on Boolean Algebras. For example, we construct, in ZFC, for any BA $B$, and cardinal $\kappa$ BAs $B_1,B_2$ extending $B$ such that the depth of the free product of $B_1,B_2$ over $B$ is strictly larger than the depths of $B_1$ and of $B_2$ than $\kappa$. We give a condition (for $\lambda$, $\mu$ and $\theta$) which implies that for some BA $A_\theta$ there are $B_1=B^1_{\lambda,\mu,\theta}$ and $B_2B^2_{\lambda,\mu,\theta}$ such that Depth$(B_t)\leq\mu$ and Depth$(B_1\oplus_{A_\theta} B_1) \geq \lambda$. We then investigate for a fixed $A$, the existence of such $B_1,B_2$ giving sufficient and necessary conditions, involving consistency results. Further we prove that e.g. if $B$ is a BA of cardinality $\lambda$, $\lambda\ge\mu$ and $\lambda,\mu$ are strong limit singular of the same cofinality, then $B$ has a homomorphic image of cardinality $\mu$ (and with $\mu$ ultrafilters). Next we show that for a BA $B$, if $d(B)^\kappa<|B|$ then ind$(B)>\kappa$ or Depth$(B)\geq\log(|B|)$. Finally we prove that if $\square_\lambda$ holds and $\lambda=\lambda^{\aleph_0}$ then for some BAs $B_n$, Depth$(B_n)\leq\lambda$ but for any uniform ultrafilter $D$ on $\omega$, $\prod_{n<\omega} B_n/D$ has depth $\ge\lambda^+$.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (ba), (app(pcf))
  620. Sh:653
    Ciesielski, K. C., & Shelah, S. (1999). A model with no magic set. J. Symbolic Logic, 64(4), 1467–1490. arXiv: math/9801154 DOI: 10.2307/2586790 MR: 1780064
    type: article
    abstract: We will prove that there exists a model of ZFC+``$\mathfrak{c}=\omega_2$'' in which every $M\subseteq R$ of cardinality less than continuum $\mathfrak{c}$ is meager, and such that for every $X\subseteq R$ of cardinality $\mathfrak{c}$ there exists a continuous function $f:R\to R$ with $f[X]=[0,1]$. In particular in this model there is no magic set, i.e., a set $M\subseteq R$ such that the equation $f[M]=g[M]$ implies $f=g$ for every continuous nowhere constant functions $f,g:R\to R$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (creatures)
  621. Sh:654
    Just, W., Shelah, S., & Thomas, R., Simon. (1999). The automorphism tower problem revisited. Adv. Math., 148(2), 243–265. arXiv: math/0003120 DOI: 10.1006/aima.1999.1852 MR: 1736959
    type: article
    abstract: It is known that the automorphism towers of infinite centreless groups of cardinality $\kappa$ terminate in less than $\left( 2^{\kappa} \right)^{+}$ steps. In this paper, we show that $ZFC$ cannot settle the question of whether such automorphism towers actually terminate in less than $2^{\kappa}$ steps.
    keywords: S: for, (stal), (auto), (grp)
  622. Sh:655
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2001). Iteration of \lambda-complete forcing notions not collapsing \lambda^+. Int. J. Math. Math. Sci., 28(2), 63–82. arXiv: math/9906024 DOI: 10.1155/S016117120102018X MR: 1885053
    type: article
    abstract: We look for a parallel to the notion of ``proper forcing" among $\lambda$-complete forcing notions not collapsing $\lambda^+$. We suggest such a definition and prove that it is preserved by suitable iterations.
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  623. Sh:657
    Shelah, S., & Väänänen, J. A. (2000). Stationary sets and infinitary logic. J. Symbolic Logic, 65(3), 1311–1320. arXiv: math/9706225 DOI: 10.2307/2586701 MR: 1791377
    type: article
    abstract: Let $K^0_\lambda$ be the class of structures $\langle\lambda,< ,A\rangle$, where $A\subseteq\lambda$ is disjoint from a club, and let $K^1_\lambda$ be the class of structures $\langle\lambda,< ,A\rangle$, where $A\subseteq\lambda$ contains a club. We prove that if $\lambda=\lambda^{< \kappa}$ is regular, then no sentence of $L_{\lambda^+\kappa}$ separates $K^0_\lambda$ and $K^1_\lambda$. On the other hand, we prove that if $\lambda=\mu^+$, $\mu=\mu^{< \mu}$, and a forcing axiom holds (and $\aleph_1^L=\aleph_1$ if $\mu=\aleph_0$), then there is a sentence of $L_{\lambda\lambda}$ which separates $K^0_\lambda$ and $K^1_\lambda$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (inf-log), (set-mod)
  624. Sh:658
    Bartoszyński, T., & Shelah, S. (2002). Strongly meager and strong measure zero sets. Arch. Math. Logic, 41(3), 245–250. arXiv: math/9907137 DOI: 10.1007/s001530000068 MR: 1901186
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper we present several consistency results concerning the existence of large strong measure zero and strongly meager sets.
    keywords: S: str, (set)
  625. Sh:659
    Džamonja, M., & Shelah, S. (2003). Universal graphs at the successor of a singular cardinal. J. Symbolic Logic, 68(2), 366–388. arXiv: math/0102043 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1052669056 MR: 1976583
    type: article
    abstract: The paper is concerned with the existence of a universal graph at the successor of a strong limit singular $\mu$ of cofinality $\aleph_0$. Starting from the assumption of the existence of a supercompact cardinal, a model is built in which for some such $\mu$ there are $\mu^{++}$ graphs on $\mu^+$ that taken jointly are universal for the graphs on $\mu^+$, while $2^{\mu^+}>>\mu^{++}$. The paper also addresses the general problem of obtaining a framework for consistency results at the successor of a singular strong limit starting from the assumption that a supercompact cardinal $\kappa$ exists. The result on the existence of universal graphs is obtained as a specific application of a more general method.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (graph), (univ)
  626. Sh:660
    Shelah, S. Covering numbers associated with trees branching into a countably generated set of possibilities. Real Anal. Exchange, 24(1), 205–213. arXiv: math/9711223 MR: 1691746
    type: article
    abstract: This paper is concerned with certain generalizations of meagreness and their combinatorial equivalents. The simplest example, and the one which motivated further study in this area, comes about by considering the following definition: a set $X\subseteq R$ is said to be $Q$-nowhere dense if and only if for every rational $q$ there exists and integer $k$ such that the interval whose endpoints are $q$ and $q+1/k$ is disjoint from $X$. A set which is the union of countably many $Q$-nowhere dense sets will be called $Q$-very meagre. Steprans considered the least number of $Q$-meagre sets required to cover the real line and denoted by $d_1$. He showed that there is a continuous function $H$ --- first constructed by Lebesgue --- such that the least number of smooth functions into which $H$ can be decomposed is equal to $d_1$. This paper will further study $d_1$ and some of its generalizations. As well, an equivalence will be established between $Q$-meagreness and certain combinatorial properties of trees. This will lead to new cardinal invariants and various independence results about these will then be established.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  627. Sh:661
    Kolman, O., & Shelah, S. (1998). A result related to the problem CN of Fremlin. J. Appl. Anal., 4(2), 161–165. arXiv: math/9712287 DOI: 10.1515/JAA.1998.161 MR: 1667030
    type: article
    abstract: We show that the set of injective functions from any uncountable cardinal less than the continuum into the real numbers is of second category in the box product topology.
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  628. Sh:662
    Halko, A., & Shelah, S. (2001). On strong measure zero subsets of ^\kappa2. Fund. Math., 170(3), 219–229. arXiv: math/9710218 DOI: 10.4064/fm170-3-1 MR: 1880900
    type: article
    abstract: This paper answers three questions posed by the first author. In Theorem 2.6 we show that the family of strong measure zero subsets of ${}^{\omega_1}2$ is $2^{\aleph_1}$-additive under GMA and CH. In Theorem 3.1 we prove that the generalized Borel conjecture is false in ${}^{\omega_1}2$ assuming ZFC+CH. Next, in Theorem 4.2, we show that the family of subsets of ${}^{\omega_1}2$ with the property of Baire is not closed under the Souslin operation.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (ps-dst)
  629. Sh:663
    Shelah, S., & Spinas, O. (1999). On tightness and depth in superatomic Boolean algebras. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 127(12), 3475–3480. arXiv: math/9802135 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-99-04944-8 MR: 1610793
    type: article
    abstract: We introduce a large cardinal property which is consistent with $L$ and show that for every superatomic Boolean algebra $B$ and every cardinal $\lambda$ with the large cardinal property, if tightness$^+(B)\geq\lambda^+$, then depth$(B)\geq\lambda$. This improves a theorem of Dow and Monk.
    keywords: S: for, (ba), (inv(ba))
  630. Sh:664
    Shelah, S. (2001). Strong dichotomy of cardinality. Results Math., 39(1-2), 131–154. arXiv: math/9807183 DOI: 10.1007/BF03322680 MR: 1817405
    type: article
    abstract: A usual dichotomy is that in many cases, reasonably definable sets, satisfy the CH, i.e. if they are uncountable they have cardinality continuum. A strong dichotomy is when: if the cardinality is infinite it is continuum as in [Sh:273]. We are interested in such phenomena when $\lambda=\aleph_0$ is replaced by $\lambda$ regular uncountable and also by $\lambda=\beth_\omega$ or more generally by strong limit of cofinality $\aleph_0$.
    keywords: S: ods, (stal), (ps-dst)
  631. Sh:665
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (2001). The covering numbers of Mycielski ideals are all equal. J. Symbolic Logic, 66(2), 707–718. arXiv: math/9712288 DOI: 10.2307/2695039 MR: 1833473
    type: article
    abstract: The Mycielski ideal $M_k$ is defined to consist of all sets $A\subseteq k^\omega$ such that $\{f\restriction X: f\in A\}\neq k^X$ for all $X\in [\omega]^{\aleph_0}$. It will be shown that the covering numbers for these ideals are all equal. However, the covering numbers of the closely associated Roslanowski ideals will be shown to be consistently different.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (creatures)
  632. Sh:666
    Shelah, S. (2000). On what I do not understand (and have something to say). I. Fund. Math., 166(1-2), 1–82. arXiv: math/9906113 MR: 1804704
    type: article
    abstract: This is a non-standard paper, containing some problems I have in various degrees been interested in, sometimes with discussion on what I have to say; why they seem interesting, sometimes how I have tried to solve them, failed tries, anecdote and opinion, so the discussion is quite personal, in other words, egocentric and somewhat accidental. As we discuss many problems, history and side references are erratic, usually kept at a minimum (see $\ldots$ means: see the references there and possibly the paper itself). The base were lectures in Rutgers Fall '97.
    keywords: S: ods, (set), (stal)
  633. Sh:667
    Shelah, S. (2003). Successor of singulars: combinatorics and not collapsing cardinals \le\kappa in (<\kappa)-support iterations. Israel J. Math., 134, 127–155. arXiv: math/9808140 DOI: 10.1007/BF02787405 MR: 1972177
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with $(< \kappa)$-supported iterated forcing notions which are $(E_0,E_1)$-complete, have in mind problems on Whitehead groups, uniformizations and the general problem. We deal mainly with the successor of a singular case. This continues [Sh:587]. We also deal with complimentary combinatorial results.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (unif)
  634. Sh:668
    Shelah, S. (2004). Anti-homogeneous partitions of a topological space. Sci. Math. Jpn., 59(2), 203–255. arXiv: math/9906025 MR: 2062196
    type: article
    abstract: We prove the consistency (modulo supercompact) of a negative answer to Arhangelskii's problem (some Hausdorff compact space cannot be partitioned to two sets not containing a closed copy of Cantor discontinuum). In this model we have CH. Without CH we get consistency results using a pcf assumption, close relatives of which are necessary for such results.
    keywords: S: for, S: pcf, (set), (gt)
  635. Sh:669
    Shelah, S. (2006). Non-Cohen oracle C.C.C. J. Appl. Anal., 12(1), 1–17. arXiv: math/0303294 DOI: 10.1515/JAA.2006.1 MR: 2243849
    type: article
    abstract: The oracle c.c.c. is closed related to Cohen forcing. During an iteration we can ``omit a type''; i.e. preserve ``the intersection of a given family of Borel sets of reals is empty'' provided that Cohen forcing satisfies it. We generalize this to other cases. In \S1 we replace Cohen by ``nicely'' definable c.c.c., do the parallel of the oracle c.c.c. and end with a criterion for extracting a subforcing (not a complete subforcing) of a given nicely one and satisfying the oracle.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (cont)
  636. Sh:671
    Jech, T. J., & Shelah, S. (2000). On reflection of stationary sets in \mathcal P_\kappa\lambda. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 352(6), 2507–2515. arXiv: math/9801078 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-99-02448-4 MR: 1650097
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\kappa$ be an inaccessible cardinal, and let $E_0=\{x\in{\mathcal P}_\kappa\kappa^+:cf(\lambda_x)=cf(\kappa_x)\}$ and $E_1=\{x\in{\mathcal P}_\kappa\kappa^+:\kappa_x$ is regular and $\lambda_x =\kappa_x^+\}$. It is consistent that the set $E_1$ is stationary and that every stationary subset of $E_0$ reflects at almost every $a\in E_1$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter), (normal), (ref), (pure(large))
  637. Sh:672
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2004). Sweet & sour and other flavours of ccc forcing notions. Arch. Math. Logic, 43(5), 583–663. arXiv: math/9909115 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-004-0213-7 MR: 2076408
    type: article
    abstract: We continue developing the general theory of forcing notions built with the use of norms on possibilities, this time concentrating on ccc forcing notions and classifying them.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (pure(for))
  638. Sh:673
    Kojman, M., & Shelah, S. (2000). The PCF trichotomy theorem does not hold for short sequences. Arch. Math. Logic, 39(3), 213–218. arXiv: math/9712289 DOI: 10.1007/s001530050143 MR: 1758508
    type: article
    abstract: We show that the assumption $\lambda> \kappa^+$ in the Trichotomy Theorem cannot be relaxed to $\lambda> \kappa$.
    keywords: S: for, S: pcf, (set)
  639. Sh:674
    Balogh, Z. T., Davis, S. W., Just, W., Shelah, S., & Szeptycki, P. J. (2000). Strongly almost disjoint sets and weakly uniform bases. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 352(11), 4971–4987. arXiv: math/9803167 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-00-02599-X MR: 1707497
    type: article
    abstract: A combinatorial principle CECA is formulated and its equivalence with GCH+ certain weakenings of $\Box_\lambda$ for singular $\lambda$ is proved. CECA is used to show that certain ``almost point-$< \tau$'' families can be refined to point-$< \tau$ families by removing a small set from each member of the family. This theorem in turn is used to show the consistency of ``every first countable $T_1$-space with a weakly uniform base has a point-countable base.''
    keywords: S: ico, S: pcf, (set)
  640. Sh:675
    Shelah, S. (1997). On Ciesielski’s problems. J. Appl. Anal., 3(2), 191–209. arXiv: math/9801155 DOI: 10.1515/JAA.1997.191 MR: 1619548
    type: article
    abstract: We discuss some problems posed by Ciesielski. For example we show that, consistently, $d_c$ is a singular cardinal and $e_c<d_c$. Next we prove that the Martin Axiom for $\sigma$--centered forcing notions implies that for every function $f:R^2\longrightarrow R$ there are functions $g_n,h_n:R\longrightarrow R$, $n<\omega$, such that $f(x,y)=\sum_{n=0}^{\infty} g_n(x)h_n(y)$. Finally, we deal with countably continuous functions and we show that in the Cohen model they are exactly the functions $f$ with the property that $(\forall U\in [R]^{\aleph_1})(\exists U^*\in [U]^{\aleph_1}) (f\restriction U^*$ is continuous).
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (app(pcf))
  641. Sh:676
    Hyttinen, T., & Shelah, S. (2001). Main gap for locally saturated elementary submodels of a homogeneous structure. J. Symbolic Logic, 66(3), 1286–1302. arXiv: math/9804157 DOI: 10.2307/2695107 MR: 1856742
    type: article
    abstract: We prove a main gap theorem for e-saturated submodels of a homogeneous structure. We also study the number of e-saturated models, which are not elementarily embeddable to each other
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  642. Sh:677
    Shelah, S., & Spinas, O. (2000). On incomparability and related cardinal functions on ultraproducts of Boolean algebras. Math. Japon., 52(3), 345–358. arXiv: math/9903116 MR: 1796651
    type: article
    abstract: Let $C$ denote any of the following cardinal characteristics of Boolean algebras: incomparability, spread, character, $\pi$-character, hereditary Lindel\"of number, hereditary density. It is shown to be consistent that there exists a sequence $\langle B_i:i<\kappa\rangle$ of Boolean algebras and an ultrafilter $D$ on $\kappa$ such that $C(\prod_{i<\kappa}B_i/D)<|\prod_{i<\kappa}C(B_i)/D|$. This answers a number of problems posed by Monk.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (ba), (large), (up), (inv(ba))
  643. Sh:678
    Eklof, P. C., & Shelah, S. (1999). Absolutely rigid systems and absolutely indecomposable groups. In Abelian groups and modules (Dublin, 1998), Birkhäuser, Basel, pp. 257–268. arXiv: math/0010264 MR: 1735574
    type: article
    abstract: We give a new proof that there are arbitrarily large indecomposable abelian groups; moreover, the groups constructed are absolutely indecomposable, that is, they remain indecomposable in any generic extension. However, any absolutely rigid family of groups has cardinality less than the partition cardinal $\kappa(\omega)$.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (inf-log)
  644. Sh:679
    Shelah, S. (2002). A partition theorem. Sci. Math. Jpn., 56(2), 413–438. arXiv: math/0003163 MR: 1922806
    type: article
    abstract: We prove the following: there is a primitive recursive function $f_{-}^*(-,-)$, in the three variables, such that: for every natural numbers $t,n>0$, and $c$, for any natural number $k\geq f^*_t(n,c)$ the following holds. Assume $\Lambda$ is an alphabet with $n>0$ letters, $M$ is the family of non empty subsets of $\{1,\ldots,k\}$ with $\leq t$ members and $V$ is the set of functions from $M$ to $\Lambda$ and lastly $d$ is a $c$--colouring of $V$ (i.e., a function with domain $V$ and range with at most $c$ members). Then there is a $d$--monochromatic $V$--line, which means that there are $w \subseteq \{1,\ldots,k\}$, with at least $t$ members and function $\rho$ from $\{u\in M: u$ not a subset of $w\}$ to $\Lambda$ such that letting $L=\{\eta\in V:\eta$ extend $\rho$ and for each $s=1,\ldots,t$ it is constant on $\{u\in M:u\subseteq w$ has $s$ members $\}\}$, we have $d\restriction L$ is constant (for $t=1$ those are the Hales Jewett numbers).
    keywords: S: ods, (pc), (fc)
  645. Sh:680
    Ciesielski, K. C., & Shelah, S. Uniformly antisymmetric functions with bounded range. Real Anal. Exchange, 24(2), 615–619. arXiv: math/9805151 MR: 1704738
    type: article
    abstract: The goal of this note is to construct a uniformly antisymmetric function $f:R\to R$ with a bounded countable range. This answers Problem 1(b) of Ciesielski and Larson. (See also list of problems in Thomson and Problem 2(b) from Ciesielski's survey.) A problem of existence of uniformly antisymmetric function $f:R\to R$ with finite range remains open.
    keywords: S: ico, S: str, (set)
  646. Sh:681
    Göbel, R., Shelah, S., & Strüngmann, L. H. (2004). Generalized E-rings. In Rings, modules, algebras, and abelian groups, Vol. 236, Dekker, New York, pp. 291–306. arXiv: math/0404271 MR: 2050718
    type: article
    abstract: A ring $R$ is called an $E$-ring if the canonical homomorphism from $R$ to the endomorphism ring $End(R_{\mathbb Z})$ of the additive group $R_{\mathbb Z}$, taking any $r \in R$ to the endomorphism left multiplication by $r$ turns out to be an isomorphism of rings. In this case $R_{\mathbb Z}$ is called an $E$-group. Obvious examples of $E$-rings are subrings of ${\mathbb Q}$. However there is a proper class of examples constructed recently. $E$-rings come up naturally in various topics of algebra. This also led to a generalization: an abelian group $G$ is an ${\mathbb E}$-group if there is an epimorphism from $G$ onto the additive group of $End(G)$. If $G$ is torsion-free of finite rank, then $G$ is an $E$-group if and only if it is an ${\mathbb E}$-group. The obvious question was raised a few years ago which we will answer by showing that the two notions do not coincide. We will apply combinatorial machinery to non-commutative rings to produce an abelian group $G$ with (non-commutative) $End(G)$ and the desired epimorphism with prescribed kernel $H$. Hence, if we let $H=0$, we obtain a non-commutative ring $R$ such that $End(R_{{\mathbb Z}}) \cong R$ but $R$ is not an $E$-ring.
    keywords: M: non, (ab), (large)
  647. Sh:682
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (1999). Almost free splitters. Colloq. Math., 81(2), 193–221. arXiv: math/9910161 DOI: 10.4064/cm-81-2-193-221 MR: 1715347
    See [Sh:E22]

    type: article
    abstract: Let $R$ be a subring of the rationals. We want to investigate self splitting $R$-modules $G$ that is ${\rm Ext}_R(G,G)=0$ holds. For simplicity we will call such modules splitters. Our investigation continues [GbSh:647]. In [GbSh:647] we answered an open problem by constructing a large class of splitters. Classical splitters are free modules and torsion-free, algebraically compact ones. In [GbSh:647] we concentrated on splitters which are larger then the continuum and such that countable submodules are not necessarily free. The `opposite' case of $\aleph_1$-free splitters of cardinality less or equal to $\aleph_1$ was singled out because of basically different techniques. This is the target of the present paper. If the splitter is countable, then it must be free over some subring of the rationals by a result of Hausen. We can show that all $\aleph_1$-free splitters of cardinality $\aleph_1$ are free indeed.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (af), (unif)
  648. Sh:683
    Kolman, O., & Shelah, S. (1999). Almost disjoint pure subgroups of the Baer-Specker group. In Abelian groups and modules (Dublin, 1998), Birkhäuser, Basel, pp. 225–230. arXiv: math/0102057 MR: 1735570
    type: article
    abstract: We prove in ZFC that the Baer-Specker group ${\bf Z}^\omega$ has $2^{\aleph_1}$ non-free pure subgroups of cardinality $\aleph_1$ which are almost disjoint: there is no non-free subgroup embeddable in any pair.
    keywords: S: ico, S: str, (ab)
  649. Sh:684
    Mildenberger, H., & Shelah, S. (2000). Changing cardinal characteristics without changing \omega-sequences or confinalities. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 106(1-3), 207–261. arXiv: math/9901096 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(00)00026-9 MR: 1785760
    type: article
    abstract: We show: There are pairs of universes $V_1\subseteq V_2$ and there is a notion of forcing $P\in V_1$ such that the change mentioned in the title occurs when going from $V_1[G]$ to $V_2[G]$ for a $P$--generic filter $G$ over $V_2$. We use forcing iterations with partial memories. Moreover, we implement highly transitive automorphism groups into the forcing orders.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (inv), (pure(for))
  650. Sh:685
    Džamonja, M., & Shelah, S. (2000). On versions of \clubsuit on cardinals larger than \aleph_1. Math. Japon., 51(1), 53–61. arXiv: math/9911228 MR: 1739051
    type: article
    abstract: We give two results on guessing unbounded subsets of $\lambda^+$. The first is a positive result and applies to the situation of $\lambda$ regular and at least equal to $\aleph_3$, while the second is a negative consistency result which applies to the situation of $\lambda$ a singular strong limit with $2^\lambda>\lambda^+$. The first result shows that in ZFC there is a guessing of unbounded subsets of $S^{\lambda^+}_\lambda$. The second result is a consistency result (assuming a supercompact cardinal exists) showing that a natural guessing fails. A result of Shelah in [Sh:667] shows that if $2^\lambda=\lambda^+$ and $\lambda$ is a strong limit singular, then the corresponding guessing holds. Both results are also connected to an earlier result of D{\v z}amonja-Shelah in which they showed that a certain version of $\clubsuit$ holds at a successor of singular just in ZFC. The first result here shows that a result of [DjSh:545] can to a certain extent be extended to the successor of a regular. The negative result here gives limitations to the extent to which one can hope to extend the mentioned D{\v z}amonja-Shelah result.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (iter)
  651. Sh:686
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2001). The yellow cake. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 129(1), 279–291. arXiv: math/9810179 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-00-05538-6 MR: 1694876
    type: article
    abstract: We consider the following property: $(*)$ For every function $f:R\times R\longrightarrow R$ there are functions $g^0_n,g^1_n:R\longrightarrow R$ (for $n<\omega$) such that $(\forall x,y\in R)(f(x,y)=\sum_{n<\omega}g^0_n(x)g^1_n(y))$. We show that, despite some expectation suggested by [Sh:675], $(*)$ does not imply MA($\sigma$-centered). Next, we introduce cardinal characteristics of the continuum responsible for the failure of $(*)$.
    keywords: S: str, (set)
  652. Sh:687
    Laskowski, M. C., & Shelah, S. (2003). Karp complexity and classes with the independence property. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 120(1-3), 263–283. arXiv: math/0303345 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(02)00080-5 MR: 1949710
    type: article
    abstract: A class ${\bf K}$ of structures is {\em controlled\/} if for all cardinals $\lambda$, the relation of $L_{\infty,\lambda}$-equivalence partitions ${\bf K}$ into a set of equivalence classes (as opposed to a proper class). We prove that no pseudo-elementary class with the independence property is controlled. By contrast, there is a pseudo-elementary class with the strict order property that is controlled.
    keywords: M: non, (mod)
  653. Sh:688
    Goldstern, M., & Shelah, S. (1999). There are no infinite order polynomially complete lattices, after all. Algebra Universalis, 42(1-2), 49–57. arXiv: math/9810050 DOI: 10.1007/s000120050122 MR: 1736340
    type: article
    abstract: If $L$ is a lattice with the interpolation property whose cardinality is a strong limit cardinal of uncountable cofinality, then some finite power $L^n$ has an antichain of size~$ \kappa $. Hence there are no infinite opc lattices (i.e., lattices on which every $n$-ary monotone function is a polynomial). However, the existence of strongly amorphous sets implies (in ZF) the existence of infinite opc lattices.
    keywords: O: alg, (ua)
  654. Sh:689
    Cherlin, G. L., Shelah, S., & Shi, N. (1999). Universal graphs with forbidden subgraphs and algebraic closure. Adv. In Appl. Math., 22(4), 454–491. arXiv: math/9809202 DOI: 10.1006/aama.1998.0641 MR: 1683298
    type: article
    abstract: We apply model theoretic methods to the problem of existence of countable universal graphs with finitely many forbidden connected subgraphs. We show that to a large extent the question reduces to one of local finiteness of an associated "algebraic closure" operator. The main applications are new examples of universal graphs with forbidden subgraphs and simplified treatments of some previously known cases.
    keywords: M: odm, (mod), (graph), (univ)
  655. Sh:690
    Eisworth, T., Nyikos, P. J., & Shelah, S. (2003). Gently killing S-spaces. Israel J. Math., 136, 189–220. arXiv: math/9812133 DOI: 10.1007/BF02807198 MR: 1998110
    type: article
    abstract: We produce a model of ZFC in which there are no locally compact first countable S--spaces, and in which $2^{\aleph_0}<2^{\aleph_1}$. A consequence of this is that in this model there are no locally compact, separable, hereditarily normal spaces of size $\aleph_1$, answering a question of the second author
    keywords: S: for, (iter), (gt)
  656. Sh:691
    Džamonja, M., & Shelah, S. (2003). Weak reflection at the successor of a singular cardinal. J. London Math. Soc. (2), 67(1), 1–15. arXiv: math/0003118 DOI: 10.1112/S0024610702003757 MR: 1942407
    See [Sh:E20]

    type: article
    abstract: The notion of stationary reflection is one of the most important notions of combinatorial set theory. We investigate weak reflection, which is, as its name suggests, a weak version of stationary reflection. Our main result is that modulo a large cardinal assumption close to 2-hugeness, there can be a regular cardinal $\kappa$ such that the first cardinal weakly reflecting at $\kappa$ is the successor of a singular cardinal. This answers a question of Cummings, D\v zamonja and Shelah.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (large), (ref)
  657. Sh:692
    Džamonja, M., & Shelah, S. (2004). On \vartriangleleft^*-maximality. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 125(1-3), 119–158. arXiv: math/0009087 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2003.11.001 MR: 2033421
    type: article
    abstract: This paper investigates a connection between the ordering $\triangleleft^\ast$ among theories in model theory and the (N)SOP${}_n$ hierarchy of Shelah. It introduces two properties which are natural extensions of this hierarchy, called SOP${}_2$ and SOP${}_1$, and gives a strong connection between SOP${}_1$ and the maximality in Keisler ordering. Together with the known results about the connection between the (N)SOP${}_n$ hierarchy and the existence of universal models in the absence of $GCH$, the paper provides a step toward the classification of unstable theories without the strict order property.
    keywords: M: cla, S: ico, (mod)
  658. Sh:693
    Shelah, S., & Trlifaj, J. (2001). Spectra of the \Gamma-invariant of uniform modules. J. Pure Appl. Algebra, 162(2-3), 367–379. arXiv: math/0009060 DOI: 10.1016/S0022-4049(00)00118-3 MR: 1843814
    type: article
    abstract: For a ring $R$, denote by ${\rm Spec}^R_\kappa (\Gamma)$ the $\kappa$-spectrum of the $\Gamma$-invariant of strongly uniform right $R$-modules. Recent realization techniques of Goodearl and Wehrung show that ${\rm Spec}^R_{\aleph_1} (\Gamma)$ is full for suitable von Neumann regular algebras $R$, but the techniques do not extend to cardinals $\kappa > \aleph_1$. By a direct construction, we prove that for any field $F$ and any regular uncountable cardinal $\kappa$ there is an $F$-algebra $R$ such that ${\rm Spec}^R_\kappa (\Gamma)$ is full. We also derive some consequences for the complexity of Ziegler spectra of infinite dimensional algebras.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  659. Sh:694
    Jech, T. J., & Shelah, S. (2001). Simple complete Boolean algebras. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 129(2), 543–549. arXiv: math/0406438 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-00-05566-0 MR: 1707521
    type: article
    abstract: For every regular cardinal $\kappa$ there exists a simple complete Boolean algebra with $\kappa$ generators.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (ba), (pure(for))
  660. Sh:695
    Ciesielski, K. C., & Shelah, S. (2000). Category analogue of sup-measurability problem. J. Appl. Anal., 6(2), 159–172. arXiv: math/9905147 DOI: 10.1515/JAA.2000.159 MR: 1805097
    type: article
    abstract: A function $F\colon{\mathbb R}^2\to{\mathbb R}$ is sup-measurable if $F_f\colon{\mathbb R}\to{\mathbb R}$ given by $F_f(x)=F(x,f(x))$, $x\in{\mathbb R}$, is measurable for each measurable function $f\colon{\mathbb R}\to{\mathbb R}$. It is known that under different set theoretical assumptions, including CH, there are sup-measurable non-measurable functions, as well as their category analog. In this paper we will show that the existence of category analog of sup-measurable non-measurable functions is independent of ZFC. A problem whether the similar is true for the original measurable case remains open.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (leb)
  661. Sh:696
    Goldstern, M., & Shelah, S. (2002). Antichains in products of linear orders. Order, 19(3), 213–222. arXiv: math/9902054 DOI: 10.1023/A:1021289412771 MR: 1942184
    type: article
    abstract: We show that: For many cardinals $ \lambda$, for all $n\in \{2,3,4,\ldots\}$ There is a linear order $L$ such that $L^n$ has no (incomparability-)antichain of cardinality $\lambda$, while $L^{n+1}$ has an antichain of cardinality $\lambda$. For any nondecreasing sequence $(\lambda_n: n \in \{2,3,4,\ldots\})$ of infinite cardinals it is consistent that there is a linear order $L$ such that $L^n$ has an antichain of cardinality $\lambda_n$, but not one of cardinality $\lambda_n^+$.
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  662. Sh:697
    Hajnal, A., Juhász, I., & Shelah, S. (2000). Strongly almost disjoint families, revisited. Fund. Math., 163(1), 13–23. arXiv: math/9812114 MR: 1750332
    type: article
    abstract: The relations $M(\kappa,\lambda,\mu)\to B$ (resp. $B(\sigma)$) meaning that if ${\mathcal A}\subset [\kappa]^\lambda$ with $|{\mathcal A}|=\kappa$ is $\mu$-almost disjoint then ${\mathcal A}$ has property $B$ (resp. has a $\sigma$-transversal) had been introduced and studied under GCH by Erdos and Hajnal in 1961. Our two main results here say the following: Assume GCH and $\varrho$ be any regular cardinal with a supercompact [resp. 2-huge] cardinal above $\varrho$. Then there is a $\varrho$-closed forcing $P$ such that, in $V^P$, we have both GCH and $M(\varrho^{(+\varrho+1)},\varrho^+,\varrho)\nrightarrow B$ (resp. $M(\varrho^{(+\varrho+1)},\lambda,\varrho) \nrightarrow B(\varrho^+)$ for all $\lambda\le\varrho^{(+\varrho+1)}$).
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (large)
  663. Sh:698
    Shelah, S. (2002). On the existence of large subsets of [\lambda]^{<\kappa} which contain no unbounded non-stationary subsets. Arch. Math. Logic, 41(3), 207–213. arXiv: math/9908159 DOI: 10.1007/s001530000054 MR: 1901184
    type: article
    abstract: Here we deal with some problems of Mate, written as it developed. The first section deals with the existence of stationary subsets of $[\lambda]^{<\kappa}$ with no unbounded subsets which are not stationary, where $\kappa$ is regular uncountable $\leq\lambda$. In the section section we deal with the existence of such clubs.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (normal), (app(pcf))
  664. Sh:699
    Halbeisen, L. J., & Shelah, S. (2001). Relations between some cardinals in the absence of the axiom of choice. Bull. Symbolic Logic, 7(2), 237–261. arXiv: math/0010268 DOI: 10.2307/2687776 MR: 1839547
    type: article
    abstract: If we assume the axiom of choice, then every two cardinal numbers are comparable. In the absence of the axiom of choice, this is no longer so. For a few cardinalities related to an arbitrary infinite set, we will give all the possible relationships between them, where possible means that the relationship is consistent with the axioms of set theory. Further we investigate the relationships between some other cardinal numbers in specific permutation models and give some results provable without using the axiom of choice.
    keywords: S: ods, (AC)
  665. Sh:700
    Shelah, S. (2004). Two cardinal invariants of the continuum (\mathfrak d<\mathfrak a) and FS linearly ordered iterated forcing. Acta Math., 192(2), 187–223. Previous title “Are \mathfrak a and \mathfrak d your cup of tea?” arXiv: math/0012170 DOI: 10.1007/BF02392740 MR: 2096454
    type: article
    abstract: We show that consistently, every MAD family has cardinality strictly bigger than the dominating number, that is $\mathfrak{a} > \mathfrak{d}$, thus solving one of the oldest problems on cardinal invariants of the continuum. The method is a contribution to the theory of iterated forcing for making the continuum large.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (iter), (inv)
  666. Sh:701
    Göbel, R., Rodrı́guez Blancas, J. L., & Shelah, S. (2002). Large localizations of finite simple groups. J. Reine Angew. Math., 550, 1–24. arXiv: math/9912191 DOI: 10.1515/crll.2002.072 MR: 1925906
    type: article
    abstract: We answer a question of Emanuel Farjoun on homotopy groups using cancellation theory
    keywords: M: non, (stal)
  667. Sh:702
    Shelah, S. (2000). On what I do not understand (and have something to say), model theory. Math. Japon., 51(2), 329–377. arXiv: math/9910158 MR: 1747306
    type: article
    abstract: This is a non-standard paper, containing some problems, mainly in model theory, which I have, in various degrees, been interested in. Sometimes with a discussion on what I have to say; sometimes, of what makes them interesting to me, sometimes the problems are presented with a discussion of how I have tried to solve them, and sometimes with failed tries, anecdote and opinion. So the discussion is quite personal, in other words, egocentric and somewhat accidental. As we discuss many problems, history and side references are erratic, usually kept at a minimum (``See..." means: see the references there and possibly the paper itself). The base were lectures in Rutgers Fall '97 and reflect my knowledge then. The other half, concentrating on set theory, is in print [Sh:666], but the two halves are independent. We thank A. Blass, G. Cherlin and R. Grossberg for some corrections.
    keywords: M: odm, (mod)
  668. Sh:703
    Shelah, S. (2003). On ultraproducts of Boolean algebras and irr. Arch. Math. Logic, 42(6), 569–581. arXiv: math/0012171 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-002-0167-6 MR: 2001060
    type: article
    abstract: We prove the consistency of ${\rm irr}(\prod\limits_{i< \kappa} B_i/D)<\prod\limits_{i<\kappa}{\rm irr}(B_i)/D$, where $D$ is an ultrafilter on $\kappa$ and each $B_i$ is a Boolean Algebra. This solves the last problem of this form from the Monk's list of problems, that is number 35. The solution applies to many other properties, e.g., Souslinity. Next, we get similar results with $\kappa=\aleph_1$ (easily we cannot have it for $\kappa = \aleph_0$) and Boolean Algebras $B_i$ ($i<\kappa$) of cardinality $<\beth_{\omega_1}$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (ba), (large), (inv(ba))
  669. Sh:704
    Shelah, S. (2002). Superatomic Boolean algebras: maximal rigidity. In Set theory (Piscataway, NJ, 1999), Vol. 58, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, pp. 107–128. arXiv: math/0009075 MR: 1903854
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that for any superatomic Boolean Algebra of cardinality $>\beth_\omega$ there is an automorphism moving uncountably many atoms. Similarly for larger cardinals any of those results are essentially best possible.
    keywords: O: alg, (set), (ba), (auto)
  670. Sh:706
    Shelah, S. (2012). Universality among graphs omitting a complete bipartite graph. Combinatorica, 32(3), 325–362. arXiv: math/0102058 DOI: 10.1007/s00493-012-2033-4 MR: 2965281
    type: article
    abstract: For cardinals $\lambda,\kappa,\theta$ we consider the class of graphs of cardinality $\lambda$ which has no subgraph which is $(\kappa,\theta)$-complete bipartite graph. The question is whether in such a class there is a universal one under (weak) embedding. We solve this problem completely under GCH. Under various assumptions mostly related to cardinal arithmetic we prove nonexistence of universals for this problem and some related ones.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (graph), (univ)
  671. Sh:708
    Gitik, M., & Shelah, S. (2001). On some configurations related to the Shelah weak hypothesis. Arch. Math. Logic, 40(8), 639–650. arXiv: math/9909087 DOI: 10.1007/s001530100076 MR: 1867686
    type: article
    abstract: We show that some cardinal arithmetic configurations related to the negation of the Shelah Weak Hypothesis and natural from the forcing point of view are impossible.
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  672. Sh:709
    Kolman, O., & Shelah, S. (2000). Infinitary axiomatizability of slender and cotorsion-free groups. Bull. Belg. Math. Soc. Simon Stevin, 7(4), 623–629. arXiv: math/9910162 http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.bbms/1103055621 MR: 1806941
    type: article
    abstract: The classes of slender and cotorsion-free abelian groups are axiomatizable in the infinitary logics $L_{\infty\omega_1}$ and $L_{\infty\omega}$ respectively. The Baer-Specker group ${\mathbb Z}^\omega$ is not $L_{\infty\omega_1}$-equivalent to a slender group.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  673. Sh:710
    Džamonja, M., & Shelah, S. (2006). On properties of theories which preclude the existence of universal models. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 139(1-3), 280–302. arXiv: math/0009078 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2005.06.001 MR: 2206258
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper we investigate some properties of first order theories which prevent them from having universal models under certain cardinal assumptions. Our results give a new syntactical condition, oak property, which is a sufficient condition for a theory not to have universal models in cardinality $\lambda$ when certain cardinal arithmetic assumptions implying the failure of $GCH$ (and close to the failure of $SCH$) hold.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (univ)
  674. Sh:711
    Shelah, S. (2005). On nicely definable forcing notions. J. Appl. Anal., 11(1), 1–17. arXiv: math/0303293 DOI: 10.1515/JAA.2005.1 MR: 2151390
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that if $\mathbb Q$ is a nw-nep forcing then it cannot add a dominating real. We also prove that Amoeba forcing cannot be ${\mathcal P}(X)/I$ if $I$ is an $\aleph_1$-complete ideal.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (pure(for))
  675. Sh:712
    Fuchino, S., Geschke, S., Shelah, S., & Soukup, L. (2001). On the weak Freese-Nation property of complete Boolean algebras. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 110(1-3), 89–105. arXiv: math/9911230 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(01)00023-9 MR: 1846760
    type: article
    abstract: The following results are proved: (a) In a Cohen model, there is always a ccc complete Boolean algebras without the weak Freese-Nation property. (b) Modulo the consistency strength of a supercompact cardinal, the existence of a ccc complete Boolean algebras without the weak Freese-Nation property consistent with GCH. (c) Under some consequences of $\neg0^\#$, the weak Freese-Nation property of $({\mathcal P}(\omega),{\subseteq})$ is equivalent to the weak Freese-Nation property of any of ${\mathbb C}(\kappa)$ or ${\mathbb R}(\kappa)$ for uncountable $\kappa$. (d) Modulo consistency of $(\aleph_{\omega+1},\aleph_\omega) \longrightarrow(\aleph_1,\aleph_0)$, it is consistent with GCH that the assertion in (c) does not hold and also that adding $\aleph_\omega$ Cohen reals destroys the weak Freese-Nation property of $({\mathcal P}(\omega),{\subseteq})$.
    keywords: S: ico, (ba)
  676. Sh:713
    Matet, P., Péan, C., & Shelah, S. (2016). Cofinality of normal ideals on [\lambda]^{<\kappa} I. Arch. Math. Logic, 55(5-6), 799–834. arXiv: math/0404318 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-016-0496-5 MR: 3523657
    type: article
    abstract: Given an ordinal $\delta\leq\lambda$ and a cardinal $\theta\leq\kappa$, an ideal $J$ on $P_{\kappa}(\lambda)$ is said to be $\lbrack\delta\rbrack^{<\theta}$-normal if given $B_e\in J$ for $e\in P_\theta(\delta)$, the set of all $a\in P_{\kappa}(\lambda)$ such that $a\in B_e$ for some $e\in P_{|a\cap\theta|}(a\cap\delta)$ lies in $J$. We give necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of such ideals and we describe the least one and we compute its cofinality.
    keywords: S: ico, S: pcf, (set), (normal)
  677. Sh:714
    Juhász, I., Shelah, S., Soukup, L., & Szentmiklóssy, Z. (2003). A tall space with a small bottom. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 131(6), 1907–1916. arXiv: math/0104198 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-03-06662-0 MR: 1955280
    type: article
    abstract: We introduce a general method of constructing locally compact scattered spaces from certain families of sets and then, with the help of this method, we prove that if $\kappa^{<\kappa} = \kappa$ then there is such a space of height $\kappa^+$ with only $\kappa$ many isolated points. This implies that there is a locally compact scattered space of height ${\omega}_2$ with $\omega_1$ isolated points in ZFC, solving an old problem of the first author.
    keywords: O: top, (ba), (gt)
  678. Sh:715
    Shelah, S. (2004). Classification theory for elementary classes with the dependence property—a modest beginning. Sci. Math. Jpn., 59(2), 265–316. arXiv: math/0009056 MR: 2062198
    type: article
    abstract: Our thesis is that for the family of classes of the form EC$(T),T$ a complete first order theory with the dependence property (which is just the negation of the independence property) there is a substantial theory which means: a substantial body of basic results for all such classes and some complimentary results for the first order theories with the independence property, as for the family of stable (and the family of simple) first order theories. We examine some properties.
    keywords: O: alg, (mod), (stal)
  679. Sh:716
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2001). Decompositions of reflexive modules. Arch. Math. (Basel), 76(3), 166–181. arXiv: math/0003165 DOI: 10.1007/s000130050557 MR: 1816987
    type: article
    abstract: We continue [GbSh:568], proving a stronger result under the special continuum hypothesis (CH). The original question of Eklof and Mekler related to dual abelian groups. We want to find a particular example of a dual group, which will provide a negative answer to the question. In order to derive a stronger and also more general result we will concentrate on reflexive modules over countable principal ideal domains $R$. Following H.~Bass, an $R$-module $G$ is reflexive if the evaluation map $\sigma:G\longrightarrow G^{**}$ is an isomorphism. Here $G^*={\rm Hom} (G,R)$ denotes the dual group of $G$. Guided by classical results the question about the existence of a reflexive $R$-module $G$ of infinite rank with $G\not\cong G\oplus R$ is natural. We will use a theory of bilinear forms on free $R$-modules which strengthens our algebraic results in [GbSh:568]. Moreover we want to apply a model theoretic combinatorial theorem from [Sh:e] which allows us to avoid the weak diamond principle. This has the great advantage that the used prediction principle is still similar to the diamond, but holds under CH.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  680. Sh:717
    Eklof, P. C., & Shelah, S. (2002). The structure of \mathrm{Ext}(A,\mathbb Z) and GCH: possible co-Moore spaces. Math. Z., 239(1), 143–157. arXiv: math/0303344 DOI: 10.1007/s002090100288 MR: 1879333
    type: article
    abstract: We consider what ${\rm Ext}(A,{\mathbb{Z}})$ can be when $A$ is torsion-free and ${\rm Hom}(A,{\mathbb{Z}})=0$. We thereby give an answer to a question of Golasi\'{n}ski and Gon\c{c}alves which asks for the divisible Abelian groups which can be the type of a co-Moore space.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  681. Sh:718
    Shelah, S., & Väisänen, P. (2002). The number of L_{\infty\kappa}-equivalent nonisomorphic models for \kappa weakly compact. Fund. Math., 174(2), 97–126. arXiv: math/9911232 DOI: 10.4064/fm174-2-1 MR: 1927234
    type: article
    abstract: For a cardinal $\kappa$ and a model ${\mathcal M}$ of cardinality $\kappa$ let ${\rm No}({\mathcal M})$ denote the number of non-isomorphic models of cardinality $\kappa$ which are $L_{\infty\kappa}$--equivalent to ${\mathcal M}$. In [Sh:133] Shelah established that when $\kappa$ is a weakly compact cardinal and $\mu \leq \kappa$ is a nonzero cardinal, there exists a model ${\mathcal M}$ of cardinality $\kappa$ with ${\rm No}({\mathcal M})=\mu$. We prove here that if $\kappa$ is a weakly compact cardinal, the question of the possible values of ${\rm No}({\mathcal M})$ for models ${\mathcal M}$ of cardinality $\kappa$ is equivalent to the question of the possible numbers of equivalence classes of equivalence relations which are $\Sigma^1_1$-definable over $V_\kappa$. In [ShVa:719] we prove that, consistent wise, the possible numbers of equivalence classes of $\Sigma^1_1$-equivalence relations can be completely controlled under the singular cardinal hypothesis. These results settle the problem of the possible values of ${\rm No}({\mathcal M})$ for models of weakly compact cardinality, provided that the singular cardinal hypothesis holds.
    keywords: M: smt, M: non, (nni), (inf-log), (set-mod), (pure(large)), (ps-dst)
  682. Sh:719
    Shelah, S., & Väisänen, P. (2002). On equivalence relations second order definable over H(\kappa). Fund. Math., 174(1), 1–21. arXiv: math/9911231 DOI: 10.4064/fm174-1-1 MR: 1925484
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\kappa$ be an uncountable regular cardinal. Call an equivalence relation on functions from $\kappa$ into 2 $\Sigma_1^1$-definable over $H(\kappa)$ if there is a first order sentence $\phi$ and a parameter $R\subseteq H(\kappa)$ such that functions $f ,g \in {}^\kappa 2$ are equivalent iff for some $h\in {}^\kappa 2$, the structure $(H(\kappa),\in,R,f,g,h)$ satisfies $\phi$, where $\in$, $R$, $f$, $g$, and $h$ are interpretations of the symbols appearing in $\phi$. All the values $\mu$, $1\leq\mu \leq\kappa^+$ or $\mu=2^\kappa$, are possible numbers of equivalence classes for such a $\Sigma_1^1$-equivalence relation. Additionally, the possibilities are closed under unions of $\leq\kappa$-many cardinals and products of $<\kappa$-many cardinals. We prove that, consistent wise, these are the only restrictions under the singular cardinal hypothesis. The result is that the possible numbers of equivalence classes of $\Sigma_1^1$-equivalence relations might consistent wise be exactly those cardinals which are in a prearranged set, provided that the singular cardinal hypothesis holds and that some necessary conditions are fulfilled.
    keywords: M: smt, (nni), (inf-log), (set-mod), (pure(large)), (ps-dst)
  683. Sh:720
    Kojman, M., & Shelah, S. (2001). Fallen cardinals. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 109(1-2), 117–129. arXiv: math/0009079 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(01)00045-8 MR: 1835242
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that for every singular cardinal $\mu$ of cofinality $\omega$, the complete Boolean algebra ${\rm comp}{\mathcal P}_\mu(\mu)$ contains as a complete subalgebra an isomorphic copy of the collapse algebra ${\rm Comp}\;{\rm Col}(\omega_1,\mu^{\aleph_0})$. Consequently, adding a generic filter to the quotient algebra ${\mathcal P}_\mu(\mu)={\mathcal P}(\mu)/[\mu]^{<\mu}$ collapses $\mu^{\aleph_0}$ to $\aleph_1$. Another corollary is that the Baire number of the space $U(\mu)$ of all uniform ultrafilters over $\mu$ is equal to $\omega_2$. The corollaries affirm two conjectures by Balcar and Simon. The proof uses pcf theory.
    keywords: S: ico, S: pcf, (set), (ba), (pure(for))
  684. Sh:721
    Göbel, R., Shelah, S., & Wallutis, S. L. (2001). On the lattice of cotorsion theories. J. Algebra, 238(1), 292–313. arXiv: math/0103154 DOI: 10.1006/jabr.2000.8619 MR: 1822193
    type: article
    abstract: We discuss the lattice of cotorsion theories for abelian groups. First we show that the sublattice of the well--studied rational cotorsion theories can be identified with the well--known lattice of types. Using a recently developed method for making Ext vanish we also prove that any power set together with the ordinary set inclusion (and thus any poset) can be embedded into the lattice of all cotorsion theories.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  685. Sh:722
    Bartoszyński, T., & Shelah, S. (2001). Continuous images of sets of reals. Topology Appl., 116(2), 243–253. arXiv: math/0001051 DOI: 10.1016/S0166-8641(00)00079-1 MR: 1855966
    type: article
    abstract: We show that, consistently, every uncountable set can be continuously mapped onto a non measure zero set, while there exists an uncountable set whose all continuous images into a Polish space are meager.
    keywords: S: str, (set)
  686. Sh:723
    Shelah, S. (2001). Consistently there is no non trivial ccc forcing notion with the Sacks or Laver property. Combinatorica, 21(2), 309–319. arXiv: math/0003139 DOI: 10.1007/s004930100027 MR: 1832454
    type: article
    abstract: The result in the title answers a problem of Boban Velickovic. A definable version of it (that is for Souslin forcing notions) has been answered in [Sh 480], and our proof follows it. Independently Velickovic proved this consistency, following [Sh 480] and some of his works, proving it from PFA and from OCA. We prove that moreover, consistently there is no ccc forcing with the Laver property. Note that if cov(meagre)=continuum (which follows e.g. from PFA) then there is a (non principal) Ramsey ultrafilter on $\omega$ hence a forcing notion with the Laver property. So the results are incomparable.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (pure(for))
  687. Sh:724
    Shelah, S. (2004). On nice equivalence relations on ^\lambda 2. Arch. Math. Logic, 43(1), 31–64. arXiv: math/0009064 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-003-0183-1 MR: 2036248
    type: article
    abstract: The main question here is the possible generalization of the following theorem on ``simple" equivalence relation on ${}^\omega 2$ to higher cardinals. Theorem: (1) Assume that (a) $E$ is a Borel 2-place relation on ${}^\omega 2$, (b) $E$ is an equivalence relation, (c) if $\eta,\nu\in{}^\omega 2$ and $(\exists!n)(\eta(n)\neq \nu(n))$, then $\eta,\nu$ are not $E$--equivalent. Then there is a perfect subset of ${}^\omega 2$ of pairwise non $E$-equivalent members. (2) Instead of ``$E$ is Borel'', ``$E$ is analytic (or even a Borel combination of analytic relations)'' is enough. (3) If $E$ is a $\Pi^1_2$ relation which is an equivalence relation satisfying clauses (b)+(c) in $V^{\rm Cohen}$, then the conclusion of (1) holds.
    keywords: S: dst, S: ods, (set), (ps-dst)
  688. Sh:725
    Mildenberger, H., & Shelah, S. (2004). On needed reals. Israel J. Math., 141, 1–37. arXiv: math/0104276 DOI: 10.1007/BF02772209 MR: 2063023
    type: article
    abstract: Following Blass, we call a real $a$ ``needed'' for a binary relation $R$ on the reals if in every $R$-adequate set we find an element from which $a$ is Turing computable. We show that every real needed for ${\bf Cof}({\mathcal N})$ is hyperarithmetic. Replacing ``$R$-adequate'' by ``$R$-adequate with minimal cardinality'' we get related notion of being ``weakly needed''. We show that is is consistent that the two notions do not coincide for the reaping relation. (They coincide in many models.) We show that not all hyperarithmetical reals are needed for the reaping relation. This answers some questions asked by Blass at the Oberwolfach conference in December 1999.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  689. Sh:726
    Shelah, S., & Väänänen, J. A. (2005). A note on extensions of infinitary logic. Arch. Math. Logic, 44(1), 63–69. arXiv: math/0009080 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-004-0212-8 MR: 2116833
    type: article
    abstract: We show that a strong form of the so called Lindstr\"om's Theorem fails to generalize to extensions of $L_{\kappa\omega}$ and $L_{\kappa\kappa}$: For weakly compact $\kappa$ there is no strongest extension of $L_{\kappa\omega}$ with the $(\kappa,\kappa)$-compactness property and the L\"owenheim-Skolem theorem down to $\kappa$. With an additional set-theoretic assumption, there is no strongest extension of $L_{\kappa\kappa}$ with the $(\kappa,\kappa)$-compactness property and the L\"owenheim-Skolem theorem down to $<\kappa$.
    keywords: M: smt, (set), (inf-log), (pure(large))
  690. Sh:727
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2001). Reflexive subgroups of the Baer-Specker group and Martin’s axiom. In Abelian groups, rings and modules (Perth, 2000), Vol. 273, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, pp. 145–158. arXiv: math/0009062 DOI: 10.1090/conm/273/04431 MR: 1817159
    type: article
    abstract: In two recent papers we answered a question raised in the book by Eklof and Mekler (p. 455, Problem 12) under the set theoretical hypothesis of $\diamondsuit_{\aleph_1}$ which holds in many models of set theory, respectively of the special continuum hypothesis (CH). The objects are reflexive modules over countable principal ideal domains $R$, which are not fields. Following H. Bass, an $R$-module $G$ is reflexive if the evaluation map $\sigma: G\longrightarrow G^{**}$ is an isomorphism. Here $G^*={\rm Hom}(G, R)$ denotes the dual module of $G$. We proved the existence of reflexive $R$-modules $G$ of infinite rank with $G \not\cong G \oplus R$, which provide (even essentially indecomposable) counter examples to the question mentioned above. Is CH a necessary condition to find `nasty' reflexive modules? In the last part of this paper we will show (assuming the existence of supercompact cardinals) that large reflexive modules always have large summands. So at least being essentially indecomposable needs an additional set theoretic assumption. However the assumption need not be CH as shown in the first part of this paper. We will use Martin's axiom to find reflexive modules with the above decomposition which are submodules of the Baer-Specker module $R^\omega$.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  691. Sh:728
    Kennedy, J. C., & Shelah, S. (2003). On embedding models of arithmetic of cardinality \aleph_1 into reduced powers. Fund. Math., 176(1), 17–24. arXiv: math/0105134 DOI: 10.4064/fm176-1-2 MR: 1971470
    type: article
    abstract: In the early 1970's S.Tennenbaum proved that all countable models of $PA^- + \forall_1 -Th({\mathbb N})$ are embeddable into the reduced product ${\mathbb N}^\omega/{\mathcal F}$, where ${\mathcal F}$ is the cofinite filter. In this paper we show that if $M$ is a model of $PA^- + \forall_1 -Th({\mathbb N})$, and $|M|=\aleph_1$, then $M$ is embeddable into ${\mathbb N}^\omega/D$, where $D$ is any regular filter on $\omega$.
    keywords: M: odm, (mod), (univ), (up)
  692. Sh:729
    Shelah, S., & Strüngmann, L. H. (2001). The failure of the uncountable non-commutative Specker phenomenon. J. Group Theory, 4(4), 417–426. arXiv: math/0009045 DOI: 10.1515/jgth.2001.031 MR: 1859179
    type: article
    abstract: Higman proved in 1952 that every free group is non-commutatively slender, this is to say that if $G$ is a free group and $h$ is a homomorphism from the countable complete free product $\bigotimes_\omega{\mathbb Z}$ to $G$, then there exists a finite subset $F\subseteq\omega$ and a homomorphism $\bar{h}: *_{i\in F} {\mathbb Z}\longrightarrow G$ such that $h=\bar{h}\rho_F$, where $\rho_F$ is the natural map from $\bigotimes_{i\in\omega}{\mathbb Z}$ to $*_{i\in F}{\mathbb Z}$. Corresponding to the abelian case this phenomenon was called the non-commutative Specker Phenomenon. In this paper we show that Higman's result fails if one passes from countable to uncountable. In particular, we show that for non-trivial groups $G_\alpha$ ($\alpha\in\lambda$) and uncountable cardinal $\lambda$ there are $2^{2^\lambda}$ homomorphisms from the complete free product of the $G_\alpha$'s to the ring of integers.
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (stal), (grp)
  693. Sh:730
    Shelah, S. (2000). A space with only Borel subsets. Period. Math. Hungar., 40(2), 81–84. arXiv: math/0009047 DOI: 10.1023/A:1010364023601 MR: 1805307
    type: article
    abstract: Mikl\'os Laczkovich asked if there exists a Haussdorff (or even normal) space in which every subset is Borel yet it is not meager. The motivation of the last condition is that under ${\rm MA}_\kappa$ every subspace of the reals of cardinality $\kappa$ has the property that all subsets are ${\rm F}_\sigma$ however Martin's axiom also implies that these subsets are meager. Here we answer Laczkovich' question.
    keywords: S: str, (gt)
  694. Sh:731
    Mildenberger, H., & Shelah, S. (2002). The relative consistency of \mathfrak g<\mathrm{cf}(\mathrm{Sym}(\omega)). J. Symbolic Logic, 67(1), 297–314. arXiv: math/0009077 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1190150045 MR: 1889552
    type: article
    abstract: We prove the consistency result from the title. By forcing we construct a model of $\mathfrak{g}=\aleph_1$, $\mathfrak{b}={\rm cf}({\rm Sym}(\omega))=\aleph_2$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (iter), (inv)
  695. Sh:732
    Bartoszyński, T., & Shelah, S. (2002). Perfectly meager sets and universally null sets. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 130(12), 3701–3711. arXiv: math/0102011 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-02-06465-1 MR: 1920051
    type: article
    abstract: For a set of reals $X$: (a) $X$ is perfectly meager (PM) if for every perfect set $P\subseteq{\mathbb R}$, $P\cap X$ is meager in $P$. (b) $X$ is universal null (UN) if every Borel isomorphic image of $X$ has Lebesgue measure zero. We show that it is consistent with ZFC that PM is a subset of UN.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (leb), (meag)
  696. Sh:733
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2001). Historic forcing for depth. Colloq. Math., 89(1), 99–115. arXiv: math/0006219 DOI: 10.4064/cm89-1-7 MR: 1853418
    type: article
    abstract: We show that, consistently, for some regular cardinals $\theta<\lambda$, there exist a Boolean algebra $B$ such that $|B|= \lambda^+$ and for every subalgebra $B'\subseteq B$ of size $\lambda^+$ we have ${\rm Depth}(B')=\theta$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (ba), (inv(ba))
  697. Sh:735
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (2002). Martin’s axiom is consistent with the existence of nowhere trivial automorphisms. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 130(7), 2097–2106. arXiv: math/0011166 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-01-06280-3 MR: 1896046
    type: article
    abstract: Martin's~Axiom does not imply that all automorphisms of ${\mathcal P}({\mathbb N})/[{\mathbb N}]^{<\aleph_0}$ are somewhere trivial.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (auto)
  698. Sh:736
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2006). Measured creatures. Israel J. Math., 151, 61–110. arXiv: math/0010070 DOI: 10.1007/BF02777356 MR: 2214118
    type: article
    abstract: Using forcing with measured creatures we build a universe of set theory in which (a) every sup-measurable function $f:{\mathbb R}^2\longrightarrow{\mathbb R}$ is measurable, and (b) every function $f:{\mathbb R}\longrightarrow{\mathbb R}$ is continuous on a non-measurable set. This answers von Weizs\"acker's problem (see Fremlin's list of problems) and a question of Balcerzak, Ciesielski and Kharazishvili.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (creatures)
  699. Sh:737
    Goldstern, M., & Shelah, S. (2002). Clones on regular cardinals. Fund. Math., 173(1), 1–20. arXiv: math/0005273 DOI: 10.4064/fm173-1-1 MR: 1899044
    type: article
    abstract: We investigate the structure of the lattice of clones on an infinite set $X$. We first observe that ultrafilters naturally induce clones; this yields a simple proof of Rosenberg's theorem: there are $2^{2^{\lambda}}$ many maximal (= ``precomplete'') clones on a set of size~$\lambda$. The clones we construct do not contain all unary functions. We then investigate clones that do contain all unary functions. Using a strong negative partition theorem we show that for many cardinals $\lambda$ (in particular, for all successors of regulars) there are $2^{2^\lambda }$ many such clones on a set of size $\lambda$. Finally, we show that on a weakly compact cardinal there are exactly 2 maximal clones which contain all unary functions.
    keywords: O: alg, (ua)
  700. Sh:738
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2003). Philip Hall’s problem on non-abelian splitters. Math. Proc. Cambridge Philos. Soc., 134(1), 23–31. arXiv: math/0009091 DOI: 10.1017/S0305004102006096 MR: 1937789
    type: article
    abstract: Philip Hall raised around 1965 the following question which is stated in the Kourovka Notebook: {\it Is there a non-trivial group which is isomorphic with every proper extension of itself by itself?} We will decompose the problem into two parts: We want to find non-commutative splitters, that are groups $G\neq 1$ with ${\rm Ext}(G,G)=1$. The class of splitters fortunately is quite large so that extra properties can be added to $G$. We can consider groups $G$ with the following properties: There is a complete group $L$ with cartesian product $L^\omega\cong G$, ${\rm Hom}(L^\omega, S_\omega)=0$ ($S_\omega$ the infinite symmetric group acting on $\omega$) and ${\rm End}(L,L)={\rm Inn} L\cup\{0\}$. We will show that these properties ensure that $G$ is a splitter and hence obviously a Hall-group in the above sense. Then we will apply a recent result from our joint paper [GbSh:739] which also shows that such groups exist, in fact there is a class of Hall-groups which is not a set.
    keywords: O: alg, (stal), (grp)
  701. Sh:739
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2002). Constructing simple groups for localizations. Comm. Algebra, 30(2), 809–837. arXiv: math/0009089 DOI: 10.1081/AGB-120013184 MR: 1883027
    type: article
    abstract: A group homomorphism $\eta: A\to H$ is called a {\it localization} of $A$ if every homomorphism $\varphi:A\to H$ can be `extended uniquely' to a homomorphism $\Phi:H\to H$ in the sense that $\Phi\eta=\varphi$. This categorical concepts, obviously not depending on the notion of groups, extends classical localizations as known for rings and modules. Moreover this setting has interesting applications in homotopy theory. For localizations $\eta:A\to H$ of (almost) commutative structures $A$ often $H$ resembles properties of $A$, e.g. size or satisfying certain systems of equalities and non-equalities. Perhaps the best known example is that localizations of finite abelian groups are finite abelian groups. This is no longer the case if $A$ is a finite (non-abelian) group. Libman showed that $A_n\to SO_{n-1}({\mathbb R})$ for a natural embedding of the alternating group $A_n$ is a localization if $n$ even and $n\geq 10$. Answering an immediate question by Dror Farjoun and assuming the generalized continuum hypothesis GCH we recently showed in [GRSh:701] that any non-abelian finite simple has arbitrarily large localizations. In this paper we want to remove GCH so that the result becomes valid in ordinary set theory. At the same time we want to generalize the statement for a larger class of $A$'s.
    keywords: M: non, O: alg, (stal), (grp)
  702. Sh:740
    Göbel, R., Paras, A. T., & Shelah, S. (2002). Groups isomorphic to all their non-trivial normal subgroups. Israel J. Math., 129, 21–27. arXiv: math/0009088 DOI: 10.1007/BF02773151 MR: 1910930
    type: article
    abstract: In answer to a question of P. Hall, we supply another construction of a group which is isomorphic to each of its non--trivial normal subgroups.
    keywords: O: alg, (stal), (grp)
  703. Sh:741
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2002). Radicals and Plotkin’s problem concerning geometrically equivalent groups. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 130(3), 673–674. arXiv: math/0010303 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-01-06108-1 MR: 1866018
    type: article
    abstract: If $G$ and $X$ are groups and $N$ is a normal subgroup of $X$, then the $G-$closure of $N$ in $X$ is the normal subgroup ${\overline X}^G=\bigcap\{{\rm ker}\varphi|\varphi:X\rightarrow G, \text{ with } N \subseteq{\rm ker}\varphi\}$ of $X$. In particular, ${\overline 1}^G = R_GX$ is the $G-$radical of $X$. Plotkin calls two groups $G$ and $H$ geometrically equivalent, written $G\sim H$, if for any free group $F$ of finite rank and any normal subgroup $N$ of $F$ the $G$--closure and the $H$--closure of $N$ in $F$ are the same. Quasiidentities are formulas of the form $(\bigwedge_{i\le n} w_i = 1 \rightarrow w =1)$ for any words $w, w_i \ (i\le n)$ in a free group. Generally geometrically equivalent groups satisfy the same quasiidentiies. Plotkin showed that nilpotent groups $G$ and $H$ satisfy the same quasiidenties if and only if $G$ and $H$ are geometrically equivalent. Hence he conjectured that this might hold for any pair of groups. We provide a counterexample.
    keywords: O: alg, (stal), (grp)
  704. Sh:742
    Göbel, R., Shelah, S., & Wallutis, S. L. (2003). On universal and epi-universal locally nilpotent groups. Illinois J. Math., 47(1-2), 223–236. arXiv: math/0112252 http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.ijm/1258488149 MR: 2031317
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper we mainly consider the class $LN$ of all locally nilpotent groups. We first show that there is no universal group in $LN_\lambda$ if $\lambda$ is a cardinal such that $\lambda=\lambda^{\aleph_0}$; here we call a group $G$ {\em universal} (in $LN_\lambda$) if any group $H\in LN_\lambda$ can be embedded into $G$ where $LN_\lambda$ denotes the class of all locally nilpotent groups of cardinality at most $\lambda$. However, our main interest is the construction of torsion-free epi-universal groups in $LN_\lambda$, where $G\in LN_\lambda$ is said to be {\em epi-universal} if any group $H\in LN_\lambda$ is an epimorphic image of $G$. Thus we give an affirmative answer to a question by Plotkin. To prove the torsion-freeness of the constructed locally nilpotent group we adjust the well-known commutator collecting process due to P. Hall to our situation. Finally, we briefly discuss how to use the same methods as for the class $LN$ for other canonical classes of groups to construct epi-universal objects.
    keywords: O: alg, (stal), (univ), (grp)
  705. Sh:743
    Droste, M., & Shelah, S. (2002). Outer automorphism groups of ordered permutation groups. Forum Math., 14(4), 605–621. arXiv: math/0010304 DOI: 10.1515/form.2002.026 MR: 1900174
    type: article
    abstract: An infinite linearly ordered set $(S,\leq)$ is called doubly homogeneous if its automorphism group $A(S)$ acts $2$-transitively on it. We show that any group $G$ arises as outer automorphism group $G\cong{\rm Out}(A(S))$ of the automorphism group $A(S)$, for some doubly homogeneous chain $(S,\leq)$.
    keywords: O: alg, (stal), (auto)
  706. Sh:744
    Shelah, S. (2003). A countable structure does not have a free uncountable automorphism group. Bull. London Math. Soc., 35(1), 1–7. arXiv: math/0010305 DOI: 10.1112/S0024609302001534 MR: 1934424
    type: article
    abstract: Solecki proved that the group of automorphisms of a countable structure cannot be an uncountable free abelian group. See more in Just, Shelah and Thomas [JShT:654] where as a by product we can say something on on uncountable structures. We prove here the following Theorem: If ${\mathbb A}$ is a countable model, then ${\rm Aut}(M)$ cannot be a free uncountable group.
    keywords: O: alg, (stal), (graph)
  707. Sh:745
    Nešetřil, J., & Shelah, S. (2003). On the order of countable graphs. European J. Combin., 24(6), 649–663. arXiv: math/0404319 DOI: 10.1016/S0195-6698(03)00064-7 MR: 1995579
    type: article
    abstract: A set of graphs is said to be {\em independent} if there is no homomorphism between distinct graphs from the set. We consider the existence problems related to the independent sets of countable graphs. While the maximal size of an independent set of countable graphs is $2^\omega$ the {\em On Line} problem of extending an independent set to a larger independent set is much harder. We prove here that singletons can be extended (``partnership theorem''). While this is the best possible in general, we give structural conditions which guarantee independent extensions of larger independent sets. This is related to universal graphs, rigid graphs and to the density problem for countable graphs.
    keywords: S: ico
  708. Sh:746
    Larson, P. B., & Shelah, S. (2003). Bounding by canonical functions, with CH. J. Math. Log., 3(2), 193–215. arXiv: math/0011187 DOI: 10.1142/S021906130300025X MR: 2030084
    type: article
    abstract: We show that that a certain class of semi-proper iterations does not add $\omega$-sequences. As a result, starting from suitable large cardinals one can obtain a model in which the Continuum Hypothesis holds and every function from $\omega_{1}$ to $\omega_{1}$ is bounded by a canonical function on a club, and so $\omega_{1}$ is the $\omega_{2}$-nd canonical function.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (iter), (normal), (large)
  709. Sh:747
    Goldstern, M., & Shelah, S. (2009). Large intervals in the clone lattice. Algebra Universalis, 62(4), 367–374. arXiv: math/0208066 DOI: 10.1007/s00012-010-0047-6 MR: 2670171
    type: article
    abstract: We give three examples of large intervals in the lattice of (local) clones on an infinite set $X$, by exhibiting clones ${\mathcal C}_1$, ${\mathcal C}_2$, ${\mathcal C}_3$ such that: (1) the interval $[{\mathcal C}_1,{\mathcal O}]$ in the lattice of local clones is (as a lattice) isomorphic to $\{0,1,2,\ldots\}$ under the divisibility relation, (2) the interval $[{\mathcal C}_2, {\mathcal O}]$ in the lattice of local clones is isomorphic to the congruence lattice of an arbitrary semilattice, (3) the interval $[{\mathcal C}_3,{\mathcal O}]$ in the lattice of all clones is isomorphic to the lattice of all filters on $X$. These examples explain the difficulty of obtaining a satisfactory analysis of the clone lattice on infinite sets. In particular, (1) shows that the lattice of local clones is not dually atomic.
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (stal), (ua)
  710. Sh:748
    Kikyo, H., & Shelah, S. (2002). The strict order property and generic automorphisms. J. Symbolic Logic, 67(1), 214–216. arXiv: math/0010306 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1190150038 MR: 1889545
    type: article
    abstract: If $T$ is an model complete theory with the strict order property, then the theory of the models of $T$ with an automorphism has no model companion.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (auto)
  711. Sh:749
    Eklof, P. C., & Shelah, S. (2003). On the existence of precovers. Illinois J. Math., 47(1-2), 173–188. arXiv: math/0011228 http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.ijm/1258488146 MR: 2031314
    type: article
    abstract: It is proved undecidable in ZFC + GCH whether every ${\mathbb Z}$-module has a $^{\perp}\{{\mathbb Z}\}$-precover.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  712. Sh:750
    Shelah, S. (2011). On \lambda strong homogeneity existence for cofinality logic. Cubo, 13(2), 59–72. arXiv: 0902.0439 DOI: 10.4067/s0719-06462011000200003 MR: 2908010
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  713. Sh:751
    Eda, K., & Shelah, S. (2002). The non-commutative Specker phenomenon in the uncountable case. J. Algebra, 252(1), 22–26. arXiv: math/0011231 DOI: 10.1016/S0021-8693(02)00045-5 MR: 1922382
    type: article
    abstract: An infinitary version of the notion of free products has been introduced and investigated by G.Higman. Let $G_i$ (for $i\in I$) be groups and $\ast_{i\in X} G_i$ the free product of $G_i$ ($i\in X$) for $X \Subset I$ and $ p _{XY}:\ast_{i\in Y} G_{i}\rightarrow \ast_{i\in X} G_{i}$ the canonical homomorphism for $X\subseteq Y \Subset I.$ ( $X\Subset I$ denotes that $X$ is a finite subset of $I$.) Then, the unrestricted free product is the inverse limit $\lim (\ast_{i\in X} G_i, p_{XY}: X\subseteq Y\Subset I).$ We remark $\ast_{i\in\emptyset} G_i=\{e\}$. We prove: Theorem: Let $F$ be a free group. Then, for each homomorphism $h: \lim \ast G_i \to F$ there exist countably complete ultrafilters $u_0,\cdots,u_m$ on $I$ such that $h = h\cdot p_{U_0\cup \cdots\cup U_m}$ for every $U_0\in u_0,\cdots ,U_m\in u_m$. If the cardinality of the index set $I$ is less than the least measurable cardinal, then there exists a finite subset $X_0$ of $I$ and a homomorphism $\overline{h}:\ast _{i\in X_0}G_i\to F$ such that $h=\overline{h}\cdot p_{X_0}$, where $p_{X_0}:\lim\ast G_i\to \ast_{i\in X_0}G_i$ is the canonical projection.
    keywords: O: alg, (stal), (grp)
  714. Sh:752
    Eklof, P. C., & Shelah, S. (2002). Whitehead modules over large principal ideal domains. Forum Math., 14(3), 477–482. arXiv: math/0011230 DOI: 10.1515/form.2002.021 MR: 1899295
    type: article
    abstract: We consider the Whitehead problem for principal ideal domains of large size. It is proved, in ZFC, that some p.i.d.'s of size $\geq\aleph_{2}$ have non-free Whitehead modules even though they are not complete discrete valuation rings.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  715. Sh:753
    Mildenberger, H., & Shelah, S. (2002). The splitting number can be smaller than the matrix chaos number. Fund. Math., 171(2), 167–176. arXiv: math/0011188 DOI: 10.4064/fm171-2-4 MR: 1880382
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\chi$ be the minimum cardinal of a subset of $2^\omega$ that cannot be made convergent by multiplication with a single Toeplitz matrix. By an application of creature forcing we show that ${\mathfrak s}<\chi$ is consistent. We thus answer a question by Vojt\'a\v{s}. We give two kinds of models for the strict inequality. The first is the combination of an $\aleph_2$-iteration of some proper forcing with adding $\aleph_1$ random reals. The second kind of models is got by adding $\delta$ random reals to a model of ${\rm MA}_{<\kappa}$ for some $\delta\in [\aleph_1,\kappa)$. It was a conjecture of Blass that ${\mathfrak s}=\aleph_1<\chi= \kappa$ holds in such a model. For the analysis of the second model we again use the creature forcing from the first model.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (iter), (inv)
  716. Sh:754
    Shelah, S., & Strüngmann, L. H. (2003). It is consistent with ZFC that B_1-groups are not B_2. Forum Math., 15(4), 507–524. arXiv: math/0012172 DOI: 10.1515/form.2003.028 MR: 1978332
    type: article
    abstract: A torsion-free abelian group $B$ of arbitrary rank is called a $B_1$-group if ${\rm Bext}^1(B,T)=0$ for every torsion abelian group $T$, where ${\rm Bext}^1$ denotes the group of equivalence classes of all balanced exact extensions of $T$ by $B$. It is a long-standing problem whether or not the class of $B_1$-groups coincides with the class of $B_2$-groups. A torsion-free abelian group $B$ is called a $B_2$-group if there exists a continuous well-ordered ascending chain of pure subgroups, $0=B_0 \subset B_1 \subset\cdots\subset B_\alpha\subset\cdots\subset B_\lambda=B= \bigcup\limits_{\alpha\in\lambda} B_\alpha$ such that $B_{\alpha+1} =B_\alpha+G_\alpha$ for every $\alpha\in\lambda$ for some finite rank Butler group $G_\alpha.$ Both, $B_1$-groups and $B_2$-groups are natural generalizations of finite rank Butler groups to the infinite rank case and it is known that every $B_2$-group is a $B_1$-group. Moreover, assuming $V=L$ it was proven that the two classes coincide. Here we demonstrate that it is undecidable in ZFC whether or not all $B_1$-groups are $B_2$-groups. Using Cohen forcing we prove that there is a model of ZFC in which there exists a $B_1$-group that is not a $B_2$-group.
    keywords: S: for, (ab)
  717. Sh:755
    Shelah, S. (2002). Weak diamond. Sci. Math. Jpn., 55(3), 531–538. arXiv: math/0107207 MR: 1901038
    type: article
    abstract: Under some cardinal arithmetic assumptions, we prove that every stationary of $\lambda$ of a right cofinality has the weak diamond. This is a strong negation of uniformization. We then deal with a weaker version of the weak diamond- colouring restrictions. We then deal with semi- saturated (normal) filters.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (normal), (wd)
  718. Sh:756
    Hyttinen, T., & Shelah, S. (2002). Forcing a Boolean algebra with predesigned automorphism group. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 130(10), 2837–2843. arXiv: math/0102044 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-02-06399-2 MR: 1908905
    type: article
    abstract: For suitable groups $G$ we will show that one can add a Boolean algebra $B$ by forcing in such a way that $Aut(B)$ is almost isomorphic to $G$. In particular, we will give a positive answer to the following question due to J. Roitman: Is $\aleph_{\omega}$ a possible number of automorphisms of a rich Boolean algebra?
    keywords: S: for, (set), (ba), (auto)
  719. Sh:757
    Shelah, S. (2004). Quite complete real closed fields. Israel J. Math., 142, 261–272. arXiv: math/0112212 DOI: 10.1007/BF02771536 MR: 2085719
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that any ordered field can be extended to one for which every decreasing sequence, of closed intervals has a non empty intersection.
    keywords: O: alg, (stal)
  720. Sh:758
    Matsubara, Y., & Shelah, S. (2002). Nowhere precipitousness of the non-stationary ideal over \mathcal P_{\kappa}\lambda. J. Math. Log., 2(1), 81–89. arXiv: math/0102045 DOI: 10.1142/S021906130200014X MR: 1900548
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that if $\lambda$ is a strong limit singular cardinal and $\kappa$ a regular uncountable cardinal $<\lambda$, then $NS_{\kappa\lambda}$, the non-stationary ideal over ${\mathcal P}_{\kappa}\lambda$, is nowhere precipitous. We also show that under the same hypothesis every stationary subset of ${\mathcal P}_{\kappa}\lambda$ can be partitioned into $\lambda^{< \kappa}$ disjoint stationary sets.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (normal), (app(pcf))
  721. Sh:759
    Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (2001). Model companions of T_\mathrm{Aut} for stable T. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 42(3), 129–142 (2003). arXiv: math/0105136 DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1063372196 MR: 2010177
    type: article
    abstract: Let $T$ be a complete first order theory in a countable relational language $L$. We assume relation symbols have been added to make each formula equivalent to a predicate. Adjoin a new unary function symbol $\sigma$ to obtain the language $L_\sigma$; $T_\sigma$ is obtained by adding axioms asserting that $\sigma$ is an $L$-automorphism. We provide necessary and sufficient conditions for $T_{\rm Aut}$ to have a model companion when $T$ is stable. Namely, we introduce a new condition: $T$ admits obstructions, and show that $T_{\rm Aut}$ has a model companion iff and only if $T$ does not admit obstructions. This condition is weakening of the finite cover property: if a stable theory $T$ has the finite cover property then $T$ admits obstructions.
    keywords: M: cla, O: alg, (mod), (auto), (sta)
  722. Sh:760
    Blass, A. R., Gurevich, Y., & Shelah, S. (2002). On polynomial time computation over unordered structures. J. Symbolic Logic, 67(3), 1093–1125. arXiv: math/0102059 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1190150152 MR: 1926601
    type: article
    abstract: This paper is motivated by the question whether there exists a logic capturing polynomial time computation over unordered structures. We consider several algorithmic problems near the border of the known, logically defined complexity classes contained in polynomial time. We show that fixpoint logic plus counting is stronger than might be expected, in that it can express the existence of a complete matching in a bipartite graph. We revisit the known examples that separate polynomial time from fixpoint plus counting. We show that the examples in a paper of Cai, F\"urer, and Immerman, when suitably padded, are in choiceless polynomial time yet not in fixpoint plus counting. Without padding, they remain in polynomial time but appear not to be in choiceless polynomial time plus counting. Similar results hold for the multipede examples of Gurevich and Shelah, except that their final version of multipedes is, in a sense, already suitably padded. Finally, we describe another plausible candidate, involving determinants, for the task of separating polynomial time from choiceless polynomial time plus counting.
    keywords: O: fin, (fmt)
  723. Sh:761
    Shelah, S. (2003). A partition relation using strongly compact cardinals. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 131(8), 2585–2592. arXiv: math/0103155 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-02-06789-8 MR: 1974659
    type: article
    abstract: If $\kappa$ is strongly compact, $\lambda>\kappa$ is regular, then $(2^{<\lambda})^+\to (\lambda+\eta)^2_\theta$ holds for $\eta$, $\theta<\kappa$.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (pc), (pure(large))
  724. Sh:762
    Brendle, J., & Shelah, S. (2003). Evasion and prediction. IV. Strong forms of constant prediction. Arch. Math. Logic, 42(4), 349–360. arXiv: math/0103153 DOI: 10.1007/s001530200143 MR: 2018086
    type: article
    abstract: Say that a function $\pi:n^{<\omega}\to n$ (henceforth called a predictor) $k$--constantly predicts a real $x\in n^\omega$ if for almost all intervals $I$ of length $k$, there is $i\in I$ such that $x(i)=\pi(x\restriction i)$. We study the $k$--constant prediction number ${\mathfrak v}_n^{\rm const}(k)$, that is, the size of the least family of predictors needed to $k$--constantly predict all reals, for different values of $n$ and $k$, and investigate their relationship.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (inv)
  725. Sh:763
    Fuchino, S., Greenberg, N., & Shelah, S. (2006). Models of real-valued measurability. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 142(1-3), 380–397. arXiv: math/0601087 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2006.04.003 MR: 2250550
    See [Sh:E85]

    type: article
    abstract: Solovay's random-real forcing is the standard way of producing real-valued measurable cardinals. Following questions of Fremlin, by giving a new construction, we show that there are combinatorial, measure-theoretic properties of Solovay's model that do not follow from the existence of real-valued measurability.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (leb)
  726. Sh:764
    Shelah, S., & Shioya, M. (2006). Nonreflecting stationary sets in \mathcal P_\kappa\lambda. Adv. Math., 199(1), 185–191. arXiv: math/0405013 DOI: 10.1016/j.aim.2005.01.012 MR: 2187403
    See [Sh:E86]

    type: article
    abstract: Let $\kappa$ be a regular uncountable cardinal and $\lambda\geq \kappa^+$. The principle of stationary reflection for ${\mathcal P}_\kappa\lambda$ has been successful in settling problems of infinite combinatorics in the case $\kappa=\omega_1$. For a greater $\kappa$ the principle is known to fail at some $\lambda$. This note shows that it fails at every $\lambda$ if $\kappa$ is the successor of a regular uncountable cardinal or $\kappa$ is countably closed.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (normal), (ref)
  727. Sh:765
    Juhász, I., Shelah, S., Soukup, L., & Szentmiklóssy, Z. (2004). Cardinal sequences and Cohen real extensions. Fund. Math., 181(1), 75–88. arXiv: math/0404322 DOI: 10.4064/fm181-1-3 MR: 2071695
    type: article
    abstract: We show that if we add any number of Cohen reals to the ground model then, in the generic extension, a locally compact scattered space has at most $(2^{\aleph_0})^V$ many levels of size $\omega$. We also give a complete $ZFC$ characterization of the cardinal sequences of regular scattered spaces. Although the classes of the regular and of the $0$-dimensional scattered spaces are different, we prove that they have the same cardinal sequences.
    keywords: O: top, (set), (ba), (gt)
  728. Sh:766
    Fuchs, L., & Shelah, S. (2003). On a non-vanishing Ext. Rend. Sem. Mat. Univ. Padova, 109, 235–239. arXiv: math/0405015 MR: 1997989
    type: article
    abstract: The existence of valuation domains admitting non-standard uniserial modules for which certain Exts do not vanish was proved under Jensen's Diamond Principle. In this note, the same is verified using the ZFC axioms alone.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (wh)
  729. Sh:767
    Shelah, S., & Tsuboi, A. (2002). Definability of initial segments. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic, 43(2), 65–73 (2003). arXiv: math/0104277 DOI: 10.1305/ndjfl/1071509428 MR: 2033316
    type: article
    abstract: We consider implicit definability of the standard part $\{0,1,...\}$ in nonstandard models of Peano arithmetic (PA), and we ask whether there is a model of PA in which the standard part is implicitly definable. In \S 1, we define a certain class of formulas, and show that in any model of PA the standard part is not implicitly defined by using such formulas. In \S 2 we construct a model of PA in which the standard part is implicitly defined. To construct such a model, first we assume a set theoretic hypothesis $\diamondsuit_{S_\lambda^{\lambda^+}}$, which is an assertion of the existence of a very general set. Then we shall eliminate the hypothesis using absoluteness for the existence of a model having a tree structure with a certain property.
    keywords: M: non, (mod)
  730. Sh:768
    Shelah, S., & Tsaban, B. (2003). Critical cardinalities and additivity properties of combinatorial notions of smallness. J. Appl. Anal., 9(2), 149–162. arXiv: math/0304019 DOI: 10.1515/JAA.2003.149 MR: 2021285
    type: article
    abstract: Motivated by the minimal tower problem, an earlier work studied diagonalizations of covers where the covers are related to linear quasiorders ($\tau$-covers). We deal with two types of combinatorial questions which arise from this study. (a) Two new cardinals introduced in the topological study are expressed in terms of well known cardinals characteristics of the continuum. (b) We study the additivity numbers of the combinatorial notions corresponding to the topological diagonalization notions. This gives new insights on the structure of the eventual dominance ordering on the Baire space, the almost inclusion ordering on the Rothberger space, and the interactions between them.
    keywords: S: ico, (inv)
  731. Sh:769
    Kennedy, J. C., & Shelah, S. (2002). On regular reduced products. J. Symbolic Logic, 67(3), 1169–1177. arXiv: math/0105135 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1190150156 MR: 1926605
    type: article
    abstract: Assume $\langle\aleph_0,\aleph_1\rangle\rightarrow\langle \lambda,\lambda^+\rangle$. Assume $M$ is a model of a first order theory $T$ of cardinality at most $\lambda^+$ in a vocabulary ${\mathcal L}(T)$ of cardinality $\leq\lambda$. Let $N$ be a model with the same vocabulary. Let $\Delta$ be a set of first order formulas in ${\mathcal L}(T)$ and let $D$ be a regular filter on $\lambda$. Then $M$ is $\Delta$-embeddable into the reduced power $N^\lambda/D$, provided that every $\Delta$-existential formula true in $M$ is true also in $N$. We obtain the following corollary: for $M$ as above and $D$ a regular ultrafilter over $\lambda$, $M^\lambda/ D$ is $\lambda^{++}$-universal. Our second result is as follows: For $i<\mu$ let $M_i$ and $N_i$ be elementarily equivalent models of a vocabulary which has has cardinality $\le\lambda$. Suppose $D$ is a regular filter on $\mu$ and $\langle \aleph_0,\aleph_1\rangle\rightarrow\langle\lambda,\lambda^+ \rangle$ holds. We show that then the second player has a winning strategy in the Ehrenfeucht-Fraisse game of length $\lambda^+$ on $\prod_i M_i/D$ and $\prod_i N_i/D$. This yields the following corollary: Assume GCH and $\lambda$ regular (or just $\langle\aleph_0,\aleph_1 \rangle \rightarrow \langle \lambda,\lambda^+ \rangle$ and $2^\lambda=\lambda^+$). For $L$, $M_i$ and $N_i$ as above, if $D$ is a regular filter on $\lambda$, then $\prod_i M_i/D\cong\prod_i N_i/D$.
    keywords: S: ico, (mod), (up)
  732. Sh:770
    Hellsten, A., Hyttinen, T., & Shelah, S. (2002). Potential isomorphism and semi-proper trees. Fund. Math., 175(2), 127–142. arXiv: math/0112288 DOI: 10.4064/fm175-2-3 MR: 1969631
    type: article
    abstract: We study a notion of potential isomorphism, where two structures are said to be potentially isomorphic if they are isomorphic in some generic extension that preserves stationary sets and does not add new sets of cardinality less than the cardinality of the models. We introduce the notions of semi-proper and weakly semi-proper trees, and note that there is a strong connection between the existence of potentially isomorphic models for a given complete theory and the existence of weakly semi-proper trees. We prove the existence of semi-proper trees under certain cardinal arithmetic assumptions. We also show the consistency of the non-existence of weakly semi-proper trees assuming the consistency of some large cardinals.
    keywords: M: odm, (set-mod)
  733. Sh:771
    Shelah, S. (2011). Polish algebras, shy from freedom. Israel J. Math., 181, 477–507. arXiv: math/0212250 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-011-0020-x MR: 2773054
    type: article
    abstract: Every Polish group is not free whereas some $F_\sigma$ group may be free. Also every automorphism group of a structure of cardinality, e.g. $\beth_\omega$ is not free.
    keywords: S: dst, (mod), (stal), (grp), (ps-dst)
  734. Sh:772
    Shelah, S., & Strüngmann, L. H. (2003). Kulikov’s problem on universal torsion-free abelian groups. J. London Math. Soc. (2), 67(3), 626–642. arXiv: math/0112253 DOI: 10.1112/S0024610703004216 MR: 1967696
    type: article
    abstract: Let $T$ be an abelian group and $\lambda$ an uncountable regular cardinal. We consider the question of whether there is a $\lambda$-universal group $G^*$ among all torsion-free abelian groups $G$ of cardinality less than or equal to $\lambda$ satisfying ${\rm Ext}(G,T)=0$. Here $G^*$ is said to be $\lambda$-universal for $T$ if, whenever a torsion-free abelian group $G$ of cardinality less than or equal to $\lambda$ satisfies ${\rm Ext}(G,T)=0$, then there is an embedding of $G$ into $G^*$. For large classes of abelian groups $T$ and cardinals $\lambda$ it is shown that the answer is consistently no. In particular, for $T$ torsion, this solves a problem of Kulikov.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (wh)
  735. Sh:773
    Shelah, S., & Strüngmann, L. H. (2002). Cotorsion theories cogenerated by \aleph_1-free abelian groups. Rocky Mountain J. Math., 32(4), 1617–1626. arXiv: math/0107208 DOI: 10.1216/rmjm/1181070044 MR: 1987629
    type: article
    abstract: Given an $\aleph_1$-free abelian group $G$ we characterize the class ${\mathfrak C_G}$ of all torsion abelian groups $T$ satisfying ${\rm Ext}(G,T)=0$ assuming the continuum hypothesis CH. Moreover, in G\"odel's constructable universe we prove that this characterizes ${\mathfrak C}_G$ for arbitrary torsion-free abelian $G$. It follows that there exist some ugly $\aleph_1$-free abelian groups.
    keywords: S: ico, (ab), (cont)
  736. Sh:774
    Bartoszyński, T., Shelah, S., & Tsaban, B. (2003). Additivity properties of topological diagonalizations. J. Symbolic Logic, 68(4), 1254–1260. arXiv: math/0112262 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1067620185 MR: 2017353
    type: article
    abstract: In a work of Just, Miller, Scheepers and Szeptycki it was asked whether certain diagonalization properties for sequences of open covers are provably closed under taking finite or countable unions. In a recent work, Scheepers proved that one of the classes in question is closed under taking countable unions. In this paper we show that none of the remaining classes is provably closed under taking finite unions, and thus settle the problem. We also show that one of these properties is consistently (but not provably) closed under taking unions of size less than the continuum, by relating a combinatorial version of this problem to the Near Coherence of Filters (NCF) axiom, which asserts that the Rudin-Keisler ordering is downward directed.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (gt)
  737. Sh:775
    Shelah, S. (2005). Middle diamond. Arch. Math. Logic, 44(5), 527–560. arXiv: math/0212249 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-004-0239-x MR: 2210145
    type: article
    abstract: Under some cardinal arithmetic assumptions, we prove that many stationary subsets of $\lambda$ of a right cofinality has the ``middle diamond''. In particular, for many regular $\kappa$ for every large enough regular $\lambda$ we have the middle diamond on $\{\delta<\lambda:{\rm cf}(\delta)=\kappa\}$. This is a strong negation of uniformization.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (wd)
  738. Sh:776
    Hyttinen, T., Shelah, S., & Väänänen, J. A. (2002). More on the Ehrenfeucht-Fraïssé game of length \omega_1. Fund. Math., 175(1), 79–96. arXiv: math/0212234 DOI: 10.4064/fm175-1-5 MR: 1971240
    type: article
    abstract: Let $A$ and $B$ be two first order structures of the same relational vocabulary $L$. The Ehrenfeucht-Fra{\"\i}ss\'e-game of length $\gamma$ of $A$ and $B$ denoted by $EFG_\gamma(A,B)$ is defined as follows: There are two players called $\forall$ and $\exists$. First $\forall$ plays $x_0$ and then $\exists$ plays $y_0$. After this $\forall$ plays $x_1$, and $\exists$ plays $y_1$, and so on. Eventually a sequence $\langle(x_\beta,y_\beta):\beta< \gamma\rangle$ has been played. The rules of the game say that both players have to play elements of $A\cup B$. Moreover, if $\forall$ plays his $x_\beta$ in $A$ ($B$), then $\exists$ has to play his $y_\beta$ in $B$ ($A$). Thus the sequence $\langle(x_\beta,y_\beta): \beta<\gamma\rangle$ determines a relation $\pi\subseteq A\times B$. Player $\exists$ wins this round of the game if $\pi$ is a partial isomorphism. Otherwise $\forall$ wins. The game $EFG_\gamma^\delta(A,B)$ is defined similarly except that the players play sequences of length $<\delta$ at a time. Theorem 1: The following statements are equiconsistent relative to ZFC: (A) There is a weakly compact cardinal. (B) CH and $EF_{\omega_1}(A,B)$ is determined for all models $A,B$ of cardinality $\aleph_2$. Theorem 2: Assume that $2^\omega<2^{\omega_3}$ and $T$ is a countable complete first order theory. Suppose that one of (i)-(iii) below holds. Then there are $A ,B\models T$ of power $\omega_3$ such that for all cardinals $1<\theta\leq\omega_3$, $EF^\theta_{\omega_1}(A,B)$ is non-determined. [(i)] $T$ is unstable. [(ii)] $T$ is superstable with DOP or OTOP. [(iii)] $T$ is stable and unsuperstable and $2^\omega\leq\omega_3$.
    keywords: M: smt, (inf-log), (set-mod)
  739. Sh:777
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2007). Sheva-Sheva-Sheva: large creatures. Israel J. Math., 159, 109–174. arXiv: math/0210205 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-007-0040-8 MR: 2342475
    type: article
    abstract: We develop the theory of the forcing with trees and creatures for an inaccessible $\lambda$ continuing Ros{\l}anowski and Shelah [RoSh:470], [RoSh:672]. To make a real use of these forcing notions (that is to iterate them without collapsing cardinals) we need suitable iteration theorems, and those are proved as well. (In this aspect we continue Ros{\l}anowski and Shelah [RoSh:655].)
    keywords: S: for, (set), (creatures)
  740. Sh:778
    Mildenberger, H., & Shelah, S. (2003). Specialising Aronszajn trees by countable approximations. Arch. Math. Logic, 42(7), 627–647. arXiv: math/0112287 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-002-0168-5 MR: 2015092
    type: article
    abstract: We show that there are proper forcings based upon countable trees of creatures that specialize a given Aronszajn tree.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (creatures)
  741. Sh:779
    Larson, P. B., & Shelah, S. (2017). Consistency of a strong uniformization principle. Colloq. Math., 146(1), 1–13. DOI: 10.4064/cm6542-3-2016 MR: 3570198
    type: article
    abstract: We prove the consistency of a strong uniformization for some $\aleph_1$ branches ${}^{\omega>}\omega$. As a consequence we get the consistency of a relative speaking on groups.
    keywords: S: str
  742. Sh:780
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2003). Characterizing automorphism groups of ordered abelian groups. Bull. London Math. Soc., 35(3), 289–292. arXiv: math/0112264 DOI: 10.1112/S0024609302001881 MR: 1960938
    type: article
    abstract: We want to characterize the groups isomorphic to full automorphism groups of ordered abelian groups. The result will follow from classical theorems on ordered groups adding an argument from proofs used to realize rings as endomorphism rings of abelian groups.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab)
  743. Sh:781
    Kojman, M., & Shelah, S. (2003). van der Waerden spaces and Hindman spaces are not the same. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 131(5), 1619–1622. arXiv: math/0112265 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-02-06916-2 MR: 1950294
    type: article
    abstract: A Hausdorff topological space $X$ is {\em van der Waerden} if for every sequence $(x_n)_n$ in $X$ there is a converging subsequence $(x_n)_{n\in A}$ where $A\subseteq\omega$ contains arithmetic progressions of all finite lengths. A Hausdorff topological space $X$ is {\em Hindman} if for every sequence $(x_n)_n$ in $X$ there is an {\em IP-converging} subsequence $(x_n)_{n\in FS(B)}$ for some infinite $B\subseteq\omega$. We show that the continuum hypothesis implies the existence of a van der Waerden space which is not Hindman.
    keywords: S: ico, S: str
  744. Sh:782
    Shelah, S. (2005). On the Arrow property. Adv. In Appl. Math., 34(2), 217–251. arXiv: math/0112213 DOI: 10.1016/j.aam.2002.03.001 MR: 2110551
    type: article
    abstract: Let $X$ be a finite set of alternatives. A choice function $c$ is a mapping which assigns to nonempty subsets $S$ of $X$ an element $c(S)$ of $S$. A {\it rational} choice function is one for which there is a linear ordering on the alternatives such that $c(S)$ is the maximal element of $S$ according to that ordering. Arrow's impossibility theorem asserts that under certain natural conditions, if there are at least three alternatives then every non-dictatorial social choice gives rise to a non-rational choice function. Gil Kalai asked if Arrow's theorem can be extended to the case when the individual choices are not rational but rather belong to an arbitrary non-trivial symmetric class of choice functions. The main theorem of this paper gives an affirmative answer in a very general setting.
    keywords: O: fin
  745. Sh:783
    Shelah, S. (2009). Dependent first order theories, continued. Israel J. Math., 173, 1–60. arXiv: math/0406440 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-009-0082-1 MR: 2570659
    type: article
    abstract: A dependent theory is a (first order complete theory) $T$ which does not have the independence property. A major result here is: if we expand a model of $T$ by the traces on it of sets definable in a bigger model then we preserve its being dependent. Another one justifies the cofinality restriction in the theorem (from a previous work) saying that pairwise perpendicular indiscernible sequences, can have arbitrary dual-cofinalities in some models containing them. We introduce "strongly dependent" and look at definable groups; and also at dividing, forking and relatives.
    keywords: M: cla
  746. Sh:784
    Shelah, S. (2004). Forcing axiom failure for any \lambda>\aleph_1. Arch. Math. Logic, 43(3), 285–295. arXiv: math/0112286 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-003-0208-9 MR: 2052883
    type: article
    abstract: David Aspero asks on the possibility of having Forcing axiom $FA_{{\aleph_2}}(\mathfrak{K})$, where $\mathfrak{K}$ is the class of forcing notions preserving stationarily of subsets of $\aleph_1$ and of $\aleph_2$. We answer negatively, in fact we show the negative result for any regular $\lambda>\aleph_1$ even demanding adding no new sequence of ordinals of length $<\lambda$.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set)
  747. Sh:785
    Göbel, R., Shelah, S., & Strüngmann, L. H. (2003). Almost-free E-rings of cardinality \aleph_1. Canad. J. Math., 55(4), 750–765. arXiv: math/0112214 DOI: 10.4153/CJM-2003-032-8 MR: 1994072
    type: article
    abstract: An $E$-ring is a unital ring $R$ such that every endomorphism of the underlying abelian group $R^+$ is multiplication by some ring-element. The existence of almost-free $E$-rings of cardinality greater than $2^{\aleph_0}$ is undecidable in ZFC. While they exist in Goedel's universe, they do not exist in other models of set theory. For a regular cardinal $\aleph_1\leq\lambda\leq 2^{\aleph_0}$ we construct $E$-rings of cardinality $\lambda$ in ZFC which have $\aleph_1$-free additive structure. For $\lambda= \aleph_1$ we therefore obtain the existence of almost-free $E$-rings of cardinality $\aleph_1$ in ZFC.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab)
  748. Sh:786
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (2007). Possible cardinalities of maximal abelian subgroups of quotients of permutation groups of the integers. Fund. Math., 196(3), 197–235. arXiv: math/0212233 DOI: 10.4064/fm196-3-1 MR: 2353856
    type: article
    abstract: The maximality of Abelian subgroups play a role in various parts of group theory. For example, Mycielski has extended a classical result of Lie groups and shown that a maximal Abelian subgroup of a compact connected group is connected and, furthermore, all the maximal Abelian subgroups are conjugate. For finite symmetric groups the question of the size of maximal Abelian subgroups has been examined by Burns and Goldsmith in 1989 and Winkler in 1993. We show that there is not much interest in generalizing this study to infinite symmetric groups; the cardinality of any maximal Abelian subgroup of the symmetric group of the integers is $2^{\aleph_0}$. Our purpose is also to examine the size of maximal Abelian subgroups for a class of groups closely related to the the symmetric group of the integers; these arise by taking an ideal on the integers, considering the subgroup of all permutations which respect the ideal and then taking the quotient by the normal subgroup of permutations which fix all integers except a set in the ideal. We prove that the maximal size of Abelian subgroups in such groups is sensitive to the nature of the ideal as well as various set theoretic hypotheses.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (ab)
  749. Sh:787
    Shelah, S., & Väisänen, P. (2002). Almost free groups and Ehrenfeucht-Fraïssé games for successors of singular cardinals. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 118(1-2), 147–173. arXiv: math/0212063 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(02)00037-4 MR: 1934121
    type: article
    abstract: We strengthen non-structure theorems for almost free Abelian groups by studying long Ehrenfeucht-Fra{\"\i}ss\'e games between a fixed group of cardinality $\lambda$ and a free Abelian group. A group is called $\epsilon$-game-free if the isomorphism player has a winning strategy in the game (of the described form) of length $\epsilon \in \lambda$. We prove for a large set of successor cardinals $\lambda = \mu^+$ existence of nonfree $(\mu \cdot \omega_1)$-game-free groups of cardinality $\lambda$. We concentrate on successors of singular cardinals.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab)
  750. Sh:788
    Komjáth, P., & Shelah, S. (2005). Finite subgraphs of uncountably chromatic graphs. J. Graph Theory, 49(1), 28–38. arXiv: math/0212064 DOI: 10.1002/jgt.20060 MR: 2130468
    type: article
    abstract: It is consistent that for every monotonically increasing function $f:\omega\to\omega$ there is a graph with size and chromatic number $\aleph_1$ in which every $n$-chromatic subgraph has at least $f(n)$ elements ($n\geq 3$). This solves a \textdollar~250 problem of Erd\H{o}s. It is also consistent that there is a graph $X$ with ${\rm Chr}(X)=|X|=\aleph_1$ such that if $Y$ is a graph all whose finite subgraphs occur in $X$ then ${\rm Chr}(Y)\leq \aleph_2$.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for
  751. Sh:789
    Shelah, S., & Usvyatsov, A. (2006). Banach spaces and groups—order properties and universal models. Israel J. Math., 152, 245–270. arXiv: math/0303325 DOI: 10.1007/BF02771986 MR: 2214463
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with two natural examples of almost-elementary classes: the class of all Banach spaces (over ${\mathbb R}$ or ${\mathbb C}$) and the class of all groups. We show both of these classes do not have the strict order property, and find the exact place of each one of them in Shelah's $SOP_n$ (strong order property of order $n$) hierarchy. Remembering the connection between this hierarchy and the existence of universal models, we conclude, for example, that there are ``few'' universal Banach spaces (under isometry) of regular cardinalities.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (grp)
  752. Sh:790
    Shelah, S., & Väänänen, J. A. (2006). Recursive logic frames. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 52(2), 151–164. arXiv: math/0405016 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200410058 MR: 2214627
    type: article
    abstract: We define the concept of a {\em logic frame}, which extends the concept of an abstract logic by adding the concept of a syntax and an axiom system. In a {\em recursive} logic frame the syntax and the set of axioms are recursively coded. A recursive logic frame is called recursively (countably) compact, if every recursive (respectively, countable) finitely consistent theory has a model. We show that for logic frames built from the cardinality quantifiers "there exists at least $\lambda$" recursive compactness always implies countable compactness. On the other hand we show that a recursively compact extension need not be countably compact.
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  753. Sh:791
    Shelah, S., & Zapletal, J. (2002). Duality and the PCF theory. Math. Res. Lett., 9(5-6), 585–595. arXiv: math/0212041 DOI: 10.4310/MRL.2002.v9.n5.a2 MR: 1906062
    type: article
    abstract: We consider natural cardinal invariants ${\mathfrak hm}_n$ and prove several duality theorems, saying roughly: if $I$ is a suitably definable ideal and provably ${\rm cov}(I)\geq{\mathfrak hm}_n$, then ${\rm non}(I)$ is provably small. The proofs integrate the determinacy theory, forcing and pcf theory.
    keywords: S: for, S: pcf, S: str
  754. Sh:792
    Shelah, S., & Zapletal, J. (2003). Games with creatures. Comment. Math. Univ. Carolin., 44(1), 9–21. arXiv: math/0212042 MR: 2045842
    type: article
    abstract: Many forcing notions obtained using the creature technology are naturally connected with certain integer games
    keywords: S: for, (set), (creatures)
  755. Sh:793
    Kojman, M., Kubiś, W., & Shelah, S. (2004). On two problems of Erdős and Hechler: new methods in singular madness. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 132(11), 3357–3365. arXiv: math/0406441 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-04-07580-X MR: 2073313
    type: article
    abstract: For an infinite cardinal $\mu$, ${\rm MAD}(\mu)$ denotes the set of all cardinalities of nontrivial maximal almost disjoint families over $\mu$. Erd{\H o}s and Hechler proved the consistency of $\mu\in {\rm MAD}(\mu)$ for a singular cardinal $\mu$ and asked if it was ever possible for a singular $\mu$ that $\mu\notin {\rm MAD}(\mu)$, and also whether $2^{{\rm cf}\mu}<\mu\Longrightarrow\mu\in{\rm MAD} (\mu)$ for every singular cardinal $\mu$. We introduce a new method for controlling ${\rm MAD}(\mu)$ for a singular $\mu$ and, among other new results about the structure of ${\rm MAD}(\mu)$ for singular $\mu$, settle both problems affirmatively.
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  756. Sh:794
    Shelah, S. (2008). Reflection implies the SCH. Fund. Math., 198(2), 95–111. arXiv: math/0404323 DOI: 10.4064/fm198-2-1 MR: 2369124
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that, e.g., if $\mu>{\rm cf}(\mu)=\aleph_0$ and $\mu> 2^{\aleph_0}$ and every stationary family of countable subsets of $\mu^+$ reflect in some subset of $\mu^+$ of cardinality $\aleph_1$, then the SCH for $\mu^+$ (moreover, for $\mu^+$, any scale for $\mu^+$ has a bad stationary set of cofinality $\aleph_1$). This answers a question of Foreman and Todorcevic who got such conclusion from the simultaneous reflection of four stationary sets.
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  757. Sh:795
    Juhász, I., & Shelah, S. (2003). Generic left-separated spaces and calibers. Topology Appl., 132(2), 103–108. arXiv: math/0212027 DOI: 10.1016/S0166-8641(02)00367-X MR: 1991801
    type: article
    abstract: We use a natural forcing to construct a left-separated topology on an arbitrary cardinal $\kappa$. The resulting left-separated space $X_\kappa$ is also 0-dimensional $T_2$, hereditarily Lindel\"of, and countably tight. Moreover if $\kappa$ is regular then $d(X_\kappa)=\kappa$, hence $\kappa$ is not a caliber of $X_\kappa$, while all other uncountable regular cardinals are. We also prove it consistent that for every countable set $A$ of uncountable regular cardinals there is a hereditarily Lindel\"of $T_3$ space $X$ such that $\varrho=cf(\varrho) >\omega$ is a caliber of $X$ exactly if $\varrho\not\in A$.
    keywords: S: for
  758. Sh:796
    Komjáth, P., & Shelah, S. (2003). A partition theorem for scattered order types. Combin. Probab. Comput., 12(5-6), 621–626. arXiv: math/0212022 DOI: 10.1017/S0963548303005686 MR: 2037074
    type: article
    abstract: If $\phi$ is a scattered order type, $\mu$ a cardinal, then there exists a scattered order type $\psi$ such that $\psi \to [\phi]^{1}_{\mu,\aleph_0}$ holds.
    keywords: S: ico
  759. Sh:797
    Shelah, S. (2012). Nice infinitary logics. J. Amer. Math. Soc., 25(2), 395–427. arXiv: 1005.2806 DOI: 10.1090/S0894-0347-2011-00712-1 MR: 2869022
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with soft model theory of infinitary logics. We find a logic between ${mathbb L}_{\infty,\aleph_0}$ and ${\mathbb L}_{\infty, \infty}$ which has some striking properties. First, it has interpolations (it was known that each of those logics fail interpolation though the pair has). Second, well ordering is not characterized in a strong way. Third, it can be characterized as the maximal such nice logic (in fact, is the maximal logic stronger than ${\mathbb L}_{\infty, \aleph_0}$ and which satisfies ``well ordering is not characterized in a strong way").
    keywords: M: smt, (inf-log)
  760. Sh:799
    Matet, P., Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2005). Cofinality of the nonstationary ideal. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 357(12), 4813–4837. arXiv: math/0210087 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-05-04007-9 MR: 2165389
    type: article
    abstract: We show that the reduced cofinality of the nonstationary ideal $NS_\kappa$ on a regular uncountable cardinal $\kappa$ may be less than its cofinality, where the reduced cofinality of $NS_\kappa$ is the least cardinality of any family $F$ of nonstationary subsets of $\kappa$ such that every nonstationary subset of $\kappa$ can be covered by less than $\kappa$ many members of $F$.
    keywords: S: ico, S: pcf, (set), (normal)
  761. Sh:801
    Doron, M., & Shelah, S. (2005). A dichotomy in classifying quantifiers for finite models. J. Symbolic Logic, 70(4), 1297–1324. arXiv: math/0405091 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1129642126 MR: 2194248
    type: article
    abstract: We consider a family $\mathfrak{U}$ of finite universes. The second order quantifier $Q_{\mathfrak{R}}$, means for each $U\in {\mathfrak{U}}$ quantifying over a set of $n({\mathfrak{R}})$-place relations isomorphic to a given relation. We define a natural partial order on such quantifiers called interpretability. We show that for every $Q_{\mathfrak {R}}$, ever $Q_{\mathfrak {R}}$ is interpretable by quantifying over subsets of $U$ and one to one functions on $U$ both of bounded order, or the logic $L(Q_{\mathfrak{R}})$ (first order logic plus the quantifier $Q_{\mathfrak{R}}$) is undecidable.
    keywords: M: smt, M: non, (fmt)
  762. Sh:802
    Kubiś, W., & Shelah, S. (2003). Analytic colorings. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 121(2-3), 145–161. arXiv: math/0212026 DOI: 10.1016/S0168-0072(02)00110-0 MR: 1982945
    type: article
    abstract: We investigate the existence of perfect homogeneous sets for analytic colorings. An {\em analytic coloring} of $X$ is an analytic subset of $[X]^N$, where $N>1$ is a natural number. We define an absolute rank function on trees representing analytic colorings, which gives an upper bound for possible cardinalities of homogeneous sets and which decides whether there exists a perfect homogeneous set. We construct universal $\sigma$-compact colorings of any prescribed rank $\gamma<\omega_1$. These colorings consistently contain homogeneous sets of cardinality $\aleph_\gamma$ but they do not contain perfect homogeneous sets. As an application, we discuss the so-called defectedness coloring of subsets of Polish linear spaces.
    keywords: S: str
  763. Sh:803
    Shelah, S., & Strüngmann, L. H. (2009). Large indecomposable minimal groups. Q. J. Math., 60(3), 353–365. DOI: 10.1093/qmath/han012 MR: 2533663
    type: article
    abstract: Assuming $V=L$ we prove that there exist indecomposable almost-free minimal groups of size $\lambda$ for every regular cardinal $\lambda$ below the first weakly compact cardinal. This is to say that there are indecomposable almost-free torsion-free abelian groups of cardinality $\lambda$ which are isomorphic to all of their finite index subgroups.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab)
  764. Sh:805
    Gitik, M., Schindler, R.-D., & Shelah, S. (2006). PCF theory and Woodin cardinals. In Logic Colloquium ’02, Vol. 27, Assoc. Symbol. Logic, La Jolla, CA, pp. 172–205. arXiv: math/0211433 MR: 2258707
    type: article
    abstract: We prove the following two results. Theorem A: Let $\alpha$ be a limit ordinal. Suppose that $2^{|\alpha|}<\aleph_\alpha$ and $2^{|\alpha|^+}<\aleph_{| \alpha|^+}$, whereas $\aleph_\alpha^{|\alpha|}>\aleph_{| \alpha|^+}$. Then for all $n<\omega$ and for all bounded $X\subset \aleph_{|\alpha|^+}$, $M_n^\#(X)$ exists. Theorem B: Let $\kappa$ be a singular cardinal of uncountable cofinality. If $\{\alpha<\kappa\ | \ 2^\alpha=\alpha^+\}$ is stationary as well as co-stationary then for all $n<\omega$ and for all bounded $X\subset\kappa$, $M_n^\#(X)$ exists. Theorem A answers a question of Gitik and Mitchell, and Theorem B yields a lower bound for an assertion discussed in Gitik, M., {\em Introduction to Prikry type forcing notions}, in: Handbook of set theory, Foreman, Kanamori, Magidor (see Problem 4 there). The proofs of these theorems combine pcf theory with core model theory. Along the way we establish some ZFC results in cardinal arithmetic, motivated by Silver's theorem and we obtain results of core model theory, motivated by the task of building a ``stable core model.'' Both sets of results are of independent interest.
    keywords: S: pcf, (set)
  765. Sh:806
    Shelah, S. Martin’s axiom and maximal orthogonal families. Real Anal. Exchange, 28(2), 477–480. arXiv: math/0211438 DOI: 10.14321/realanalexch.28.2.0477 MR: 2010330
    type: article
    abstract: It is shown that Martin's Axiom for $\sigma$-centred partial orders implies that every maximal orthogonal family in ${\mathbb R}^{\mathbb N}$ is of size $2^{\aleph_0}$.
    keywords: S: str, (set)
  766. Sh:807
    Bartoszyński, T., & Shelah, S. (2003). Strongly meager sets of size continuum. Arch. Math. Logic, 42(8), 769–779. arXiv: math/0211023 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-003-0184-0 MR: 2020043
    type: article
    abstract: We will construct several models where there are no strongly meager sets of size $2^{\aleph_0}$.
    keywords: S: str, (set)
  767. Sh:808
    Goldstern, M., & Shelah, S. (2005). Clones from creatures. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 357(9), 3525–3551. arXiv: math/0212379 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-04-03593-7 MR: 2146637
    type: article
    abstract: We show that (consistently) there is a clone $C$ on a countable set such that the interval of clones above $C$ is linearly ordered and has no coatoms.
    keywords: S: for, (ua)
  768. Sh:809
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (2005). Comparing the uniformity invariants of null sets for different measures. Adv. Math., 192(2), 403–426. arXiv: math/0405092 DOI: 10.1016/j.aim.2004.04.010 MR: 2128705
    type: article
    abstract: It is shown to be consistent with set theory that the uniformity invariant for Lebesgue measure is strictly greater than the corresponding invariant for Hausdorff $r$-dimensional measure where $0<r<1$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  769. Sh:811
    Geschke, S., & Shelah, S. (2003). Some notes concerning the homogeneity of Boolean algebras and Boolean spaces. Topology Appl., 133(3), 241–253. arXiv: math/0211399 DOI: 10.1016/S0166-8641(03)00103-2 MR: 2000501
    type: article
    abstract: We consider homogeneity properties of Boolean algebras that have nonprincipal ultrafilters which are countably generated. It is shown that a Boolean algebra $B$ is homogeneous if it is the union of countably generated nonprincipal ultrafilters and has a dense subset $D$ such that for every $a\in D$ the relative algebra $B\restriction a:=\{b\in B:b\leq a\}$ is isomorphic to $B$. In particular, the free product of countably many copies of an atomic Boolean algebra is homogeneous. Moreover, a Boolean algebra $B$ is homogeneous if it satisfies the following conditions: (i) $B$ has a countably generated ultrafilter, (ii) $B$ is not c.c.c., and (iii) for every $a\in B\setminus\{0\}$ there are finitely many automorphisms $h_1,\dots,h_n$ of $B$ such that $1=h_1(a)\cup\dots\cup h_n(a)$.
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  770. Sh:812
    Shelah, S., Väisänen, P., & Väänänen, J. A. (2005). On ordinals accessible by infinitary languages. Fund. Math., 186(3), 193–214. DOI: 10.4064/fm186-3-1 MR: 2191236
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\lambda$ be an infinite cardinal number. The ordinal number $\delta(\lambda)$ is the least ordinal $\gamma$ such that if $\phi$ is any sentence of $L_{\lambda^+\omega}$, with a unary predicate $D$ and a binary predicate $\prec$, and $\phi$ has a model $M$ with $\langle D^M,\prec^M\rangle$ a well-ordering of type $\ge\gamma$, then $\phi$ has a model $M'$ where $\langle D^{M'}, \prec^{M'}\rangle$ is non-well-ordered. One of the interesting properties of this number is that the Hanf number of $L_{\lambda^+\omega}$ is exactly $\beth_{\delta(\lambda)}$. We show the following theorem. {\bf Theorem}\ Suppose $\aleph_0<\lambda<\theta\leq\kappa$ are cardinal numbers such that $\lambda^{<\lambda}=\lambda$, ${\rm cf}(\theta)\geq \lambda^+$ and $\mu^\lambda<\theta$ whenever $\mu<\theta$, and $\kappa^\lambda = \kappa$. Then there is a forcing extension preserving all cofinalities, adding no new sets of cardinality $< \lambda$ such that in the extension $2^\lambda = \kappa$ and $\delta(\lambda)= \theta$.
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  771. Sh:813
    Matet, P., Péan, C., & Shelah, S. (2005). Cofinality of normal ideals on P_\kappa(\lambda). II. Israel J. Math., 150, 253–283. DOI: 10.1007/BF02762383 MR: 2255811
    type: article
    abstract: We investigate sufficient conditions for the existence of members of ${\mathcal E}$, a normal filter on $[\lambda]^{<\kappa}$, which contains no unbounded, nonstationary subsets continuing [Sh:698].
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (normal)
  772. Sh:814
    Eklof, P. C., Shelah, S., & Trlifaj, J. (2004). On the cogeneration of cotorsion pairs. J. Algebra, 277(2), 572–578. arXiv: math/0405117 DOI: 10.1016/j.jalgebra.2003.09.018 MR: 2067620
    type: article
    abstract: Let $R$ be a Dedekind domain. Enochs' solution of the Flat Cover Conjecture was extended as follows: ($*$) If $\mathfrak C$ is a cotorsion pair generated by a class of cotorsion modules, then $\mathfrak C$ is cogenerated by a set. We show that ($*$) is the best result provable in ZFC in case $R$ has a countable spectrum: the Uniformization Principle $UP^{+}$ implies that $\mathfrak C$ is not cogenerated by a set whenever $\mathfrak C$ is a cotorsion pair generated by a set which contains a non-cotorsion module.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab)
  773. Sh:815
    Baizhanov, B. S., Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (2005). Subsets of superstable structures are weakly benign. J. Symbolic Logic, 70(1), 142–150. arXiv: math/0303324 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1107298514 MR: 2119127
    type: article
    abstract: Baizhanov and Baldwin introduced the notion of benign and weakly benign sets to investigate the preservation of stability by naming arbitrary subsets of a stable structure. They connected the notion with works of Baldwin, Benedikt, Bouscaren, Casanovas, Poizat, and Ziegler. Stimulated by those results, we investigate here the existence of benign or weakly benign sets.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  774. Sh:816
    Shelah, S. (2009). What majority decisions are possible. Discrete Math., 309(8), 2349–2364. arXiv: math/0405119 DOI: 10.1016/j.disc.2008.05.010 MR: 2510361
    type: article
    abstract: Suppose we are given a family of choice functions on pairs from a given finite set (with at least three elements) closed under permutations of the given set. The set is considered the set of alternatives (say candidates for an office). The question is, what are the choice functions $\mathbf c$ on pairs of this set of the following form: for some (finite) family of ``voters", each having a preference, i.e., a choice from each pair from the given family, $\mathbf c\{x,y\}$ is chosen by the preference of the majority of voters. We give full characterization.
    keywords: O: fin
  775. Sh:817
    Shelah, S. (2004). Spectra of monadic second order sentences. Sci. Math. Jpn., 59(2), 351–355. arXiv: math/0405158 MR: 2062201
    type: article
    abstract: For a monadic sentence $\psi$ in the finite vocabulary we show that the spectra, the set of cardinalities of models of $\psi$ is almost periodic under reasonable conditions. The first is that every model is so called ``weakly $k$-decomposable". The second is that we restrict ourselves to a nice class of models constructed by some recursion.
    keywords: M: smt, O: fin, (fmt)
  776. Sh:818
    Kramer, L., Shelah, S., Tent, K., & Thomas, R., Simon. (2005). Asymptotic cones of finitely presented groups. Adv. Math., 193(1), 142–173. arXiv: math/0306420 DOI: 10.1016/j.aim.2004.04.012 MR: 2132762
    type: article
    abstract: Let $G$ be a connected semisimple Lie group with at least one absolutely simple factor $S$ such that ${\mathbb R}\text{-rank}(S) \geq 2$ and let $\Gamma$ be a uniform lattice in $G$. (a) If $CH$ holds, then $\Gamma$ has a unique asymptotic cone up to homeomorphism. (b) If $CH$ fails, then $\Gamma$ has $2^{2^{\omega}}$ asymptotic cones up to homeomorphism.
    keywords: S: str, (grp)
  777. Sh:819
    Eisworth, T., & Shelah, S. (2009). Successors of singular cardinals and coloring theorems. II. J. Symbolic Logic, 74(4), 1287–1309. arXiv: 0806.0031 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1254748692 MR: 2583821
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper, we investigate the extent to which techniques used in [10], [2], and [3] -- developed to prove coloring theorems at successors of singular cardinals of uncountable cofinality -- can be extended to cover the countable cofinality case.
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  778. Sh:820
    Shelah, S. (2017). Universal structures. Notre Dame J. Form. Log., 58(2), 159–177. arXiv: math/0405159 DOI: 10.1215/00294527-3800985 MR: 3634974
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with the existence of universal members in a given cardinality for several classes. First we deal with classes of Abelian groups, specifically with the existence of universal members in cardinalities which are strong limit singular of countable cofinality. Second, we then deal with (variants of) the oak property (from a work of Dzamonja and the author), a property of complete first order theories, sufficient for the non-existence of universal models under suitable cardinal assumptions. Third, we prove that the oak property holds for the class of groups (naturally interpreted, so for quantifier free formulas) and deal more with the existence of universals.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (grp)
  779. Sh:821
    Hyttinen, T., Lessmann, O., & Shelah, S. (2005). Interpreting groups and fields in some nonelementary classes. J. Math. Log., 5(1), 1–47. arXiv: math/0406481 DOI: 10.1142/S0219061305000390 MR: 2151582
    type: article
    abstract: This paper is concerned with extensions of geometric stability theory to some nonelementary classes. We prove the following theorem: {\bf Theorem}: Let $\mathfrak{C}$ be a large homogeneous model of a stable diagram $D$. Let $p, q \in S_D(A)$, where $p$ is quasiminimal and $q$ unbounded. Let $P = p(\mathfrak{C})$ and $Q = q(\mathfrak{C})$. Suppose that there exists an integer $n < \omega$ such that $dim(a_1\dots a_{n}/A \cup C)=n$, for any independent $a_1,\dots, a_{n} \in P$ and finite subset $C \subseteq Q$, but $dim(a_1\dots a_n a_{n+1}/A\cup C)\leq n$, for some independent $a_1,\dots,a_n,a_{n+1}\in P$ and some finite subset $C\subseteq Q$. Then $\mathfrak{C}$ interprets a group $G$ which acts on the geometry $P'$ obtained from $P$. Furthermore, either $\mathfrak{C}$ interprets a non-classical group, or $n = 1,2,3$ and If $n = 1$ then $G$ is abelian and acts regularly on $P'$. If $n = 2$ the action of $G$ on $P'$ is isomorphic to the affine action of $K \rtimes K^*$ on the algebraically closed field $K$. If $n = 3$ the action of $G$ on $P'$ is isomorphic to the action of $PGL_2(K)$ on the projective line $\mathbb{P}^1(K)$ of the algebraically closed field $K$.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (grp)
  780. Sh:823
    Bergman, G. M., & Shelah, S. (2006). Closed subgroups of the infinite symmetric group. Algebra Universalis, 55(2-3), 137–173. arXiv: math/0401305 DOI: 10.1007/s00012-006-1959-z MR: 2280223
    type: article
    abstract: Let $S={\rm Sym}(\omega)$ be the group of all permutations of the natural numbers, and for subgroups $G_1,G_2\leq S$ let us write $G_1\approx G_2$ if there exists a finite set $U\subseteq S$ such that $\langle G_1\cup U\rangle=\langle G_2\cup U\rangle$. It is shown that the subgroups closed in the function topology on $S$ lie in precisely four equivalence classes under this relation. Given an arbitrary subgroup $G\leq S$, which of these classes the closure of $G$ belongs to depends on which of the following statements about pointwise stabilizer subgroups $G_{(\Gamma)}$ of finite subsets $\Gamma\subseteq\omega$ holds: (i) For every finite set $\Gamma$, the subgroup $G_{(\Gamma)}$ has at least one infinite orbit in $\omega$. (ii) There exist finite sets $\Gamma$ such that all orbits of $G_{(\Gamma)}$ are finite, but none such that the cardinalities of these orbits have a common finite bound. (iii) There exist finite sets $\Gamma$ such that the cardinalities of the orbits of $G_{(\Gamma)}$ have a common finite bound, but none such that $G_{(\Gamma)}=\{1\}.$ (iv) There exist finite sets $\Gamma$ such that $G_{(\Gamma)}=\{1\}$.
    keywords: S: str, O: alg, (grp)
  781. Sh:824
    Shelah, S. (2005). Two cardinals models with gap one revisited. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 51(5), 437–447. arXiv: math/0404149 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200410036 MR: 2163755
    type: article
    abstract: We succeed to say something on the identities of $(\mu^+,\mu)$ when $\mu>\theta>{\rm cf}(\mu)$, $\mu$ strong limit $\theta$--compact. This hopefully will help to prove the consistency of ``some pair $(\mu^+,\mu)$ is not compact", however, this has not been proved.
    keywords: M: odm, S: ico, (set), (mod)
  782. Sh:825
    Kanovei, V., & Shelah, S. (2004). A definable nonstandard model of the reals. J. Symbolic Logic, 69(1), 159–164. arXiv: math/0311165 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1080938834 MR: 2039354
    type: article
    abstract: We prove, in ZFC, the existence of a definable, countably saturated elementary extension of the reals.
    keywords: M: odm, (mod), (cont), (up)
  783. Sh:826
    Bartoszyński, T., & Shelah, S. (2008). On the density of Hausdorff ultrafilters. In Logic Colloquium 2004, Vol. 29, Assoc. Symbol. Logic, Chicago, IL, pp. 18–32. arXiv: math/0311064 MR: 2401857
    type: article
    abstract: An ultrafilter $U$ is Hausdorff if for any two functions $f,g \in \omega^\omega$, $f(U)=g(U)$ iff $f \restriction X=g\restriction X$ for some $X \in U$. We will show that the statement that Hausdorff ultrafilters are dense in the Rudin-Keisler order is independent of ZFC
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (iter), (ultraf)
  784. Sh:827
    Kojman, M., & Shelah, S. (2006). Almost isometric embedding between metric spaces. Israel J. Math., 155, 309–334. arXiv: math/0406530 DOI: 10.1007/BF02773958 MR: 2269433
    type: article
    abstract: We investigate a relations of {\em almost isometric embedding} and {\em almost isometry} between metric spaces and prove that with respect to these relations: (1) There is a countable universal metric space. (2) There may exist fewer than continuum separable metric spaces on $\aleph_1$ so that every separable metric space is almost isometrically embedded into one of them when the continuum hypothesis fails. (3) There is no collection of fewer than continuum metric spaces of cardinality $\aleph_2$ so that every ultra-metric space of cardinality $\aleph_2$ is almost isometrically embedded into one of them if $\aleph_2<2^{\aleph_0}$. We also prove that various spaces $X$ satisfy that if a space $X$ is almost isometric to $X$ than $Y$ is isometric to $X$.
    keywords: S: str, O: top, (nni), (univ)
  785. Sh:828
    Kellner, J., & Shelah, S. (2005). Preserving preservation. J. Symbolic Logic, 70(3), 914–945. arXiv: math/0405081 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1122038920 MR: 2155272
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that the property ``$P$ doesn't make the old reals Lebesgue null'' is preserved under countable support iterations of proper forcings, under the additional assumption that the forcings are nep (a generalization of Suslin proper) in an absolute way. We also give some results for general Suslin ccc ideals.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (pure(for))
  786. Sh:829
    Shelah, S. (2006). More on the revised GCH and the black box. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 140(1-3), 133–160. arXiv: math/0406482 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2005.09.013 MR: 2224056
    type: article
    abstract: We strengthen the revised GCH theorem by showing, e.g., that for $\lambda={\rm cf}(\lambda)>\beth_\omega$, for all but finitely many regular $\kappa<\beth_\omega$, $\lambda$ is accessible on cofinality $\kappa$ in a weak version of it holds. In particular, $\lambda=2^\mu=\mu^+>\beth_\omega$ implies the diamond on $\lambda$ is restricted to cofinality $\kappa$ for all but finitely many $\kappa\in{\rm Reg}\cap \beth_\omega$ and we strengthen the results on the middle diamond. Moreover, we get stronger results on the middle diamond.
    keywords: S: ico, S: pcf, (set)
  787. Sh:830
    Shelah, S. (2006). The combinatorics of reasonable ultrafilters. Fund. Math., 192(1), 1–23. arXiv: math/0407498 DOI: 10.4064/fm192-1-1 MR: 2283626
    type: article
    abstract: We are interested in generalizing part of the theory of ultrafilters on $\omega$ to larger cardinals. Here we set the scene for further investigations introducing properties of ultrafilters in strong sense dual to being normal.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (ultraf)
  788. Sh:831
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2005). How rigid are reduced products? J. Pure Appl. Algebra, 202(1-3), 230–258. DOI: 10.1016/j.jpaa.2005.02.002 MR: 2163410
    type: article
    abstract: For any cardinal $\mu$ let ${\mathbb Z}^\mu$ be the additive group of all integer-valued functions $f:\mu\to {\mathbb Z}$. The support of $f$ is $[f]=\{i\in\mu: f(i)=f_i\ne 0\}$. Also let ${\mathbb Z}_\mu= {\mathbb Z}^\mu/{\mathbb Z}^{<\mu}$ with ${\mathbb Z}^{<\mu}= \{f\in {\mathbb Z}^\mu: \left|[f]\right|<\mu\}$. If $\mu\le \chi$ are regular cardinals we analyze the question when Hom$({\mathbb Z}_\mu,{\mathbb Z}_\chi) = 0$ and obtain a complete answer under GCH and independence results in Section 8. These results and some extensions are applied to a problem on groups: Let the norm $\|G\|$ of a group $G$ be the smallest cardinal $\mu$ with Hom$({\mathbb Z}_\mu,G) \ne 0$ - this is an infinite, regular cardinal (or $\infty$). As a consequence we characterize those cardinals which appear as norms of groups. This allows us to analyze another problem on radicals: The norm $\|R\|$ of a radical $R$ is the smallest cardinal $\mu$ for which there is a family $\{ G_i: i\in \mu\}$ of groups such that $R$ does not commute with the product $\prod_{i\in\mu}G_i$. Again these norms are infinite, regular cardinals and we show which cardinals appear as norms of radicals. The results extend earlier work (Arch. Math. 71 (1998) 341--348; Pacific J. Math. 118(1985) 79--104; Colloq. Math. Soc. J{\'a}nos Bolyai 61 (1992) 77--107) and a seminal result by {\L}o{\'s} on slender groups (His elegant proof appears here in new light; Proposition 4.5.), see Fuchs [Vol. 2] (Infinite Abelian Groups, vols. I and II, Academic Pess, New York, 1970 and 1973). An interesting connection to earlier (unpublished) work on model theory by (unpublished, circulated notes, 1973) is elaborated in Section 3.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  789. Sh:833
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2005). On Crawley modules. Comm. Algebra, 33(11), 4211–4218. arXiv: math/0504198 DOI: 10.1080/00927870500261520 MR: 2183994
    type: article
    abstract: This continues recent work in a paper by Corner, G\"obel and Goldsmith. A particular question was left open: Is it possible to carry over the results concerning the undecidability of torsion--free Crawley groups to modules over the ring of $p$-adic integers? We will confirm this and also strengthen one of the older results in by replacing the hypothesis of $\diamondsuit$ by $CH$.
    keywords: O: alg, (set), (ab)
  790. Sh:834
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2006). Torsionless linearly compact modules. In Abelian groups, rings, modules, and homological algebra, Vol. 249, Chapman & Hall/CRC, Boca Raton, FL, pp. 153–158. DOI: 10.1201/9781420010763.ch14 MR: 2229109
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (sta)
  791. Sh:836
    Shelah, S. (2006). On long EF-equivalence in non-isomorphic models. In Logic Colloquium ’03, Vol. 24, Assoc. Symbol. Logic, La Jolla, CA, pp. 315–325. arXiv: math/0404222 MR: 2207360
    type: article
    abstract: There has been much interest on constructing models which are not isomorphic of cardinality $\lambda$ but are equivalent under the Ehrenfeucht--Fraiss\'e game of length $\alpha$ even for every $\alpha< \lambda$. So under G.C.H. we know much. We deal here with constructions of such pairs of models proven in ZFC and get the existence under mild conditions.
    keywords: M: non, M: odm, (mod), (inf-log)
  792. Sh:837
    Shelah, S., & Usvyatsov, A. (2011). Model theoretic stability and categoricity for complete metric spaces. Israel J. Math., 182, 157–198. arXiv: math/0612350 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-011-0028-2 MR: 2783970
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with the systematic development of stability for the context of approximate elementary submodels of a monster metric space, which is not far, but still very distinct from the first order case. In particular we prove the analogue of Morley's theorem for the classes of complete metric spaces
    keywords: M: nec, (mod), (cat)
  793. Sh:840
    Shelah, S. (2009). Model theory without choice? Categoricity. J. Symbolic Logic, 74(2), 361–401. arXiv: math/0504196 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1243948319 MR: 2518563
    type: article
    abstract: The main result is \L os conjecture: characterizing in ZF of countable first order $T$ categoricity in some uncountable $\aleph_\alpha$ (or every one). If there are $\aleph_1$ real this is Morley's theorem, the ZFC one. Otherwise, we get a different theorem. The characterization (and the proof) are different.
    keywords: M: cla, M: odm, (mod), (AC)
  794. Sh:841
    Shelah, S., & Sági, G. (2005). On topological properties of ultraproducts of finite sets. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 51(3), 254–257. arXiv: math/0404148 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200410024 MR: 2135487
    type: article
    abstract: Motivated by the model theory of higher order logics, a certain kind of topological spaces had been introduced on ultraproducts. These spaces are called ultratopologies. Ultratopologies provide a natural extra topological structure for ultraproducts and using this extra structure some preservation and characterization theorems had been obtained for higher order logics. The purely topological properties of ultratopologies seem interesting on their own right. Here we present the solutions of two problems of Gerlits and S\'agi. More concretely we show that (1) there are sequences of finite sets of pairwise different cardinality such that in their certain ultraproducts there are homeomorphic ultratopologies and (2) one can always find a dense set in an ultratopology whose cardinality is strictly smaller than the cardinality of the ultraproduct, provided that the factors of the corresponding ultraproduct are finite.
    keywords: M: odm, O: top, (mod), (up)
  795. Sh:843
    Mildenberger, H., & Shelah, S. (2007). Increasing the groupwise density number by c.c.c. forcing. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 149(1-3), 7–13. arXiv: math/0404147 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2007.07.001 MR: 2364193
    type: article
    abstract: We try to control many cardinal characteristics by working with a notion of orthogonality between two families of forcings. We show that ${\mathfrak b}^+<{\mathfrak g}$ is consistent
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (iter), (inv)
  796. Sh:844
    Shelah, S., & Usvyatsov, A. (2008). More on SOP_1 and SOP_2. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 155(1), 16–31. arXiv: math/0404178 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2008.02.003 MR: 2454629
    type: article
    abstract: This paper continues [DjSh692]. We present a rank function for NSOP$_{1}$ theories and give an example of a theory which is NSOP$_{1}$ but not simple. We also investigate the connection between maximality in the ordering $\lhd^*$ among complete first order theories and the (N)SOP${}_2$ property. We complete the proof started in [DjSh692] of the fact that $\lhd^*$-maximality implies SOP${}_2$ and get weaker results in the other direction. The paper provides a step toward the classification of unstable theories without the strict order property.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  797. Sh:845
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2007). Universal forcing notions and ideals. Arch. Math. Logic, 46(3-4), 179–196. arXiv: math/0404146 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-007-0037-3 MR: 2306175
    type: article
    abstract: The main result of this paper is a partial answer to [RoSh:672, Problem 5.5]: a finite iteration of Universal Meager forcing notions adds generic filters for many forcing notions determined by universality parameters. We also give some results concerning cardinal characteristics of the $\sigma$--ideals determined by those universality parameters.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (inv)
  798. Sh:846
    Shelah, S. (2008). The spectrum of characters of ultrafilters on \omega. Colloq. Math., 111(2), 213–220. arXiv: math/0612240 DOI: 10.4064/cm111-2-5 MR: 2365799
    type: article
    abstract: We show the consistency of the statement: ``the set of regular cardinals which are the characters of ultrafilters on $\omega$ is not convex". We also deal with the set of $\pi$-characters of ultrafilters on $\omega$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (inv), (cont), (ultraf)
  799. Sh:847
    Mildenberger, H., Shelah, S., & Tsaban, B. (2006). Covering the Baire space by families which are not finitely dominating. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 140(1-3), 60–71. arXiv: math/0407487 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2005.09.008 MR: 2224049
    type: article
    abstract: We show that the mentioned constellation of three cardinal characteristices is relatively consistent to ZFC
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (inv), (cont), (ultraf)
  800. Sh:848
    Mildenberger, H., & Shelah, S. (2009). Specializing Aronszajn trees and preserving some weak diamonds. J. Appl. Anal., 15(1), 47–78. DOI: 10.1515/JAA.2009.47 MR: 2537976
    type: article
    abstract: We show that $\diamondsuit({\mathbb R}, {\mathcal L}, \not\in)$ together with ``all Aronszajn trees are special'' is consistent relative to ZFC. The weak diamond for the uniformity of Lebegue null sets was the only weak diamond in the Cicho\'n diagramme for relations whose consistency together with ``all Aronszajn trees are special'' was not yet settled. We can have CH or $2^{\aleph_0} = \aleph_2$. Our techniques give more on coverings by related small sets that are preserved in iterations that are stronger relatives to [Sh:f, Chap. V, sect. 5--7]
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (trees), (wd), (aron)
  801. Sh:849
    Shelah, S. (2016). Beginning of stability theory for Polish spaces. Israel J. Math., 214(2), 507–537. arXiv: 1011.3578 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-016-1342-5 MR: 3544691
    type: article
    abstract: We consider stability theory for Polish spaces, and more generally, for definable structures (say with elements of a set of reals). We clarify by proving some equivalent conditions for $\aleph_0$-stability. We succeed to prove existence of indiscernibles under reasonable conditions; this provides strong evidence that such a theory exists.
    keywords: M: cla, S: str, S: dst, (mod), (sta)
  802. Sh:850
    Cherlin, G. L., & Shelah, S. (2007). Universal graphs with a forbidden subtree. J. Combin. Theory Ser. B, 97(3), 293–333. arXiv: math/0512218 DOI: 10.1016/j.jctb.2006.05.008 MR: 2305886
    type: article
    abstract: We show that the problem of the existence of universal graphs with specified forbidden subgraphs can be systematically reduced to certain critical cases by a simple pruning technique which simplifies the underlying structure of the forbidden graphs, viewed as trees of blocks. As an application, we characterize the trees T for which a universal countable T-free graph exists.
    keywords: M: odm, (mod), (graph), (univ)
  803. Sh:851
    Laskowski, M. C., & Shelah, S. (2006). Decompositions of saturated models of stable theories. Fund. Math., 191(2), 95–124. DOI: 10.4064/fm191-2-1 MR: 2231058
    type: article
    abstract: We characterize the stable theories $T$ for which the saturated models of $T$ admit decompositions. Additionally, we show that when $T$ is countable the criterion can be weakened.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (sta)
  804. Sh:852
    Kennedy, J. C., & Shelah, S. (2004). More on regular reduced products. J. Symbolic Logic, 69(4), 1261–1266. arXiv: math/0504200 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1102022222 MR: 2135667
    type: article
    abstract: The authors show, by means of a finitary version $\square^{fin}_{\lambda,D}$ of the combinatorial principle $\square^{b^*}_{\lambda}$, the consistency of the failure, relative to the consistency of supercompact cardinals, of the following: for all regular filters $D$ on a cardinal $\lambda$, if $M_i$ and $N_i$ are elementarily equivalent models of a language of size $\le\lambda$, then the second player has a winning strategy in the Ehrenfeucht-Fra{\"\i}ss\'e game of length $\lambda^+$ on $\prod_i M_i/D$ and $\prod_i N_i/D$. If in addition $2^{\lambda}=\lambda^+$ and $i<\lambda$ implies $|M_i|+|N_i|\leq \lambda^+$ this means that the ultrapowers are isomorphic.
    keywords: M: odm, S: ico, (mod), (up)
  805. Sh:853
    Shelah, S. (2005). The depth of ultraproducts of Boolean algebras. Algebra Universalis, 54(1), 91–96. arXiv: math/0406531 DOI: 10.1007/s00012-005-1925-1 MR: 2217966
    type: article
    abstract: We show that if $\mu$ is a compact cardinal then the depth of ultraproducts of less than $\mu$ many Boolean algebras is at most $\mu$ plus the ultraproduct of the depths of those Boolean algebras
    keywords: S: ico, (ba), (large)
  806. Sh:854
    Blass, A. R., & Shelah, S. (2005). Ultrafilters and partial products of infinite cyclic groups. Comm. Algebra, 33(6), 1997–2007. arXiv: math/0504199 DOI: 10.1081/AGB-200063355 MR: 2150855
    type: article
    abstract: We consider, for infinite cardinals $\kappa$ and $\alpha\leq\kappa^+$, the group $\Pi(\kappa,<\alpha)$ of sequences of integers, of length $\kappa$, with non-zero entries in fewer than $\alpha$ positions. Our main result tells when $\Pi(\kappa,<\alpha)$ can be embedded in $\Pi(\lambda,<\beta)$. The proof involves some set-theoretic results, one about familes of finite sets and one about families of ultrafilters.
    keywords: S: str, O: alg, (set), (ab), (ultraf)
  807. Sh:855
    Shelah, S., & Strüngmann, L. H. (2010). Filtration-equivalent \aleph_1-separable abelian groups of cardinality \aleph_1. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 161(7), 935–943. arXiv: math/0612241 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2009.12.001 MR: 2601022
    type: article
    abstract: We show that it is consistent with ordinary set theory $ZFC$ and the generalized continuum hypothesis that there exist two $aleph_1$ separable abelian groups of cardinality $\aleph_1$ which are filtration-equivalent and one is a Whitehead group but the other is not. This solves one of the open problems of Eklof and Mekler.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (ba), (stal), (normal)
  808. Sh:856
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2006). How much sweetness is there in the universe? MLQ Math. Log. Q., 52(1), 71–86. arXiv: math/0406612 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200410056 MR: 2195002
    type: article
    abstract: We continue investigations of forcing notions with strong ccc properties introducing new methods of building sweet forcing notions. We also show that quotients of topologically sweet forcing notions over Cohen reals are topologically sweet.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (creatures)
  809. Sh:857
    Kuhlmann, S., & Shelah, S. (2005). \kappa-bounded exponential-logarithmic power series fields. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 136(3), 284–296. arXiv: math/0512220 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2005.04.001 MR: 2169687
    type: article
    abstract: In [KKSh:601] it was shown that fields of generalized power series cannot admit an exponential function. In this paper, we construct fields of generalized power series with {\em bounded support} which admit an exponential. We give a natural definition of an exponential, which makes these fields into models of real exponentiation. The method allows to construct for every $\kappa$ regular uncountable cardinal, $2^{\kappa}$ pairwise non-isomorphic models of real exponentiation (of cardinality $\kappa$), but all isomorphic as ordered fields. Indeed, the $2^{\kappa}$ exponentials constructed have pairwise distinct {\em growth rates}. This method relies on constructing lexicographic chains with many automorphisms.
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg
  810. Sh:858
    Mildenberger, H., Shelah, S., & Tsaban, B. (2007). The combinatorics of \tau-covers. Topology Appl., 154(1), 263–276. arXiv: math/0409068 DOI: 10.1016/j.topol.2006.04.011 MR: 2271787
    type: article
    abstract: We compute the critical cardinalities for some topological properties involving $\tau$-covers. A surprising structure counterpart of one of the computations is that, using Scheepers' notation: If $X^2$ satisfies $S_{\rm fin}(\Gamma,T)$, then $X$ satisfies Hurewicz' property $U_{\rm fin}(\Gamma,\Gamma)$. Some results on the additivity of these properties and special elements are also provided.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (inv)
  811. Sh:859
    Kellner, J., & Shelah, S. (2011). Saccharinity. J. Symbolic Logic, 76(4), 1153–1183. arXiv: math/0511330 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1318338844 MR: 2895391
    type: article
    abstract: We present a method to iterate finitely splitting lim-sup tree forcings along non-wellfounded linear orders. We apply this method to construct a forcing (without using an inaccessible or amalgamation) that makes all definable sets of reals measurable with respect to a certain (non-ccc) ideal.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (creatures)
  812. Sh:860
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2006). Reasonably complete forcing notions. In Set theory: recent trends and applications, Vol. 17, Dept. Math., Seconda Univ. Napoli, Caserta, pp. 195–239. arXiv: math/0508272 MR: 2374767
    type: article
    abstract: We introduce more properties of forcing notions which imply that their $\lambda$--support iterations are $\lambda$--proper, where $\lambda$ is an inaccessible cardinal. This paper is a direct continuation of Ros{\l}anowski and Shelah [RoSh:777, \S A.2]. As an application of our iteration result we show that it is consistent that dominating numbers associated with two normal filters on $\lambda$ are distinct.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (ultraf)
  813. Sh:861
    Shelah, S. (2007). Power set modulo small, the singular of uncountable cofinality. J. Symbolic Logic, 72(1), 226–242. arXiv: math/0612243 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1174668393 MR: 2298480
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\mu$ be singular of uncountable cofinality. If $\mu> 2^{{\rm cf}(\mu)}$, we prove that in ${\mathbb P}=([\mu]^\mu, \supseteq)$ as a forcing notion we have a natural complete embedding of ${\rm Levy}(\aleph_0,\mu^+)$ (so ${\mathbb P}$ collapses $\mu^+$ to $\aleph_0$) and even ${\rm Levy}(\aleph_0, {\bf U}_{J^{{\rm bd}}_\kappa}(\mu))$. The ``natural" means that the forcing $(\{p \in [\mu]^\mu:p$ closed$\},\supseteq)$ is naturally embedded and is equivalent to the Levy algebra. If $\mu<2^{{\rm cf}(\mu)}$ we have weaker results.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (app(pcf))
  814. Sh:862
    Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (2008). Examples of non-locality. J. Symbolic Logic, 73(3), 765–782. DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1230396746 MR: 2444267
    type: article
    abstract: We use $\kappa$-free but not Whitehead Abelian groups to construct abstract elementary classes which satisfy the amalgamation property but fail various conditions on the locality of types. We show in fact that in a large class of cases amalgamation can have no positive effect on locality by exhibiting a transformation of aec's which preserves non-locality but takes any aec satisfying a new property called admitting closures to one with amalgamation.
    keywords: M: nec, (mod), (ab), (grp), (aec)
  815. Sh:863
    Shelah, S. (2014). Strongly dependent theories. Israel J. Math., 204(1), 1–83. arXiv: math/0504197 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-014-1111-2 MR: 3273451
    type: article
    abstract: We further investigate the class of models of a strongly dependent (first order complete) theory $T$, continuing [Sh:783]. If $|A|+|T|\le\mu$, $I\subseteq \mathfrak{C}$, $|I|\ge \beth_{|T|^+}(\mu)$ then some $J\subseteq I$ of cardinality $\mu^+$ is an indiscernible sequence over $A$.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  816. Sh:864
    Shelah, S., & Sági, G. (2006). On weak and strong interpolation in algebraic logics. J. Symbolic Logic, 71(1), 104–118. arXiv: math/0612244 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1140641164 MR: 2210057
    type: article
    abstract: We show that there is a restriction, or modification of the finite-variable fragments of First Order Logic in which a weak form of Craig's Interpolation Theorem holds, but a strong form of this theorem does not hold. Translating these results into Algebraic Logic we obtain a finitely axiomatizable subvariety of finite dimensional Representable Cylindric Algebras that has the Strong Amalgamation Property, but does not have the Superamalgamation Property. This settles a conjecture of Pigozzi
    keywords: M: odm, (mod)
  817. Sh:865
    Doron, M., & Shelah, S. (2007). Relational structures constructible by quantifier free definable operations. J. Symbolic Logic, 72(4), 1283–1298. arXiv: math/0607375 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1203350786 MR: 2371205
    type: article
    abstract: We consider three classes of models: models of bounded patch width defined Fisher and Makowsky, models constructible by addition operations that preserve monadic theories defined in [Sh:817], and models monadicaly interpretable in trees defined below. For all three classes we have eventual periodicity of restricted spectrum of MSO sentences. We show that the second and third classes are in some sence equivalent, while the first is essentially smaller.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  818. Sh:866
    Havlin, C., & Shelah, S. (2007). Existence of EF-equivalent non-isomorphic models. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 53(2), 111–127. arXiv: math/0612245 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200610031 MR: 2308491
    type: article
    abstract: We prove the existence of pairs of models of the same cardinality $\lambda$ which are very equivalent according to EF games, but not isomorphic. We continue the paper [Sh:836], but we don't rely on it.
    keywords: M: non, M: odm, S: ico
  819. Sh:867
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2006). Generalized E-algebras via \lambda-calculus. I. Fund. Math., 192(2), 155–181. arXiv: 0711.3045 DOI: 10.4064/fm192-2-5 MR: 2283757
    type: article
    abstract: An $R$-algebra $A$ is called $E(R)$--algebra if the canonical homomorphism from $A$ to the endomorphism algebra $End_R A$ of the $R$-module ${}_R A$, taking any $a\in A$ to the right multiplication $a_r\in End_R A$ by $a$ is an isomorphism of algebras. In this case ${}_R A$ is called an $E(R)$--module. $E(R)$-algebras come up naturally in various topics of algebra, so it's not surprising that they were investigated thoroughly in the last decade. Despite some efforts it remained an open question whether proper generalized $E(R)$-algebras exist. These are $R$--algebras $A$ isomorphic to $End_R A$ but not under the above canonical isomorphism, so not $E(R)$--algebras. This question was raised about 30 years ago (for $R={\mathbb Z}$) by Phil Schultz and we will answer it. For PIDs $R$ of characteristic $0$ that are neither quotient fields nor complete discrete valuation rings - we will establish the existence of generalized $E(R)$-algebras. It can be shown that $E(R)$-algebras over rings $R$ that are complete discrete valuation rings or fields must trivial (copies of $R$). The main tool is an interesting connection between $\lambda$-calculus (used in theoretical computer sciences) and algebra. It seems reasonable to divide the work into two parts, in this paper we will work in V=L (Godels universe) hence stronger combinatorial methods make the final arguments more transparent. The proof based entirely on ordinary set theory (the axioms of ZFC) will appear in a subsequent paper.
    keywords: O: alg, (stal)
  820. Sh:868
    Shelah, S. (2012). When a first order T has limit models. Colloq. Math., 126(2), 187–204. arXiv: math/0603651 DOI: 10.4064/cm126-2-4 MR: 2924249
    type: article
    abstract: We to a large extent sort out when does a (first order comp- lete theory) $T$ have a superlimit model in a cardinal $\lambda$. Also we deal with relation notions of being limit.
    keywords: M: cla, M: non, (mod), (sta), (cat)
  821. Sh:869
    Matet, P., & Shelah, S. (2017). The nonstationary ideal on P_\kappa (\lambda) for \lambda singular. Arch. Math. Logic, 56(7-8), 911–934. arXiv: math/0612246 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-017-0552-9 MR: 3696072
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\kappa$ be a regular uncountable cardinal and $\lambda>\kappa$ a singular strong limit cardinal. We give a new characterization of the nonstationary subsets of $P_\kappa(\lambda)$ and use this to prove that the nonstationary ideal on $P_\kappa(\lambda)$ is nowhere precipitous.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (normal)
  822. Sh:870
    Blass, A. R., & Shelah, S. (2006). Disjoint non-free subgroups of abelian groups. In Set theory: recent trends and applications, Vol. 17, Dept. Math., Seconda Univ. Napoli, Caserta, pp. 1–24. arXiv: math/0509406 MR: 2374760
    type: article
    abstract: Let $G$ be an abelian group and let $\lambda$ be the smallest rank of any group whose direct sum with a free group is isomorphic to $G$. If $\lambda$ is uncountable, then $G$ has $\lambda$ pairwise disjoint, non-free subgroups. There is an example where $\lambda$ is countably infinite and $G$ does not have even two disjoint, non-free subgroups.
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (ab)
  823. Sh:871
    Laskowski, M. C., & Shelah, S. (2011). A trichotomy of countable, stable, unsuperstable theories. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 363(3), 1619–1629. arXiv: 0711.3043 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-2010-05196-7 MR: 2737280
    type: article
    abstract: A trichotomy theorem for countable, stable, unsuperstable theories is offered. We develop the notion of a `regular ideal' of formulas and study types that are minimal with respect to such an ideal.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (sta)
  824. Sh:872
    Kellner, J., & Shelah, S. (2009). Decisive creatures and large continuum. J. Symbolic Logic, 74(1), 73–104. arXiv: math/0601083 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1231082303 MR: 2499421
    type: article
    abstract: For $f>g\in\omega^\omega$ let $c^{\forall}_{f,g}$ be the minimal number of uniform trees with $g$-splitting needed to $\forall^\infty$-cover the uniform tree with $f$-splitting. $c^{\exists}_{f,g}$ is the dual notion for the $\exists^\infty$-cover. Assuming CH and given $\aleph_1$ many (sufficiently different) pairs $(f_\epsilon,g_\epsilon)$ and cardinals $\kappa_\epsilon$ such that $\kappa_\epsilon^{\aleph_0}=\kappa_\epsilon$, we construct a partial order forcing that $c^{\exists}_{f_\epsilon,g_\epsilon}= c^{\forall}_{f_\epsilon,g_\epsilon}=\kappa_\epsilon$. For this, we introduce a countable support semiproduct of decisive creatures with bigness and halving. This semiproduct satisfies fusion, pure decision and continuous reading of names.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  825. Sh:873
    Shelah, S., & Strüngmann, L. H. (2007). A characterization of \mathrm{Ext}(G,\mathbb Z) assuming (V=L). Fund. Math., 193(2), 141–151. arXiv: math/0609638 DOI: 10.4064/fm193-2-3 MR: 2282712
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper we complete the characterization of ${\rm Ext}(G,{\mathbb Z})$ under G\"odel's axiom of constructibility for any torsion-free abelian group $G$. In particular, we prove in $(V=L)$ that, for a singular cardinal $\nu$ of uncountable cofinality which is less than the first weakly compact cardinal and for every sequence of cardinals $(\nu_p : p \in \Pi )$ satisfying $\nu_p \leq 2^{\nu}$, there is a torsion-free abelian group $G$ of size $\nu$ such that $\nu_p$ equals the $p$-rank of ${\rm Ext}(G, {\mathbb Z})$ for every prime $p$ and $2^{\nu}$ is the torsion-free rank of ${\rm Ext}(G,{\mathbb Z})$.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (grp)
  826. Sh:874
    Shelah, S., & Strüngmann, L. H. (2007). On the p-rank of \mathrm{Ext}_{\mathbb Z}(G,\mathbb Z) in certain models of ZFC. Algebra Logika, 46(3), 369–397, 403–404. arXiv: math/0609637 DOI: 10.1007/s10469-007-0019-x MR: 2356727
    type: article
    abstract: We show that if the existence of a supercompact cardinal is consistent with $ZFC$, then it is consistent with $ZFC$ that the $p$-rank of ${\rm Ext}_{\mathbb Z}(G,\mathbb Z)$ is as large as possible for every prime $p$ and any torsion-free abelian group $G$. Moreover, given an uncountable strong limit cardinal $\mu$ of countable cofinality and a partition of $\Pi$ (the set of primes) into two disjoint subsets $\Pi_0$ and $\Pi_1$, we show that in some model which is very close to $ZFC$ there is an almost-free abelian group $G$ of size $2^{\mu}=\mu^+$ such that the $p$-rank of ${\rm Ext}_{\mathbb Z}(G,{\mathbb Z})$ equals $2^{\mu}=\mu^+$ for every $p\in\Pi_0$ and $0$ otherwise, i.e. for $p\in\Pi_1$.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal), (grp)
  827. Sh:875
    Jarden, A., & Shelah, S. (2013). Non-forking frames in abstract elementary classes. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 164(3), 135–191. arXiv: 0901.0852 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2012.09.007 MR: 3001542
    type: article
    abstract: The stability theory of first order theories was initiated by Saharon Shelah in 1969. The classification of abstract elementary classes was initiated by Shelah, too. In several papers, he introduced non-forming relations. Later, Shelah (2009) [17, 11] introduced the good non-forking frame, an axiomatization of the non-forking notion. We improve results of Shelah on good non-forming grames, mainly by weakening the stability hypothesis in several important theorems, replacing it by the almost $\lambda$-stability hypothesis: The number of types over a model of cardinality $\lambda$ is at most $\lambda^+$. We present conditions on $K_\lambda$, that imply the existence of a model in $K_{\lambda^{+n}}$ for all $n$. We do this by providing sufficiently strong conditions on $K_\lambda$, that they are inherited by a properly chosen subclass of $K_{\lambda^+}$. What are these conditions? We assume that there is a `non-forking' relation which satisfies the properties of the non-forking relation on superstable first order theories. Note that here we deal with models of fixed cardinality $\lambda$. While in Shelah (2009) [17,II] we assume stability in $\lambda$, so we can use brimmed (=limit) models, here we assume almost stability only, but we add an assumption: The conjugation property. In the context of elementary classes, the superstability assumption gives the existence of types with well-defined dimension and the $\omega$-stability assumption gives the existence and uniqueness of models prime over sets. In our context, the local character assumption is an analog to superstability and the density of the class of uniqueness triples with respect to the relation $ \preccurlyeq $ is the analog to $omega$-stability.
    keywords: M: cla, M: nec, (mod), (aec)
  828. Sh:876
    Shelah, S. (2008). Minimal bounded index subgroup for dependent theories. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 136(3), 1087–1091. arXiv: math/0603652 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-07-08654-6 MR: 2361885
    type: article
    abstract: For a dependent theory $T$, in ${\mathfrak C}_T$ for every type definable group $G$, the intersection of type definable subgroups with bounded index is a type definable subgroup with bounded index.
    keywords: M: cla, O: alg, (mod), (grp)
  829. Sh:877
    Shelah, S. (2014). Dependent T and existence of limit models. Tbilisi Math. J., 7(1), 99–128. arXiv: math/0609636 DOI: 10.2478/tmj-2014-0010 MR: 3313049
    type: article
    abstract: We continue [Sh:868] and [Sh:783]. The problem there is when does (first order) $T$ have a model $M$ of cardinality $\lambda$ which is (one of the variants of) a limit model for cofinality $\kappa$, and the most natural case to try is $\lambda=\lambda^{< \lambda}>\kappa={\rm cf}(\kappa)>|T|$. The stable theories has one; are there unstable $T$ whnce of limit models AUTHORS: Saharon Shelah ich has such limit models? We find one: the theory $T_{\rm ord}$ of dense linear orders. So does this hold for all unstable $T$? As $T_{\rm ord}$ is prototypical of dependent theories, it is natural to look for independent theories. A strong, explicit version of $T$ being independent is having the strong independence property. We prove that for such $T$ there are no limit models. We work harder to prove this for every dependent $T$, i.e., with the independence property though a weaker version. This makes us conjecture that any dependent $T$ has such models. Toward this end we continue the investigation of types for dependent $T$.
    keywords: M: cla, M: non, S: ico, (mod), (linear order)
  830. Sh:878
    Garti, S., & Shelah, S. (2008). On Depth and Depth^+ of Boolean algebras. Algebra Universalis, 58(2), 243–248. arXiv: math/0512217 DOI: 10.1007/s00012-008-2065-1 MR: 2386531
    type: article
    abstract: We show that the ${\rm Depth}^+$ of an ultraproduct of Boolean Algebras, can not jump over the ${\rm Depth}^+$ of every component by more than one cardinality. We can have, consequently, similar results for the Depth invariant
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (set), (ba), (inv(ba))
  831. Sh:879
    Eklof, P. C., Fuchs, L., & Shelah, S. (2012). Test groups for Whitehead groups. Rocky Mountain J. Math., 42(6), 1863–1873. arXiv: math/0702293 DOI: 10.1216/RMJ-2012-42-6-1863 MR: 3028765
    type: article
    abstract: We consider the question of when the dual of a Whitehead group is a test group for Whitehead groups. This turns out to be equivalent to the question of when the tensor product of two Whitehead groups is Whitehead. We investigate what happens in different models of set theory.
    keywords: S: for, O: alg, (ab), (stal), (wh)
  832. Sh:880
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2007). Absolutely indecomposable modules. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 135(6), 1641–1649. arXiv: 0711.3011 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-07-08725-4 MR: 2286071
    type: article
    abstract: A module is called {\em absolutely indecomposable} if it is directly indecomposable in every generic extension of the universe. We want to show the existence of large abelian groups that are absolutely indecomposable. This will follow from a more general result about $R$-modules over a large class of commutative rings $R$ with endomorphism ring $R$ which remains the same when passing to a generic extension of the universe. It turns out that `large' in this context has the {\em precise meaning,} namely being smaller then the first $\omega$-Erdos cardinal defined below. We will first apply result on large rigid trees with a similar property established by Shelah in 1982, and will prove the existence of related `$R_\omega$-modules' ($R$-modules with countably many distinguished submodules) and finally pass to $R$-modules. The passage through $R_\omega$-modules has the great advantage that the proofs become very transparent essentially using a few `linear algebra' arguments accessible also for graduate students. The result gives a new construction of indecomposable modules in general using a counting argument.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  833. Sh:881
    Shelah, S. (2009). The Erdős-Rado arrow for singular cardinals. Canad. Math. Bull., 52(1), 127–131. arXiv: math/0605385 DOI: 10.4153/CMB-2009-015-8 MR: 2494318
    type: article
    abstract: We try to prove that if $\mathrm{cf}(\lambda) > \aleph_0$ and $2^{\mathrm{cf}(\lambda)} < \lambda$ then $\lambda \to(\lambda, \omega +1)^2$
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (pc)
  834. Sh:882
    Kaplan, I., & Shelah, S. (2009). The automorphism tower of a centerless group without choice. Arch. Math. Logic, 48(8), 799–815. arXiv: math/0606216 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-009-0154-2 MR: 2563819
    type: article
    abstract: For a centerless group $G$, we can define its automorphism tower. We define $G^{\alpha}$: $G^0=G$, $G^{\alpha+1}= Aut(G^\alpha)$ and for limit ordinals $G^\delta= \bigcup_{\alpha<\delta}G^\alpha$. Let $\tau_G$ be the ordinal when the sequence stabilizes. Thomas' celebrated theorem says $\tau_G< 2^{|G|})^{+}$ and more. If we consider Thomas' proof too set theoretical, we have here a shorter proof with little set theory. However, set theoretically we get a parallel theorem without the axiom of choice. We attach to every element in $G^\alpha$, the $\alpha$-th member of the automorphism tower of $G$, a unique quantifier free type over $G$ (whish is a set of words from $G* \langle x\rangle$). This situation is generalized by defining ``$(G,A)$ is a special pair''.
    keywords: S: ico, S: dst, O: alg, (set), (grp), (AC)
  835. Sh:883
    Shelah, S. (2007). \aleph_n-free abelian group with no non-zero homomorphism to \mathbb Z. Cubo, 9(2), 59–79. arXiv: math/0609634 MR: 2354353
    type: article
    abstract: For any natural $n$, we construct an $\aleph_n$-free abelian groups which have few homomorphisms to $\mathbb Z$. For this we use ``$\aleph_n$-free $(n+1)$-dimensional black boxes". The method is relevant to e.g. construction of $\aleph_n$-free abelian groups with a prescribed endomorphism ring.
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (set), (grp), (sta)
  836. Sh:884
    Goldstern, M., & Shelah, S. (2016). All creatures great and small. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 368(11), 7551–7577. arXiv: 0706.1190 DOI: 10.1090/tran/6568 MR: 3546775
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\lambda$ be an uncountable regular cardinal. Assuming $2^\lambda=\lambda^+$, we show that the clone lattice on a set of size $\lambda$ is not dually atomic
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg, (sta), (creatures), (ua)
  837. Sh:885
    Shelah, S. (2009). A comment on “\mathfrak p<\mathfrak t. Canad. Math. Bull., 52(2), 303–314. arXiv: math/0404220 DOI: 10.4153/CMB-2009-033-4 MR: 2518968
    type: article
    abstract: Dealing with the cardinal invariants ${\mathfrak p}$ and ${\mathfrak t}$ of the continuum we prove that ${\mathfrak m}\geq {\mathfrak p} = \aleph_2 \Rightarrow {\mathfrak t} = \aleph_1$. In other words if ${\bf MA}_{\aleph_1}$ (or a weak version of this) then (of course $\aleph_2 \leq {\mathfrak p}\leq {\mathfrak t}$ and) ${\mathfrak p} = \aleph_2 \Rightarrow {\mathfrak p} = {\mathfrak t}$. This is based on giving a consequence.
    keywords: S: ico, S: str, (set)
  838. Sh:886
    Shelah, S. (2017). Definable groups for dependent and 2-dependent theories. Sarajevo J. Math., 13(25)(1), 3–25. arXiv: math/0703045 MR: 3666349
    type: article
    abstract: Let $T$ be a (first order complete) dependent theory, ${\mathfrak{C}}$ a $\bar{\kappa}$-saturated model of $T$ and $G$ a definable subgroup which is abelian. Among subgroups of bounded index which are the union of $<\kappa$ type definable subsets there is a minimal one, i.e. their intersection has bounded index. In fact, the bound is $\leq 2^{|T|}$. We then deal with 2-dependent theories, a wider class of first order theories.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (grp)
  839. Sh:887
    Shelah, S. (2008). Groupwise density cannot be much bigger than the unbounded number. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 54(4), 340–344. arXiv: math/0612353 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200710032 MR: 2435897
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that ${\mathfrak g}$, (the groupwise density) is smaller or equal to ${\mathfrak b}^+$, successor of the minimal cardinality of a non-dominated subset of ${}^\omega \omega$.
    keywords: S: ico, S: str, (set)
  840. Sh:888
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2011). Lords of the iteration. In Set theory and its applications, Vol. 533, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, pp. 287–330. arXiv: math/0611131 DOI: 10.1090/conm/533/10514 MR: 2777755
    type: article
    abstract: We introduce several properties of forcing notions which imply that their $\lambda$--support iterations are $\lambda$--proper. Our methods and techniques refine those studied in [RoSh:655], [RoSh:777], [RoSh:860] and [RoSh:890], covering some new forcing notions (though the exact relation of the new properties to the old ones remains undecided).
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (pure(for)), (ultraf)
  841. Sh:889
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2008). Generating ultrafilters in a reasonable way. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 54(2), 202–220. arXiv: math/0607218 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200610055 MR: 2402629
    type: article
    abstract: We continue investigations of reasonable ultrafilters on uncountable cardinals defined in Shelah [Sh:830]. We introduce a general scheme of generating a filter on $\lambda$ from filters on smaller sets and we investigate the combinatorics of objects obtained this way.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (ultraf)
  842. Sh:890
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2011). Reasonable ultrafilters, again. Notre Dame J. Form. Log., 52(2), 113–147. arXiv: math/0605067 DOI: 10.1215/00294527-1306154 MR: 2794647
    type: article
    abstract: We continue investigations of {\em reasonable ultrafilters\/} on uncountable cardinals defined in [Sh:830]. We introduce stronger properties of ultrafilters and we show that those properties may be handled in $\lambda$--support iterations of reasonably bounding forcing notions. We use this to show that consistently there are reasonable ultrafilters on an inaccessible cardinal $\lambda$ with generating system of size less than $2^\lambda$. We also show how reasonable ultrafilters can be killed by forcing notions which have enough reasonable completeness to be iterated with $\lambda$--supports (and we show the appropriate preservation theorem).
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set), (ultraf)
  843. Sh:891
    Garti, S., & Shelah, S. (2007). Two cardinal models for singular \mu. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 53(6), 636–641. arXiv: math/0612247 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200610053 MR: 2351585
    type: article
    abstract: We deal here with colorings of the pair $(\mu^+,\mu)$, when $\mu$ is a strong limit and singular cardinal. We show that there exists a coloring $c$, with no refinement. It follows, that the properties of identities of $(\mu^+,\mu)$ when $\mu$ is singular, differ in an essential way from the case of regular $\mu$.
    keywords: M: odm, S: ico, (set), (mod)
  844. Sh:892
    Dror Farjoun, E., Göbel, R., Segev, Y., & Shelah, S. (2007). On kernels of cellular covers. Groups Geom. Dyn., 1(4), 409–419. arXiv: math/0702294 DOI: 10.4171/GGD/20 MR: 2357479
    type: article
    abstract: In the present paper we continue to examine cellular covers of groups, focusing on the cardinality and the structure of the kernel $K$ of the cellular map $G\to M$. We show that in general a torsion free reduced abelian group $M$ may have a proper class of non-isomorphic cellular covers. In other words, the cardinality of the kernels is unbounded. In the opposite direction we show that if the kernel of a cellular cover of any group $M$ has certain ``freeness'' properties, then its cardinality must be bounded.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  845. Sh:893
    Shelah, S. (2015). A.E.C. with not too many models. In A. Hirvonen, M. Kesala, J. Kontinen, R. Kossak, & A. Villaveces, eds., Logic Without Borders: Essays on Set Theory, Model Theory, Philosophical Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics, Vols. Ontos Mathematical Logic, vol. 5, Berlin, Boston: DeGruyter, pp. 367–402. arXiv: 1302.4841 DOI: 10.1515/9781614516873.367
    type: article
    abstract: Consider an a.e.c. ${\mathfrak K}$ and the class of ${\mathbf C}_{\aleph_0}$ cardinals of cofinality $\aleph_0$. A nicely stated consequence of this work is for some closed unbounded class $C$ of cardinals we have (a)\quad $\dot I(\lambda,{\mathfrak K})\geq \lambda$ for $\lambda \in C \cap {\mathbf C_{\aleph_0}}$ or (b)\quad if $M \in K_\lambda$ and $\lambda \in {\mathbf C}_{\aleph_0}$, then $M$ has $\le_{\mathfrak K}$-extension (so in ${\mathfrak K}$) of arbitrarily large cardinals.
    keywords: M: nec, M: non, S: ico, (mod), (nni), (aec)
  846. Sh:894
    Mildenberger, H., & Shelah, S. (2009). The near coherence of filters principle does not imply the filter dichotomy principle. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 361(5), 2305–2317. DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-08-04806-X MR: 2471919
    type: article
    abstract: We show that there is a forcing extension in which any two ultrafilters on $\omega$ are nearly coherent and there is a non-meagre filter that is not nearly ultra. This answers Blass' longstanding question whether the principle of near coherence of filters is strictly weaker than the filter dichotomy principle.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (ultraf)
  847. Sh:895
    Shelah, S. (2010). Large continuum, oracles. Cent. Eur. J. Math., 8(2), 213–234. arXiv: 0707.1818 DOI: 10.2478/s11533-010-0018-3 MR: 2610747
    type: article
    abstract: Our main theorem is about iterated forcing for making the continuum larger than $\aleph_2$. We present a generalization of [Sh:669] which is dealing with oracles for random, etc., replacing $\aleph_1,\aleph_2$ by $\lambda,\lambda^+$ (starting with $\lambda = \lambda^{< \lambda} > \aleph_1$). Instead of properness we demand absolute c.c.c. So we get, e.g. the continuum is $\lambda^+$ but we can get cov(meagre) $=\lambda$. We also give some applications related to peculiar cuts of [Sh:885].
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (cont)
  848. Sh:896
    Kellner, J., Pauna, M., & Shelah, S. (2007). Winning the pressing down game but not Banach-Mazur. J. Symbolic Logic, 72(4), 1323–1335. arXiv: math/0609655 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1203350789 MR: 2371208
    type: article
    abstract: Let $S$ be the set of those $\alpha\in\omega_2$ that have cofinality $\omega_1$. It is consistent relative to a measurable that player II (the nonempty player) wins the pressing down game of length $\omega_1$, but not the Banach Mazur game of length $\omega+1$ (both starting with $S$).
    keywords: S: for, (normal)
  849. Sh:897
    Shelah, S. (2008). Theories with Ehrenfeucht-Fraïssé equivalent non-isomorphic models. Tbil. Math. J., 1, 133–164. arXiv: math/0703477 MR: 2563810
    type: article
    abstract: Our ``large scale'' aim is to characterize the first order $T$ (at least the countable ones) such that: for every ordinal $\alpha$ there $\lambda,M_1,M_2$ such that $M_1,M_2$ are non-isomorphic models of $T$ of cardinality $\lambda$ which are EF$_{\alpha,\lambda}$-equivalent. We expect that as in the main gap ([Sh:c,XII]) we get a strong dichotomy, so in the non-structure side we have more, better example, and in the structure side we have a parallel of [Sh:c,XIII]. We presently prove the consistency of the non-structure side for $T$ which is $\aleph_0$-independent (= not strongly dependent) or just not strongly stable, even for PC$(T_1,T)$ and more for unstable $T$ (see [Sh:c,VII] or [Sh:h]) and infinite linear order $I$.
    keywords: M: cla, M: non, (mod), (sta)
  850. Sh:898
    Shelah, S. (2013). Pcf and abelian groups. Forum Math., 25(5), 967–1038. arXiv: 0710.0157 DOI: 10.1515/forum-2013-0119 MR: 3100959
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with some pcf investigations mostly motivated by abelian group theory problems and deal their applications to test problems (we expect reasonably wide applications). We prove almost always the existence of $\aleph_\omega$-free abelian groups with trivial dual, i.e. no non-trivial homomorphisms to the integers. This relies on investigation of pcf; more specifically, for this we prove that ``almost always'' there are ${\mathcal F} \subseteq {}^\kappa \lambda$ which are quite free and has black boxes. The ``almost always'' means that there are strong restrictions on cardinal arithmetic if the universe fails this, this restriction are ``everywhere''. Those are irrating results; we replace Abelian groups by $R$-modules, so in some sense our advantage over earlier results becomes clearer.
    keywords: S: pcf, O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  851. Sh:899
    Juhász, I., & Shelah, S. (2008). Hereditarily Lindelöf spaces of singular density. Studia Sci. Math. Hungar., 45(4), 557–562. arXiv: math/0702295 DOI: 10.1556/SScMath.2007.1037 MR: 2641451
    type: article
    abstract: A cardinal $\lambda$ is called $\omega$-inaccessible if for all $\mu<\lambda$ we have $\mu^\omega < \lambda.$ We show that for every $\omega$-inaccessible cardinal $\lambda$ there is a CCC (hence cardinality and cofinality preserving) forcing that adds a hereditarily Lindel\'' of regular space of density $\lambda$. This extends an analogous earlier result of ours that only worked for regular $\lambda$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (gt)
  852. Sh:900
    Shelah, S. (2015). Dependent theories and the generic pair conjecture. Commun. Contemp. Math., 17(1), 1550004, 64. arXiv: math/0702292 DOI: 10.1142/S0219199715500042 MR: 3291978
    type: article
    abstract: On the one hand we try to understand complete types over somewhat saturated model of a complete first order theory which is dependent, by ``decomposition theorems for such types''. Our thesis is that the picture of dependent theory is the combination of the one for stable theories and the one for the theory of dense linear order or trees (and first we should try to understand the quite saturated case). On the other hand as a measure of our progress, we give several applications considering some test questions; in particular we try to prove the generic pair conjecture and do it for measurable cardinals. The order of the sections is by their conceptions, so there are some repetitions.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (ua)
  853. Sh:901
    Juhász, I., Shelah, S., & Soukup, L. (2009). Resolvability vs. almost resolvability. Topology Appl., 156(11), 1966–1969. arXiv: math/0702296 DOI: 10.1016/j.topol.2009.03.019 MR: 2536179
    type: article
    abstract: A space $X$ is {\em $\kappa$-resolvable} (resp. {\em almost $\kappa$-resolvable}) if it contains $\kappa$ dense sets that are pairwise disjoint (resp. almost disjoint over the ideal of nowhere dense subsets of $X$). Answering a problem raised by Juh\'asz, Soukup, and Szentmikl\'ossy, and improving a consistency result of Comfort and Hu, we prove, in ZFC, that for every infinite cardinal ${\kappa}$ there is an almost $2^{\kappa}$-resolvable but not ${\omega}_1$-resolvable space of dispersion character ${\kappa}$.
    keywords: S: ico
  854. Sh:902
    Larson, P. B., & Shelah, S. (2008). The stationary set splitting game. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 54(2), 187–193. arXiv: 1003.2425 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200610054 MR: 2402627
    type: article
    abstract: The \emph{stationary set splitting game} is a game of perfect information of length $\omega_{1}$ between two players, unsplit and split, in which unsplit chooses stationarily many countable ordinals and split tries to continuously divide them into two stationary pieces. We show that it is possible in ZFC to force a winning strategy for either player, or for neither. This gives a new counterexample to $\Sigma^{2}_{2}$ maximality with a predicate for the nonstationary ideal on $\omega_{1}$, and an example of a consistently undetermined game of length $\omega_{1}$ with payoff definable in the second-order monadic logic of order. We also show that the determinacy of the game is consistent with Martin's Axiom but not Martin's Maximum.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (normal)
  855. Sh:903
    Machura, M., Shelah, S., & Tsaban, B. (2010). Squares of Menger-bounded groups. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 362(4), 1751–1764. arXiv: math/0611353 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-09-05169-1 MR: 2574876
    type: article
    abstract: Using a portion of the Continuum Hypothesis, we prove that there is a Menger-bounded (also called $ o$-bounded) subgroup of the Baer-Specker group $ \mathbb{Z}^{\mathbb{N}}$, whose square is not Menger-bounded. This settles a major open problem concerning boundedness notions for groups and implies that Menger-bounded groups need not be Scheepers-bounded. This also answers some questions of Banakh, Nickolas, and Sanchis.
    keywords: S: ico, S: str, (set)
  856. Sh:904
    Shelah, S. (2010). Reflexive abelian groups and measurable cardinals and full MAD families. Algebra Universalis, 63(4), 351–366. arXiv: math/0703493 DOI: 10.1007/s00012-010-0086-z MR: 2734302
    type: article
    abstract: Answering problem (DG) of [EM90], [EM02], we show that there is a reflexive group of cardinality $\ge$ first measurable.
    keywords: S: ico, S: pcf, (set), (ab), (stal)
  857. Sh:905
    Kellner, J., & Shelah, S. (2010). A Sacks real out of nowhere. J. Symbolic Logic, 75(1), 51–76. arXiv: math/0703302 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1264433909 MR: 2605882
    type: article
    abstract: There is a proper countable support iteration of length $\omega$ adding no new reals at finite stages and adding a Sacks real in the limit.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  858. Sh:906
    Shelah, S. (2011). No limit model in inaccessibles. In Models, logics, and higher-dimensional categories, Vol. 53, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, pp. 277–290. arXiv: 0705.4131 MR: 2867976
    type: article
    abstract: Our aim is to improve the negative results i.e. non-existence of limit models, and the failure of the generic pair property from [Sh:877] to inaccessible $\lambda$ as promised there. The motivation is that in [Sh:F756] the positive results are for $\lambda$ measurable hence inaccessible, whereas in [Sh:877] in the negative results obtained only on non-strong limit cardinals.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  859. Sh:907
    Shelah, S. (2008). EF-equivalent not isomorphic pair of models. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 136(12), 4405–4412. arXiv: 0705.4126 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-08-09362-3 MR: 2431056
    type: article
    abstract: We construct non-isomorphic models $M, N$, e.g. of cardinality $\aleph_1$ such that in the Ehrenfeucht-Fraiss\'e game of length $\zeta < \omega_1$ the isomorphism player wins
    keywords: S: ico, (mod)
  860. Sh:908
    Shelah, S. (2010). On long increasing chains modulo flat ideals. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 56(4), 397–399. arXiv: 0705.4130 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200910010 MR: 2681343
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that e.g. there is no $\omega_4$---sequence in $(\omega_3)^{\omega_3}$ increasing mod countable.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (normal)
  861. Sh:909
    Gruenhut, E., & Shelah, S. (2011). Uniforming n-place functions on well founded trees. In Set theory and its applications, Vol. 533, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, pp. 267–280. arXiv: 0906.3055 DOI: 10.1090/conm/533/10512 MR: 2777753
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper the Erd\H os-Rado theorem is generalized to the class of well founded trees. We define an equivalence relation on the class ${\rm rs}(\infty)^{<\aleph_0}$ (finite sequences of decreasing sequences of ordinals) with $\aleph_0$ equivalence classes, and for $n<\omega$ a notion of $n$-end-uniformity for a colouring of ${\rm rs}(\infty)^{<\aleph_0}$ with $\mu$ colours. We then show that for every ordinal $\alpha$, $n<\omega$ and cardinal $\mu$ there is an ordinal $\lambda$ so that for any colouring $c$ of $T={\rm rs}(\lambda)^{<\aleph_0}$ with $\mu$ colours, $T$ contains $S$ isomorphic to ${\rm rs}(\alpha)$ so that $c\restriction S^{<\aleph_0}$ is $n$-end uniform. For $c$ with domain $T^n$ this is equivalent to finding $S\subseteq T$ isomorphic to ${\rm rs}(\alpha)$ so that $c\upharpoonright S^{n}$ depends only on the equivalence class of the defined relation, so in particular $T\rightarrow({\rm rs}(\alpha))^n_{\mu,\aleph_0}$. We also draw a conclusion on colourings of $n$-tuples from a scattered linear order.
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  862. Sh:910
    Blass, A. R., & Shelah, S. (2008). Basic subgroups and freeness, a counterexample. In Models, modules and abelian groups, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, pp. 63–73. arXiv: 0711.3031 DOI: 10.1515/9783110203035.63 MR: 2513227
    type: article
    abstract: We construct a non-free but $\aleph_1$-separable, torsion-free abelian group $G$ with a pure free subgroup $B$ such that all subgroups of $G$ disjoint from $B$ are free and such that $G/B$ is divisible. This answers a question of Irwin and shows that a theorem of Blass and Irwin cannot be strengthened so as to give an exact analog for torsion-free groups of a result proved for $p$-groups by Benabdallah and Irwin.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (pc)
  863. Sh:911
    Garti, S., & Shelah, S. (2011). Depth of Boolean algebras. Notre Dame J. Form. Log., 52(3), 307–314. arXiv: 0802.4185 DOI: 10.1215/00294527-1435474 MR: 2822491
    type: article
    abstract: We show under the assumption $\bf {V} = \bf {L}$ that the ${\rm Depth}$ of an ultraproduct of Boolean Algebras cannot jump over the ${\rm Depth}$ of every component by more than one cardinal. This is done for every cardinal. We also get better results for singular cardinals with countable cofinality.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (ba)
  864. Sh:912
    Kennedy, J. C., Shelah, S., & Väänänen, J. A. (2008). Regular ultrafilters and finite square principles. J. Symbolic Logic, 73(3), 817–823. DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1230396748 MR: 2444269
    type: article
    abstract: We show that many singular cardinals $\lambda$ above a strongly compact cardinal have regular ultrafilters $D$ that violate the finite square principle $\square^{fin}_{\lambda, D}$ introduced in [3]. For such ultrafilters $D$ and cardinals $\lambda$ there are models of size $\lambda$ for which $M^{\lambda}/D$ is not $\lambda^{++}$-universal and elementarily equivalent models $M$ and $N$ of size $\lambda$ for which $M^\lambda/D$ and $N^\lambda/D$ are non-isomorphic. The question of the existence of such ultrafilters and models was raised in [1].
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  865. Sh:913
    Kaplan, I., & Shelah, S. (2012). Automorphism towers and automorphism groups of fields without choice. In Groups and model theory, Vol. 576, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, pp. 187–203. arXiv: 1004.1810 DOI: 10.1090/conm/576/11337 MR: 2962885
    type: article
    abstract: The main result (already achieved in [FriedKollar]), is that any group can be represented as an automorphism group of a field. We introduce a new proof, using a simple construction. We conclude $\tau_{\kappa}^{nlg}\leq\tau_{\kappa}$ without choice.
    keywords: S: ods, O: alg, (mod), (auto), (grp)
  866. Sh:914
    Shelah, S. (2011). The first almost free Whitehead group. Tbil. Math. J., 4, 17–30. arXiv: 0708.1980 MR: 2886755
    type: article
    abstract: Assume G.C.H. and $\kappa$ is the first uncountable cardinal such that there is a $\kappa$-free abelian group which is not a Whitehead (abelian) group. We prove that $\kappa$ is necessarily an inaccessible cardinal.
    keywords: S: str, O: alg, (ab), (pc)
  867. Sh:915
    Shelah, S. (2011). The character spectrum of \beta(\mathbb N). Topology Appl., 158(18), 2535–2555. arXiv: 1004.2083 DOI: 10.1016/j.topol.2011.08.014 MR: 2847327
    type: article
    abstract: We show the consistency of: the set of regular cardinals which are the character of some ultrafilter on $\omega$ can be quite chaotic, in particular not only can be not convex but can have many gaps. We also deal with the set of $\pi$-characters of ultrafilters on $\omega$
    keywords: S: str, (set), (ultraf)
  868. Sh:916
    Dow, A. S., & Shelah, S. (2008). Tie-points and fixed-points in \mathbb N^*. Topology Appl., 155(15), 1661–1671. arXiv: 0711.3037 DOI: 10.1016/j.topol.2008.05.002 MR: 2437015
    type: article
    abstract: A point $x$ is a (bow) tie-point of a space $X$ if $X\setminus \{x\}$ can be partitioned into (relatively) clopen sets each with $x$ in its closure. Tie-points have appeared in the construction of non-trivial autohomeomorphisms of $\beta{\mathbb N} \setminus {\mathbb N}$ (e.g. [veli.oca, ShSt735]) and in the recent study of (precisely) 2-to-1 maps on $\beta{\mathbb N} \setminus {\mathbb N}$. In these cases the tie-points have been the unique fixed point of an involution on $\beta{\mathbb N} \setminus {\mathbb N}$. This paper is motivated by the search for 2-to-1 maps and obtaining tie-points of strikingly differing characteristics.
    keywords: S: str
  869. Sh:917
    Dow, A. S., & Shelah, S. (2009). More on tie-points and homeomorphism in \mathbb N^\ast. Fund. Math., 203(3), 191–210. arXiv: 0711.3038 DOI: 10.4064/fm203-3-1 MR: 2506596
    type: article
    abstract: A point $x$ is a (bow) tie-point of a space $X$ if $X\setminus \{x\}$ can be partitioned into (relatively) clopen sets each with $x$ in its closure. Tie-points have appeared in the construction of non-trivial autohomeomorphisms of $\beta{\mathbb N} \setminus {\mathbb N}=\mathbb N^*$ and in the recent study of (precisely) 2-to-1 maps on $\mathbb N^*$. In these cases the tie-points have been the unique fixed point of an involution on $\mathbb N^*$. One application of the results in this paper is the consistency of there being a 2-to-1 continuous image of $\mathbb N^*$ which is not a homeomorph of $\mathbb N^*$.
    keywords: S: str, (auto)
  870. Sh:918
    Shelah, S. (2012). Many partition relations below density. Israel J. Math., 191(2), 507–543. arXiv: 0902.0440 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-012-0027-y MR: 3011486
    type: article
    abstract: We force $2^\lambda$ to be large and for many pairs in the interval $(\lambda,2^\lambda)$ a stronger version of the polarized partition relations hold. We apply this toproblem in general topology
    keywords: S: ico, S: for, (set)
  871. Sh:919
    Cohen, M., & Shelah, S. (2016). Stable theories and representation over sets. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 62(3), 140–154. arXiv: 0906.3050 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200920105 MR: 3509699
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper we give a characterization of the class of first order stable theories using.
    keywords: M: cla, (mod), (sta)
  872. Sh:920
    Göbel, R., & Shelah, S. (2009). \aleph_n-free modules with trivial duals. Results Math., 54(1-2), 53–64. DOI: 10.1007/s00025-009-0382-0 MR: 2529626
    type: article
    abstract: In the first part of this paper we introduce a simplified version of a new Black Box from Shelah [Sh:883] which can be used to construct complicated $\aleph_n$-free abelian groups for any natural number $n\in N$. In the second part we apply this prediction principle to derive for many commutative rings $R$ the existence of $\aleph_n$-free $R$-modules $M$ with trivial dual $M^*=0$, where $M^*={\rm Hom}(M,R)$. The minimal size of the $\aleph_n$-free abelian groups constructed below is $\beth_n$, and this lower bound is also necessary as can be seen immediately if we apply GCH.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (pc)
  873. Sh:921
    Shelah, S., & Tsaban, B. (2010). On a problem of Juhász and van Mill. Topology Proc., 36, 385–392. arXiv: 0710.2768 MR: 2646986
    type: article
    abstract: A $27$ years old and still open problem of Juh\'asz and van Mill asks whether there exists a cardinal $\kappa$ such that every regular dense in itself countably compact space has a dense in itself subset of cardinality at most $\kappa$. We give a negative answer for the analogous question where \emph{regular} is weakened to \emph{Hausdorff}, and \emph{coutnably compact} is strengthened to \emph{sequentially compact}.
    keywords: S: str
  874. Sh:922
    Shelah, S. (2010). Diamonds. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 138(6), 2151–2161. arXiv: 0711.3030 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-10-10254-8 MR: 2596054
    type: article
    abstract: We prove, e.g. that if $\lambda=\chi^+=2^\chi$ and $S \subseteq \{\delta<\lambda:cf(\delta)\ne cf(\chi)\}$ is stationary then $\diamondsuit_\lambda$.
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  875. Sh:923
    Ardal, H., Maňuch, J., Rosenfeld, M., Shelah, S., & Stacho, L. (2009). The odd-distance plane graph. Discrete Comput. Geom., 42(2), 132–141. DOI: 10.1007/s00454-009-9190-2 MR: 2519871
    type: article
    abstract: The vertices of the odd-distance graph are the points of the plane $\mathbb{R}^2$. Two points are connected by an edge if their Euclidean distance is an odd integer. We prove that the chormatic number of this graph is at least five. We also prove that the odd-distance graph in $\mathbb{R}^2$ is countably choosable, which such a graph in $\mathbb{R}^3$ is not.
    keywords: S: ico, (graph)
  876. Sh:924
    Shelah, S. (2015). Models of PA: when two elements are necessarily order automorphic. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 61(6), 399–417. arXiv: 1004.3342 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200920124 MR: 3433640
    type: article
    abstract: We are interested in the question of how much the order of a non-standard model of PA can determine the model. In particular, for a model $M$, we want to characterize the complete types $p(x,y)$ of non-standard elements $(a,b)$ such that the linear orders $\{x:x< a\}$ and $\{x:x < b\}$ are necessarily isomorphic. It is proved that this set includes the complete types $p(x,y)$ such that if the pair $(a,b)$ realizes it (in $M$) then there is an element $c$ such that for all standard $n,c^n < a,c^n < b,a < bc$ and $b < ac$. We prove that this is optimal, because if $\diamondsuit_{\aleph_1}$ holds, then there is $M$ of cardinality $\aleph_1$ for which we get equality. We also deal with how much the order in a model of PA may determine the addition.
    keywords: M: odm, (mod)
  877. Sh:925
    Larson, P. B., & Shelah, S. (2009). Splitting stationary sets from weak forms of choice. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 55(3), 299–306. arXiv: 1003.2477 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200810011 MR: 2519245
    type: article
    abstract: We consider splitting stationary sets under the assumption of ZF + DC plus the existence of a ladder system for ordinals of countable cofinality. This is a continuation of [Sh835].
    keywords: S: ods, (set), (normal), (AC)
  878. Sh:926
    Bartoszyński, T., & Shelah, S. (2010). Dual Borel conjecture and Cohen reals. J. Symbolic Logic, 75(4), 1293–1310. DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1286198147 MR: 2767969
    type: article
    abstract: We construct a model of ZFC satisfying the Dual Borel Conjecture in which there is a set of size $\aleph_1$ that does not have measure zero.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  879. Sh:927
    Baldwin, J. T., Kolesnikov, A. S., & Shelah, S. (2009). The amalgamation spectrum. J. Symbolic Logic, 74(3), 914–928. DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1245158091 MR: 2548468
    type: article
    abstract: For every natural number $k^*$, there is a class ${\mathbf{K}}_*$ defined by a sentence in $L_{\omega_1,\omega}$ that has no models of cardinality $> \beth_{k^*+1}$, but ${\mathbf{K}}_*$ has the d isjoint amalgamation property on models of cardinality $\leq \aleph_{{k^*}-3}$ and has models of cardinality $\aleph_{{k^*}-1}$. More strongly, For every countable ordinal $\alpha^* $, there is a class ${\mathbf{K}}_*$ defined by a sentence in $L_{\omega_1,\omega}$ that has no models of cardinality $> \beth_{\alpha}$, but ${\mathbf{K}}_*$ has the disjoint amalgamation property on models of cardinality $\leq \aleph_{\alpha}$. Similar results hold for arbitrary $\kappa$ and $L_{\kappa^+,\omega}$.
    keywords: M: smt, (mod), (aec)
  880. Sh:929
    Herden, D., & Shelah, S. (2010). \kappa-fold transitive groups. Forum Math., 22(4), 627–640. DOI: 10.1515/FORUM.2010.034 MR: 2661440
    type: article
    abstract: A group $G$ of type $0$ is called $\kappa$-transitive for some cardinal $\kappa >0$ if for any ordered pair of pure elements $x,y \in G$ there exist exactly $\kappa$-many $\varphi \in {\rm Aut} G$ such that $x\varphi =y$. We shows the existence of large $\kappa$-transitive groups for every $\kappa\ge \aleph_0$ assuming V=L and ZFC respectively.
    keywords: M: non, (grp)
  881. Sh:930
    Herden, D., & Shelah, S. (2009). An upper cardinal bound on absolute E-rings. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 137(9), 2843–2847. DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-09-09842-6 MR: 2506440
    type: article
    abstract: We show that for every abelian group $A$ of cardinality $\ge\kappa(\omega)$ there exists a generic extension of the universe, where $A$ is countable with $2^{\aleph_O}$ injective endomorphisms. As an immediate consequence of this result there are no absolute E-rings of cardinality $\ge \kappa (\omega)$. This paper does not require any specific prior knowledge of forcing or model theory and can be considered accessible also for graduate students.
    keywords: M: non
  882. Sh:931
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (2011). Masas in the Calkin algebra without the continuum hypothesis. J. Appl. Anal., 17(1), 69–89. DOI: 10.1515/JAA.2011.004 MR: 2805847
    type: article
    abstract: Methods for constructing masas in the Calkin algebra without assuming the Continuum Hypothesis are developed
    keywords: S: ico, S: str, (set)
  883. Sh:933
    Laskowski, M. C., & Shelah, S. (2015). \mathbf P-NDOP and \mathbf P-decompositions of \aleph_\epsilon-saturated models of superstable theories. Fund. Math., 229(1), 47–81. arXiv: 1206.6028 DOI: 10.4064/fm229-1-2 MR: 3312115
    type: article
    abstract: Assume a complete first order theory $T$ is superstable. We generalize revise [Sh:401] in two respects, so do not depend on it. First issue we deal with a more general case. Let $\mathbf P$ be a class of regular types in $\mathfrak{C}$, closed under automorphisms and under $\pm$. We generalize [Sh:401] to this context to $\mathbf P^\pm$-saturated $M$'s, assuming $\mathbf P$-NDOP which is weaker than NDOP. Second issue, in this content it is more delicate to find sufficient condition on two $\mathbf P$-decomposition trees to give non-isomorphic models. For this we investigate natural structures on the set of regular types mod $\pm$ in $M$. Actually it suffices to deal with the case $M$ is $\aleph_\varepsilon$-saturated $\mathfrak{d}_\ell = \langle M^\ell_\eta,a_\eta:\eta \in I_\ell\rangle$ is a $\mathbf P$-decomposition of $M$ for $\ell=1,2$ and $\{p^{\mathfrak{d}_\ell}_\eta:\eta \in I_\ell\}/\pm = ({\mathcal P} \cap \mathbf S(M))/\pm$ and show the two trees are quite similar (or isomorphic).
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  884. Sh:934
    Hall, E. J., & Shelah, S. (2013). Partial choice functions for families of finite sets. Fund. Math., 220(3), 207–216. arXiv: 0808.0535 DOI: 10.4064/fm220-3-2 MR: 3040670
    type: article
    abstract: Let $p$ be a prime. We show that ZF $+$ ``Every countable set of $p$-element sets has an infinite partial choice function'' is not strong enough to prove that every countable set of $p$-element sets has a choice function, answering an open question from [1]. The independence result is obtained by way of a permutation (Fraenkel-Mostowski) model in which the set of atoms has the structure of a vector space over the field of $p$ elements. By way of comparison, some simpler permutation models are considered in which some countable families of $p$-element sets fail to have infinite partial choice functions.
    keywords: S: ods, (set), (AC)
  885. Sh:935
    Shelah, S. (2011). MAD saturated families and SANE player. Canad. J. Math., 63(6), 1416–1435. arXiv: 0904.0816 DOI: 10.4153/CJM-2011-057-1 MR: 2894445
    type: article
    abstract: We throw some light on the question: is there a MAD family (= a family of infinite subsets of $\mathbb N$, the intersection of any two is finite) which is completely separable (i.e. any $X \subseteq \mathbb N$ is included in a finite union of members of the family \underbar{or} include a member of the family). We prove that it is hard to prove the consistency of the negation: ``{$(a)$}'' if $2^{\aleph_0} < \aleph_\omega$, then there is such a family ``{$(b)$}'' if there is no such families then some situation related to pcf holds whose consistency is large.
    keywords: S: pcf, S: str, (set)
  886. Sh:936
    Enayat, A., & Shelah, S. (2011). An improper arithmetically closed Borel subalgebra of \mathcal P(\omega)\bmod\mathrm{FIN}. Topology Appl., 158(18), 2495–2502. DOI: 10.1016/j.topol.2011.08.006 MR: 2847322
    type: article
    abstract: We show the existence of a subalgebra ${\mathcal A}\subset {\mathcal P}(\omega)$ that satisfies the following three conditions. ${\mathcal A}$ is Borel (when ${\mathcal P}(\omega)$ is identified with $2^\omega$). ${\mathcal A}$ is arithmetically closed (i.e., ${\mathcal A}$ is closed under the Turing jump, and Turing reducibility). The forcing notion $({\mathcal A}, \subset)$ modulo the ideal FIN of finite sets collapses the continuum to $\aleph_0$.
    keywords: S: str, (set), (mod)
  887. Sh:937
    Shelah, S. (2011). Models of expansions of \mathbb N with no end extensions. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 57(4), 341–365. arXiv: 0808.2960 DOI: 10.1002/malq.200910129 MR: 2832642
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with models of Peano arithmetic (specifically with a question of Ali Enayat). The methods are from creature forcing. We find an expansion of $\mathbb N$ such that its theory has models with no (elementary) end extensions. In fact there is a Borel uncountable set of subsets of $\mathbb N$ such that expanding $\mathbb N$ by any uncountably many of them suffice. Also we find arithmetically closed ${\mathcal A}$ with no definably closed ultrafilter on it
    keywords: S: for, (set), (mod)
  888. Sh:938
    Shelah, S. (2012). PCF arithmetic without and with choice. Israel J. Math., 191(1), 1–40. arXiv: 0905.3021 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-012-0026-z MR: 2970861
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with relatives of GCH which are provable. In particular we deal with rank version of the revised GCH. Our motivation was to find such results when only weak versions of the axiom of choice are assumed but some of the results gives us additional information even in ZFC.
    keywords: S: for, S: ods, (set), (AC)
  889. Sh:939
    Kellner, J., & Shelah, S. (2011). More on the pressing down game. Arch. Math. Logic, 50(3-4), 477–501. arXiv: 0905.3913 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-011-0227-x MR: 2786767
    type: article
    abstract: We compare the pressing down and the Banach Mazur games and show: Consistently relative to a supercompact there is a nowhere precipitous normal ideal $I$ on $\aleph_2$ such that for every $I$-positive set $A$ nonempty wins the pressing down game of length $\aleph_1$ on $I$ starting with $A$.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (normal)
  890. Sh:941
    Rosłanowski, A., Shelah, S., & Spinas, O. (2012). Nonproper products. Bull. Lond. Math. Soc., 44(2), 299–310. arXiv: 0905.0526 DOI: 10.1112/blms/bdr094 MR: 2914608
    type: article
    abstract: We show that there exist two proper creature forcings having a simple (Borel) definition, whose product is not proper. We also give a new condition ensuring properness of some forcings with norms.
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  891. Sh:942
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2013). More about \lambda-support iterations of (<\lambda)-complete forcing notions. Arch. Math. Logic, 52(5-6), 603–629. arXiv: 1105.6049 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-013-0334-y MR: 3072781
    type: article
    abstract: This article continues Ros{\l}anowski and Shelah [RoSh:655, RoSh:860, RoSh:777, RoSh:888, RoSh:890] and we introduce here a new property of $({<}\lambda)$--strategically complete forcing notions which implies that their $\lambda$--support iterations do not collapse $\lambda^+$ (for a strongly inaccessible cardinal $\lambda$).
    keywords: S: for, (set)
  892. Sh:943
    Göbel, R., Herden, D., & Shelah, S. (2009). Skeletons, bodies and generalized E(R)-algebras. J. Eur. Math. Soc. (JEMS), 11(4), 845–901. DOI: 10.4171/JEMS/169 MR: 2538507
    type: article
    abstract: fill in
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  893. Sh:944
    Shelah, S. (2018). Models of PA: standard systems without minimal ultrafilters. Sarajevo J. Math., 14(27)(1), 3–11. arXiv: 0901.1499 MR: 3858024
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that $\mathbb N$ has an uncountable elementary extension $N$ such that there is no ultrafilter on the Boolean Algebra of subsets of $\mathbb N$ represented in $N$ which is so called minimal.
    keywords: S: for, (ultraf)
  894. Sh:946
    Kaplan, I., & Shelah, S. (2014). Examples in dependent theories. J. Symb. Log., 79(2), 585–619. arXiv: 1009.5420 DOI: 10.1017/jsl.2013.11 MR: 3224981
    type: article
    abstract: We show a counterexample to a conjecture by Shelah regarding the existence of indiscernible sequences in dependent theories
    keywords: M: cla, (mod)
  895. Sh:947
    Larson, P. B., Neeman, I., & Shelah, S. (2010). Universally measurable sets in generic extensions. Fund. Math., 208(2), 173–192. arXiv: 1003.2479 DOI: 10.4064/fm208-2-4 MR: 2640071
    type: article
    abstract: A subset of a topological space is said to be universally measurable if it is measurable with respect to every complete, countably additive $\sigma$-finite measure on the space, and universally null if it has measure zero for each such atomless measure. In 1934, Hausdorff proved that there exist universally null sets of cardinality $\aleph_1$, and thus that there exist a least $2^{\aleph_1}$ such sets. Laver showed in the 1970's that consistently there are just continuum many universally null sets. The question of whether there exist more than continuum many universally measurable sets was asked by Mauldin no later than 1984. We show that consistently there exist only continuum many universally measurable sets.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  896. Sh:948
    Göbel, R., Herden, D., & Shelah, S. (2011). Absolute E-rings. Adv. Math., 226(1), 235–253. DOI: 10.1016/j.aim.2010.06.019 MR: 2735757
    type: article
    abstract: A ring $R$ with $1$ is called an {\em $E$-ring} if $End_{\mathbb Z} R$ is ring-isomorphic to $R$ under the canonical homomorphism taking the value $1 \sigma$ for any $\sigma \in End_{\mathbb Z} R$. Moreover $R$ is an {\em absolute $E$-ring} if it remains an $E$-ring in every generic extension of the universe. $E$-rings are an important tool for algebraic topology as explained in the introduction. The existence of an $E$-ring $R$ of each cardinality of the form $\lambda^{\aleph_0}$ was shown by Dugas, Mader and Vinsonhaler [DMV]. We want to show the existence of absolute $E$-rings. It turns out that there is a precise cardinal-barrier $\kappa(\omega)$ for this problem: (The cardinal $\kappa(\omega)$ is the first $\omega$-Erd\H{o}s cardinal defined in the introduction. It is a relative of measurable cardinals.) We will construct absolute $E$-rings of any size $\lambda <\kappa(\omega)$. But there are no absolute $E$-rings of cardinality $\ge\kappa(\omega)$. The non-existence of huge, absolute $E$-rings $\ge \kappa(\omega)$ follows from a recent paper by Herden and Shelah [HS] and the construction of absolute $E$-rings $R$ is based on an old result by Shelah [S] where families of absolute, rigid colored trees (with no automorphism between any distinct members) are constructed. We plant these trees into our potential $E$-rings with the aim to prevent unwanted endomorphisms of their additive group to survive. Endomorphisms will recognize the trees which will have branches infinitely often divisible by primes. Our main result provides the existence of absolute $E$-rings for all infinite cardinals $\lambda <\kappa(\omega)$, i.e. these $E$-rings remain $E$-rings in all generic extensions of the universe (e.g. using forcing arguments). Indeed {\em all} previously known $E$-rings ([DMV,GT]) of cardinality $\ge 2^{\aleph_0}$ have a free additive group $R^+$ in some extended universe, thus are no longer $E$-rings, as explained in the introduction. Our construction also fills all cardinal-gaps of the earlier constructions (which have only sizes $\lambda^{\aleph_0}$). These $E$-rings are domains and as a by-product we obtain the existence of absolutely indecomposable abelian groups, compare [GS2].
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg
  897. Sh:949
    Garti, S., & Shelah, S. (2012). A strong polarized relation. J. Symbolic Logic, 77(3), 766–776. arXiv: 1103.0350 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1344862161 MR: 2987137
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that the strong polarized relation ${{\mu^+}\choose {\mu}}\rightarrow {{\mu^+}\choose {\mu}}^{1,1}_2$ is consistent with ZFC.
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  898. Sh:951
    Mildenberger, H., & Shelah, S. (2011). Proper translation. Fund. Math., 215(1), 1–38. DOI: 10.4064/fm215-1-1 MR: 2851699
    type: article
    abstract: We continue our work on weak diamonds [MdSh:848]. We show that $2^\omega= \aleph_2$ together with the weak diamond for covering by thin trees, the weak diamond for covering by meagre sets, the weak diamond for covering by null sets, and ``all Aronszajn trees are special'' is consistent relative to ZFC. We iterate alternately forcings specialising Aronszajn trees without adding reals (the NNR forcing from [Sh:f, Ch.~IV]) and {$<\omega_1$}-proper ${}^\omega \omega$-bounding forcings adding reals. We show that over a tower of elementary submodels there is a sort of a reduction (``proper translation'') of our iteration to the c.s.\ iteration of simpler iterands. If we use only Sacks iterands and NNR iterands, this allows us to guess the values of Borel functions into small trees and thus derive the mentionedweak diamonds.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set)
  899. Sh:952
    Shelah, S., & Zapletal, J. (2011). Ramsey theorems for product of finite sets with submeasures. Combinatorica, 31(2), 225–244. DOI: 10.1007/s00493-011-2677-5 MR: 2848252
    type: article
    abstract: We prove parametrized partition theorem on products of finite sets equipped with submeasures, improving the results of DiPrisco, Llopis, and Todorcevic
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (creatures)
  900. Sh:953
    Doron, M., & Shelah, S. (2010). Hereditary zero-one laws for graphs. In Fields of logic and computation, Vol. 6300, Springer, Berlin, pp. 581–614. arXiv: 1006.2888 DOI: 10.1007/978-3-642-15025-8_29 MR: 2756404
    type: article
    abstract: We consider the random graph $M^n_{\bar{p}}$ on the set $[n]$, were the probability of $\{x,y\}$ being an edge is $p_{|x-y|}$, and $\bar{p}=(p_1,p_2,p_3,...)$ is a series of probabilitie. We consider the set of all $\bar{q}$ derived from $\bar{p}$ by inserting 0 probabilities to $\bar{p}$, or alternatively by decreasing some of the $p_i$. We say that $\bar{p}$ hereditarily satisfies the 0-1 law if the 0-1 law (for first order logic) holds in $M^n_{\bar{q}}$ for any $\bar{q}$ derived from $\bar{p}$ in the relevant way described above. We give a necessary and sufficient condition on $\bar{p}$ for it to hereditarily satisfy the 0-1 law.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  901. Sh:954
    Farah, I., & Shelah, S. (2010). A dichotomy for the number of ultrapowers. J. Math. Log., 10(1-2), 45–81. arXiv: 0912.0406 DOI: 10.1142/S0219061310000936 MR: 2802082
    type: article
    abstract: We prove a strong dichotomy for the number of ultrapowers of a given model of cardinality $\le c$ associated with nonprincipal ultrafilters on $\mathbb{N}$. They are either all isomorphic, or else there are $2^c$ many. We prove the analogous result for metric structures, including $C^*$-algebras and $II_1$ factors, as well as their relative commutants
    keywords: M: non, (mod), (nni)
  902. Sh:955
    Shelah, S. (2014). Pseudo PCF. Israel J. Math., 201(1), 185–231. arXiv: 1107.4625 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-014-1063-6 MR: 3265284
    type: article
    abstract: We continue our investigation on pcf with weak forms of the axiom of choice. Characteristically, we assume DC + ${\mathcal P}(Y)$ when looking at $\prod\limits_{s \in Y} \delta_s$. We get more parallels of pcf theorems.
    keywords: S: pcf, (set), (AC)
  903. Sh:956
    Garti, S., & Shelah, S. (2012). (\kappa,\theta)-weak normality. J. Math. Soc. Japan, 64(2), 549–559. arXiv: 1104.1491 http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.jmsj/1335444403 MR: 2916079
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with the property of weak normality (for non-principal ultrafilters). We characterize the situation of $|\Pi_{i<\kappa} \lambda_i / D| = \lambda$. We have an application ofr a question of Depth in Boolean algebras.
    keywords: S: ico, (set)
  904. Sh:957
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2013). Partition theorems from creatures and idempotent ultrafilters. Ann. Comb., 17(2), 353–378. arXiv: 1005.2803 DOI: 10.1007/s00026-013-0184-7 MR: 3056773
    type: article
    abstract: We show a general scheme of Ramsey-type results for partitions of countable sets of finite functions, where ``one piece is big'' is interpreted in the language originating in creature forcing. The heart of our proofs follows Glazer's proof of the Hindman Theorem, so we prove the existence of idempotent ultrafilters with respect to suitable operation. Then we deduce partition theorems related to creature forcings.
    keywords: S: ico, (set), (creatures)
  905. Sh:958
    Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (2011). A Hanf number for saturation and omission. Fund. Math., 213(3), 255–270. DOI: 10.4064/fm213-3-5 MR: 2822421
    type: article
    abstract: Suppose {$\mathbf T$} $ =(T,T_1,p)$ is a triple of two countable theories in languages $\tau \subset \tau_1$ and a $\tau_1$-type $p$ over the empty set. We show the Hanf number for the property: There is a model $M_1$ of $T_1$ which omits $p$, but $M_1 \restriction \tau$ is saturated is at least the L\"owenheim number of second order logic.
    keywords: M: smt, (mod)
  906. Sh:959
    Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (2012). The stability spectrum for classes of atomic models. J. Math. Log., 12(1), 1250001, 19. DOI: 10.1142/S0219061312500018 MR: 2950191
    type: article
    abstract: We prove two results on the stability spectrum for $L_{\omega_1,\omega}$. Here $S^m_i(M)$ denotes an appropriate notion (${\rm at}$(+ 1 962) or ${\rm mod}$) of Stone space of $m$-types over $M$. Theorem A. Suppose that for some positive integer $m$ and for every $\alpha< \delta(T)$, there is an $M \in \mathbf K$ with $|S^m_i(M)| > |M|^{\beth_\alpha(|T|)}$. Then for every $\lambda \geq |T|$, there is an $M$ with $|S^m_i(M)| > |M|$. Theorem B. Suppose that for every $\alpha<\delta(T)$, there is $M_\alpha \in \mathbf K$ such that $\lambda_\alpha = |M_{\alpha}| \geq \beth_\alpha$ and $|S^m_{i}(M_\alpha)| > \lambda_\alpha$. Then for any $\mu$ with $\mu^{\aleph_0}>\mu \mathbf K$ is not $i$-stable in $\mu$. These results provide a new kind of sufficient condition for the unstable case and shed some light on the spectrum of strictly stable theories in this context. The methods avoid the use of compactness in the theory under study. In the Section~\label{treeindis}, we expound the construction of tree indiscernibles for sentences of $L_{\omega_1,\omega}$.
    keywords: M: nec, (mod)
  907. Sh:960
    Shelah, S. (2017). Preserving old ([\omega]^{\aleph_0},\supseteq^*) is proper. Sarajevo J. Math., 13(26)(2), 141–154. arXiv: 1005.2802 MR: 3744785
    type: article
    abstract: We give some sufficient and necessary conditions on a forcing notion $Q$ for preserving the forcing notion $([\omega]^{\aleph_0},\supseteq)$ is proper. They cover many reasonable forcing notions.
    keywords: S: for
  908. Sh:961
    Kellner, J., & Shelah, S. (2012). Creature forcing and large continuum: the joy of halving. Arch. Math. Logic, 51(1-2), 49–70. arXiv: 1003.3425 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-011-0253-8 MR: 2864397
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (set), (creatures)
  909. Sh:962
    Garti, S., & Shelah, S. (2012). Combinatorial aspects of the splitting number. Ann. Comb., 16(4), 709–717. arXiv: 1007.2266 DOI: 10.1007/s00026-012-0154-5 MR: 3000439
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that the existence of strong splitting families is equivalent to the failure of the polarized relation ${\mathfrak{s}\choose\omega} \rightarrow {\mathfrak{s}\choose {\omega}^{1,1}_2}$. We show that both directions are consistent with ZFC, and that the strong splitting number equals to the splitting number, when exists. Consequently, we can put some restriction on the possibility that $\mathfrak{s}$ is singular.
    keywords: S: str, (set)
  910. Sh:963
    Cummings, J., Džamonja, M., Magidor, M., Morgan, C., & Shelah, S. (2017). A framework for forcing constructions at successors of singular cardinals. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 369(10), 7405–7441. arXiv: 1403.6795 DOI: 10.1090/tran/6974 MR: 3683113
    type: article
    abstract: We describe a framework for proving consistency results about singular cardinals of arbitrary cofinality and their successors. This framework allows the construction of models in which the Singular Cardinals Hypothesis fails at a singular cardinal $\kappa$ of uncountable cofinality, while $\kappa^+$ enjoys various combinatorial properties. As a sample application, we prove the consistency (relative to that of ZFC plus a supercompact cardinal) of there being a strong limit singular cardinal $\kappa$ of uncountable cofinality where SCH fails and such that there is a collection of size less than $2^{\kappa^+}$ of graphs on $kappa^+$ such that any graph on $\kappa^+$ embeds into one of the graphs in the collection.
    keywords: S: for, (set), (univ)
  911. Sh:964
    Garti, S., & Shelah, S. (2012). Strong polarized relations for the continuum. Ann. Comb., 16(2), 271–276. arXiv: 1103.5195 DOI: 10.1007/s00026-012-0130-0 MR: 2927607
    type: article
    abstract: sufficient conditions for the bipartite $(2^\kappa, \kappa) ------> (2^\kappa , \kappa)$ when $ \mu - 2 \kappa $ is singular eg $cf(\mu) < \mathfrak{s} <\mu$, generalize for $\lambda$ instead ${\aleph_0}$
    keywords: S: ico, (pc)
  912. Sh:965
    Larson, P. B., Matteo, N., & Shelah, S. (2012). Majority decisions when abstention is possible. Discrete Math., 312(7), 1336–1352. arXiv: 1003.2756 DOI: 10.1016/j.disc.2011.12.024 MR: 2885917
    type: article
    abstract: Suppose we are given a family of choice functions on pairs from a given finite set. The set is considered as a set of alternatives (say candidates for an office) and the functions as potential ``voters.'' The question is, what choice functions agree, on every pair, with the majority of some finite subfamily of the voters? For the problem as stated, a complete characterization was given in [Sh:816], but here we allow each voter to abstain. There are four cases.
    keywords: O: fin, O: odo
  913. Sh:967
    Mildenberger, H., & Shelah, S. (2011). The minimal cofinality of an ultrapower of \omega and the cofinality of the symmetric group can be larger than \mathfrak b^+. J. Symbolic Logic, 76(4), 1322–1340. DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1318338852 MR: 2895398
    type: article
    abstract: We prove the statement in the title
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  914. Sh:968
    Shelah, S., & Strüngmann, L. H. (2014). On the p-rank of \mathrm{Ext}(A,B) for countable abelian groups A and B. Israel J. Math., 199(2), 567–572. arXiv: 1401.5317 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-013-0039-2 MR: 3219548
    type: article
    abstract: In this note we show that the p-rank of ${\rm Ext}(A,B)$ for countable torsion-free abelian groups $A$ and $B$ is either countable or the size of the continuum.
    keywords: S: dst, O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  915. Sh:969
    Goldstern, M., Kellner, J., Shelah, S., & Wohofsky, W. (2014). Borel conjecture and dual Borel conjecture. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 366(1), 245–307. arXiv: 1105.0823 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-2013-05783-2 MR: 3118397
    See [Sh:969a]

    type: article
    abstract: We show that it is consistent that the Borel Conjecture and the dual Borel Conjecture hold simultaneously.
    keywords: S: for, S: str, (inv)
  916. Sh:970
    Göbel, R., Herden, D., & Shelah, S. (2014). Prescribing endomorphism algebras of \aleph_n-free modules. J. Eur. Math. Soc. (JEMS), 16(9), 1775–1816. DOI: 10.4171/JEMS/475 MR: 3273308
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  917. Sh:971
    Khelif, A., & Shelah, S. (2010). Équivalence élémentaire de puissances cartésiennes d’un même groupe. C. R. Math. Acad. Sci. Paris, 348(23-24), 1241–1244. DOI: 10.1016/j.crma.2010.10.034 MR: 2745331
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that if $I$ and $J$ are infinite sets and $G$ an abelian torsion group the groups $G^I$ and $G^J$ are elementarily equivalent for the logic $L_{\infty\omega}$. The proof is based on a new and simple property with a Cantor-Bernstein flavour. A criterion applying to non commutative groups allows us to exhibit various groups (free or soluble or nilpotent or ...) $G$ such that for $I$ infinite countable and $J$ uncountable the groups $G^I$ and $G^J$ are not even elementarily equivalent for the $L_{\omega_I \omega}$ logic. Another argument leads to a countable commutative group having the same property.
    keywords: S: str, O: alg
  918. Sh:972
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2014). Monotone hulls for \mathcal N\cap\mathcal M. Period. Math. Hungar., 69(1), 79–95. arXiv: 1007.5368 DOI: 10.1007/s10998-014-0042-3 MR: 3269711
    type: article
    abstract: Using the method of decisive creatures ([KrSh:872]) we show the consistency of ``there is no increasing $\omega_2$--chain of Borel sets and ${\rm non}({\mathcal N})= {\rm non}({\mathcal M})=\omega_2=2^\omega$''. Hence, consistently, there are no monotone hulls for the ideal ${\mathcal M}\cap {\mathcal N}$. This answers Balcerzak and Filipczak. Next we use FS iteration with partial memory to show that there may be monotone Borel hulls for the ideals ${\mathcal M}$, ${\mathcal N}$ even if they are not generated by towers.
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  919. Sh:973
    Mildenberger, H., & Shelah, S. (2014). Many countable support iterations of proper forcings preserve Souslin trees. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 165(2), 573–608. arXiv: 1309.0196 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2013.08.002 MR: 3129729
    type: article
    abstract: We show that there are many models of $\rm{cov} {\mathcal M}= \aleph_1$ and ${\rm cof}{{{\mathcal M}}} = \aleph_2$ in which the club principle holds and there are Souslin trees. The proof consists of the following main steps: \begin{enumerate} \item[1.] We give some iterable and some non-iterable conditions on a forcing in terms of games that imply that the forcing is $(T,Y,\mathcal{S})$-preserving. A special case of $(T,Y,\mathcal{S})$-preserving is preserving the Souslinity of an $\omega_1$-tree. \item[2.] We show that some tree-creature forcings from [RoSh:470] satisfy the sufficient condition for one of the strongest games. \item[3.] Without the games, we show that some linear creature forcings from [RoSh:470] are $(T,Y,\mathcal{S})$-preserving. There are non-Cohen preserving examples. \item[4.] For the wider class of non-elementary proper forcings we show that $\omega$-Cohen preserving for certain candidates implies $(T,Y,\mathcal{S})$-preserving. \item[5.] (+ 1 978)We give a less general but hopefully more easily readable presentation of a result from [Sh:f, Chapter~18, \S 3]: If all iterands in a countable support iteration are proper and $(T,Y,\mathcal{S})$-preserving, then also the iteration is $(T,Y,\mathcal{S})$-preserving. This is a presentation of the so-called case A in which a division in forcings that add reals and those who do not is not needed. \end{enumerate} In [Mi:clubdistr] we showed: Many proper forcings from [RoSh:470] with finite or countable ${\rm{H}}(n)$ (see Section 2.1) force over a ground model with $\diamondsuit_{\omega_1}$ in a countable support iteration the club principle. After $\omega_1$ iteration steps the diamond holds anyway.
    keywords: S: for, (inv)
  920. Sh:975
    Kaplan, I., & Shelah, S. (2014). A dependent theory with few indiscernibles. Israel J. Math., 202(1), 59–103. arXiv: 1010.0388 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-014-1067-2 MR: 3265314
    type: article
    abstract: We continue the work started in [KpSh:946], and prove the following theorem: For every $\theta$ there is a dependent theory $T$ of size $\theta$ such that for all $\kappa$ and $\delta$, $\kappa\to\left(\delta\right)_{T,1}$ iff $\kappa\to\left(\delta\right)_{\theta}^{<\omega}$.
    keywords: M: cla, S: ico
  921. Sh:976
    Shelah, S., & Strüngmann, L. H. (2011). Kulikov’s problem on universal torsion-free abelian groups revisited. Bull. Lond. Math. Soc., 43(6), 1198–1204. DOI: 10.1112/blms/bdr055 MR: 2861541
    type: article
    abstract: Let $T$ be a torsion abelian group. We consider the class of all torsion-free abelian groups $G$ satisfying ${\rm Ext}(G,T)=0$ and search for $\lambda$-universal objects in this class. We show that for certain $T$ there is no $\omega$-universal group. However, for uncountable cardinals $\lambda$ there is always a $\lambda$-universal group if we assume $(V=L)$. Together with results by the second author this solves completely a problem by Kulikov.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  922. Sh:977
    Shelah, S. (2012). Modules and infinitary logics. In Groups and model theory, Vol. 576, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, pp. 305–316. arXiv: 1011.3581 DOI: 10.1090/conm/576/11376 MR: 2962893
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that the theory of abelian groups and $R$-modules even in infinitary logic is stable and understood to some extent.
    keywords: M: smt, O: alg, (ab)
  923. Sh:978
    Malliaris, M., & Shelah, S. (2014). Regularity lemmas for stable graphs. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 366(3), 1551–1585. arXiv: 1102.3904 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-2013-05820-5 MR: 3145742
    type: article
    abstract: Let $G$ be a finite graph with the non-$k_*$-order property (essentially, a uniform finite bound on the size of an induced sub-half-graph). The main result of the paper applies model-theoretic arguments to obtain a stronger version of Szemer\'edi's regularity lemma for such graphs: Theorem: Let $k_*$ and therefore $k_{**}$ (a constant $\leq 2^{k_*+2}$) be given. Let $G$ be a graph with the non-$k_*$-order property. Then for any $\epsilon>0$ there exists $m=m(\epsilon)$ such that if $G$ is sufficiently large, there is a partition $\langle A_i : i<i(*)\leq m\rangle$ of $G$ into at most $m$ pieces, where: 1. $m \leq \frac{1}{\epsilon_0^{4k_{**}}}$, for $\epsilon_0 = {\rm{min}}\{\epsilon, \frac{1}{2^{4k_{**}+1}}\}$ 2. for all $i,j<i(*)$, $||A_i|-|A_j||\leq 1$ 3. all of the pairs $(A_i, A_j)$ are $(\epsilon, \epsilon)$-uniform, meaning that for some truth value ${\textbf{t}}= {\textbf{t}}(A_i,A_j) \in \{0,1\}$, for all but $<\epsilon|A_i|$ of the elements of $|A_i|$, for all but $< \zeta|A_j|$ of the elements of $A_j$, $(aRb) \equiv ({\textbf{t}}(A_i,A_j)=1)$ 4. all of the pieces $A_i$ are $\epsilon$-excellent (an indivisibility condition, Definition (6.2) below) We also give several other partition theorems for this class of graphs, described in the Introduction, and discuss extensions to graphs without the independence property. Motivation for this work comes from a coincidence of model-theoretic and graph-theoretic ideas. Namely, it was known that the ``irregular pairs'' in the statement of Szemer\'edi's regularity lemma cannot be eliminated, due to the counterexample of half-graphs. The results of this paper show in what sense this counterexample is the essential difficulty. The proof is largely model-theoretic: arbitrarily large half-graphs coincide with model-theoretic instability, so in their absence, structure theorems and technology from stability theory apply.
    keywords: O: fin, (stal)
  924. Sh:979
    Shelah, S., & Simon, P. (2012). Adding linear orders. J. Symbolic Logic, 77(2), 717–725. arXiv: 1103.0206 DOI: 10.2178/jsl/1333566647 MR: 2963031
    type: article
    abstract: We address the following question: Can we expand an NIP theory by adding a linear order such that the expansion is still NIP? Easily, if acl($A$)=$A$ for all $A$, then this is true. Otherwise, we give counterexamples. More precisely, there is a totally categorical theory for which every expansion by a linear order has IP. There is also an $\omega$-stable NDOP theory for which every expansion by a linear order interprets bounded arithmetic.
    keywords: M: odm
  925. Sh:981
    Göbel, R., Shelah, S., & Strüngmann, L. H. (2013). \aleph_n-free modules over complete discrete valuation domains with almost trivial dual. Glasg. Math. J., 55(2), 369–380. DOI: 10.1017/S0017089512000614 MR: 3040868
    type: article
    abstract: Let $M^*Hom_R(M,R)$ be the dual module of $M$ for any commutative ring $R$. In [GS] we applied a recent prediction principle from Shelah [Sh] to find $\aleph_n$-free $R$-modules $M$ with trivial dual $M^*=0$ for each natural number $n$. This can be achieved for a large class of rings $R$ including all countable, principle ideal domains which are not fields. (Recall that an $R$-module $M$ is $\kappa$-free for some infinite cardinal $\kappa$ if all its submodules generated by $<\kappa$ elements are contained in a free $R$-submodule.) However, the result fails if $R$ is uncountable, as can be seen from Kaplansky's [Ka] well-known splitting theorems for modules over the ring $J_p$ of $p$-adic integers. Nevertheless we want to extend the main result from [GS] to complete discrete valuation domains (DVDs) $R$, in particular to $p$-adic modules $R$ and define a \emph{duality-test} which circumvents Kaplansky's counterexamples. We say that $M$ has \emph{almost a trivial dual} if there is no homomorphism from $M$ \emph{onto} a free $R$-module of countable (infinite) rank. In the first part of this paper we must strengthen and adjust the new combinatorial principle (called the $\aleph_n$-Black Box) and in the second part we will apply it to find arbitrarily large $\aleph_n$-free $R$-modules over complete DVD with almost trivial dual. A corresponding result for torsion modules is obtained as well. Also observe, that the existence of such modules can easily be established assuming GCH (see e.g. Eklof-Mekler [EM] on diamonds), so the problem rests on the fact that we want to stay in ordinary set theory.
    keywords: O: alg, (ab), (stal)
  926. Sh:982
    Lücke, P., & Shelah, S. (2012). External automorphisms of ultraproducts of finite models. Arch. Math. Logic, 51(3-4), 433–441. DOI: 10.1007/s00153-012-0271-1 MR: 2899700
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\mathcal{L}$ be a finite first-order language and $\langle{\mathcal{M}_n}{n<\omega}\rangle$ be a sequence of finite $\mathcal{L}$-models containing models of arbitrarily large finite cardinality. If the intersection of less than continuum-many dense open subsets of Cantor Space ${}^\omega 2$ is non-empty, then there is a non-principal ultrafilter $\mathcal{U}$ over $\omega$ such that the corresponding ultraproduct $\prod_{\mathcal{U}} \mathcal{M}_n$ is infinite and has an automorphism that is not induced by an element of $\prod_{n<\omega} {\rm Aut}{\mathcal{M}_n}$.
    keywords: M: odm
  927. Sh:983
    Pinsker, M., & Shelah, S. (2013). Universality of the lattice of transformation monoids. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 141(9), 3005–3011. arXiv: 1107.3946 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-2013-11566-2 MR: 3068953
    type: article
    abstract: The set of all transformation monoids on a fixed set of infinite cardinality $\lambda$, equipped with the order of inclusion, forms an algebraic lattice Mon$(\lambda)$ with $2^\lambda$ compact elements. We show that this lattice is universal, i.e., every algebraic lattice with at most $2^\lambda$ compact elements is isomorphic to a complete sublattice of Mon$(\lambda)$.
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg
  928. Sh:984
    Dow, A. S., & Shelah, S. (2013). An Efimov space from Martin’s axiom. Houston J. Math., 39(4), 1423–1435. MR: 3164725
    type: article
    abstract: We show from a weak set-theoretic hypothesis that there is an Efimov space.
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  929. Sh:985
    Dow, A. S., & Shelah, S. (2012). Martin’s axiom and separated mad families. Rend. Circ. Mat. Palermo (2), 61(1), 107–115. DOI: 10.1007/s12215-011-0078-7 MR: 2897749
    type: article
    abstract: Two families $\mathcal A, \mathcal B$ of subsets of $\omega$ are said to be separated if there is a subset of $\omega$ which mod finite contains every member of $\mathcal A$ and is almost disjoint from every member of $\mathcal B$. If $\mathcal A$ and $\mathcal B$ are countable disjoint subsets of an almost disjoint family, then they are separated. Luzin gaps are well-known examples of of $\omega_1$-sized subfamilies of an almost disjoint family which can not be separated. An almost disjoint family will be said to be $\omega_1$-separated if any disjoint pair of ${\leq}\omega_1$-sized subsets are separated. It is known that the proper forcing axiom (PFA) implies that no maximal almost disjoint family is ${\leq}\omega_1$-separated. We prove that this does not follow from Martin's Axiom.
    keywords: S: ico, S: str
  930. Sh:987
    Farah, I., & Shelah, S. (2014). Trivial automorphisms. Israel J. Math., 201(2), 701–728. arXiv: 1112.3571 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-014-1048-5 MR: 3265300
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that the statement `For all Borel ideals ${\mathcal I}$ and ${\mathcal J}$ on $\omega$, every isomorphism between Boolean algebras ${\mathcal P}(\omega)/{\mathcal I}$ and ${\mathcal P}(\omega)/{\mathcal J} $ has a continuous representation' is relatively consistent with ZFC. In a model of this statement we have that for a number of Borel ideals ${\mathcal I}$ on~$\omega$ every isomorphism between ${\mathcal P} (\omega)/{\mathcal I} $ and any other quotient ${\mathcal P}(\omega)/{\mathcal J}$ over a Borel ideal is trivial. We can also assure that in this model the dominating number, ${\mathfrak d}$, is equal to $\aleph_1$ and that $2^{\aleph_1}$ is arbitrarily large. In this model Calkin algebra has outer automorphisms while all automorphisms of ${\mathcal P}(\omega)/{\mathop{Fin}}$ are trivial.
    keywords: S: str
  931. Sh:988
    Mildenberger, H., & Shelah, S. (2019). Specializing Aronszajn trees with strong axiom A and halving. Notre Dame J. Form. Log., 60(4), 587–616. DOI: 10.1215/00294527-2019-0021 MR: 4019863
    type: article
    abstract: We show that there are proper forcings based upon countable trees of creatures that specialise a given Aronszajn tree. We try to get the club.
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  932. Sh:989
    Goldstern, M., Shelah, S., & Sági, G. (2013). Very many clones above the unary clone. Algebra Universalis, 69(4), 387–399. arXiv: 1108.2061 DOI: 10.1007/s00012-013-0236-1 MR: 3061094
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\mathfrak c:= 2^{\aleph_0}$. We give a family of pairwise incomparable clones on $\mathbb{N}$ with $2^{\mathfrak c}$ members, all with the same unary fragment, namely the set of all unary operations. We also give, for each $n$, a family of $2^{\mathfrak c}$ clones all with the same $n$-ary fragment, and all containing the set of all unary operations.
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg
  933. Sh:990
    Shelah, S., & Steprāns, J. (2015). Non-trivial automorphisms of \mathcal P(\mathbb N)/[\mathbb N]^{<\aleph_0} from variants of small dominating number. Eur. J. Math., 1(3), 534–544. DOI: 10.1007/s40879-015-0058-0 MR: 3401904
    type: article
    abstract: It is shown that if various cardinal invariants of the continuum related to $\mathfrak d$ are equal to $\aleph_1$ then there is a nontrivial automorphism of $\mathcal{P}(\mathbb{N})/ [\mathbb{N}]^{<\aleph_0}$. Some of these results extend to automorphisms of $\mathcal{P}(\kappa)/[\kappa]^{<\kappa}$ if $\kappa$ is inaccessible
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  934. Sh:991
    Raghavan, D., & Shelah, S. (2012). Comparing the closed almost disjointness and dominating numbers. Fund. Math., 217(1), 73–81. arXiv: 1110.6690 DOI: 10.4064/fm217-1-6 MR: 2914923
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that if there is a dominating family of size ${\aleph}_{1}$, then there is are ${\aleph}_{1}$ many compact subsets of $\omega^{\omega}$ whose union is a maximal almost disjoint family of functions that is also maximal with respect to infinite partial functions.
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  935. Sh:992
    Baldwin, J. T., & Shelah, S. (2014). A Hanf number for saturation and omission: the superstable case. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 60(6), 437–443. DOI: 10.1002/malq.201300022 MR: 3274973
    type: article
    abstract: Suppose ${\bf t} =(T,T_1,p)$ is a triple of two theories in vocabularies $\tau \subset \tau_1$ with cardinality $\lambda$ and a $\tau_1$-type $p$ over the empty set. We show the Hanf number for the property: There is a model $M_1$ of $T_1$ which omits $p$, but $M_1 \restriction \tau$ is saturated is less than $\beth_{({2^{{(2^{ \lambda})}^+}}){}^{^+}}$ if $T$ is superstable. If $T$ is required only to be stable, the Hanf number is bounded by the Hanf number of $L_{(2^\lambda)^+,\kappa(T)}$. We showed in an earlier paper that without the stability restriction the Hanf number is essentially equal to the L\"owenheim number of second order logic.
    keywords: M: cla, M: smt
  936. Sh:993
    Kaplan, I., & Shelah, S. (2013). Chain conditions in dependent groups. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 164(12), 1322–1337. arXiv: 1112.0807 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2013.06.014 MR: 3093393
    type: article
    abstract: In this short note we prove and disprove some chain conditions in dependent, strongly dependent and strongly$^{2}$ dependent theories, focusing on type definable groups.
    keywords: M: cla, O: alg
  937. Sh:994
    Goldstern, M., Pinsker, M., & Shelah, S. (2013). A closed algebra with a non-Borel clone and an ideal with a Borel clone. Internat. J. Algebra Comput., 23(5), 1115–1125. arXiv: 1112.0774 DOI: 10.1142/S0218196713500197 MR: 3096314
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg
  938. Sh:995
    Garti, S., & Shelah, S. (2014). Partition calculus and cardinal invariants. J. Math. Soc. Japan, 66(2), 425–434. arXiv: 1112.5772 DOI: 10.2969/jmsj/06620425 MR: 3201820
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: S: str, (pc), (inv)
  939. Sh:996
    Malliaris, M., & Shelah, S. (2015). Constructing regular ultrafilters from a model-theoretic point of view. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 367(11), 8139–8173. arXiv: 1204.1481 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-2015-06303-X MR: 3391912
    type: article
    abstract: This paper, the first of two, contributes to the set-theoretic side of understanding Keisler's order. We deal with properties of ultrafilters which affect saturation of unstable theories: the lower cofinality ${\mathrm{lcf}}(\aleph_0, \mathcal{D})$ of $\aleph_0$ modulo $\mathcal{D}$, saturation of the minimum unstable theory (the random graph), flexibility, goodness, goodness for equality, and realization of symmetric cuts. We work in ZFC except when noted, as several constructions appeal to complete ultrafilters thus assume a measurable cardinal. The main results are as follows. First, we investigate the strength of flexibility, known to be detected by non-low theories. Assuming $\kappa > \aleph_0$ is measurable, we construct a regular ultrafilter on $\lambda \geq 2^\kappa$ which is flexible (thus: ok) but not good, and which moreover has large ${\mathrm{lcf}} (\aleph_0)$ but does not even saturate models of the random graph. This implies (a) that flexibility alone cannot characterize saturation of any theory, however (b) by separating flexibility from goodness, we remove a main obstacle to proving non-low does not imply maximal, and (c) from a set-theoretic point of view, consistently, ok need not imply good, answering a question from Dow 1985. Under no additional assumptions, we prove that there is a loss of saturation in regular ultrapowers of unstable theories, and give a new proof that there is a loss of saturation in ultrapowers of non-simple theories. More precisely, for $\mathcal{D}$ regular on $\kappa$ and $M$ a model of an unstable theory, $M^\kappa/ \mathcal{D}$ is not $(2^\kappa)^+$-saturated; and for $M$ a model of a non-simple theory and $\lambda = \lambda^{<\lambda}$, $M^\lambda/\mathcal{D}$ is not $\lambda^{++}$-saturated. Finally, we investigate realization and omission of symmetric cuts, significant both because of the maximality of the strict order property in Keisler's order, and by recent work of the authors on $SOP_2$. We prove that if $\mathcal{D}$ is a $\kappa$- complete ultrafilter on $\kappa$, any ultrapower of a sufficiently saturated model of linear order will have no $(\kappa, \kappa)$-cuts, and that if $\mathcal{D}$ is also normal, it will have a $(\kappa^+, \kappa^+)$-cut. We apply this to prove that for any $n < \omega$, assuming the existence of $n$ measurable cardinals below $\lambda$, there is a regular ultrafilter $D$ on $\lambda$ such that any $D$-ultrapower of a model of linear order will have $n$ alternations of cuts, as defined below. Moreover, $D$ will $\lambda^+$-saturate all stable theories but will not $(2^{\kappa})^+$-saturate any unstable theory, where $\kappa$ is the smallest measurable cardinal used in the construction.
    keywords: M: cla, S: ico
  940. Sh:997
    Malliaris, M., & Shelah, S. (2014). Model-theoretic properties of ultrafilters built by independent families of functions. J. Symb. Log., 79(1), 103–134. arXiv: 1208.2579 DOI: 10.1017/jsl.2013.28 MR: 3226014
    type: article
    abstract: In this paper, the second of two, we continue our investigations of model-theoretic properties of ultrafilters: $\mu(\mathcal{D})$, the minimum size of a product of an unbounded sequence of natural numbers modulo $\mathcal{D}$; $\mathrm{lcf}(\aleph_0, \mathcal{D})$ the lower cofinality (coinitiality) of $\aleph_0$ modulo $\mathcal{D}$;flexibility, discussed extensively in the paper; realization of symmetric cuts; and goodness. We work in ZFC except where noted. Our main results are as follows. First, we prove that any ultrafilter $\mathcal{D}$ which is $\lambda$-flexible (thus: $\lambda^+$-o.k.) must have $\mu(\mathcal{D}) = 2^\lambda$. Thus, a fortiori, $\mathcal{D}$ will saturate any stable theory. This is the strongest possible statement about the saturation power of flexibility alone, in light of our proof in the companion paper (I) that consistently, flexibility does not imply saturation of the random graph. In the remainder of the paper, we focus on the method of constructing ultrafilters via families of independent functions. Our second result is a constraint, that is, a tool for building ultrafilters which are not flexible. Specifically, we prove that if, at any point in a construction by independent functions the cardinality of the range of the remaining independent family is strictly smaller than the index set, then essentially no subsequent ultrafilter can be flexible. This is a useful point of leverage since any ultrafilter which is not flexible will fail to saturate any non-low theory. The third and fourth results are ultrafilter constructions. Third, assuming the existence of a measurable cardinal $\kappa$ (to obtain a $\kappa$-complete ultrafilter), we prove that on any $\lambda \geq \kappa^+$ there is a regular ultrafilter which is flexible but not good. This gives a second proof, of independent interest, of a question from Dow [1985], complementing the proof in the companion paper (I). Fourth, assuming the existence of a weakly compact cardinal $\kappa$, we prove that for $\aleph_0 < \theta = \textrm{cf}(\theta) < \kappa \leq \lambda$ there is a regular ultrafilter $\mathcal{D}$ on $\lambda$ such that $\mathrm{lcf}(\aleph_0, \mathcal{D}) = \theta$ but $(\mathbb{N}, <)^\lambda/\mathcal{D}$ has no $(\kappa, \kappa)$-cuts. This appears counter to model-theoretic intuition, since it shows some families of cuts in linear order can be realized without saturating the minimum unstable theory. We give several extensions of this last result, and show how to eliminate the large cardinal hypothesis in the case of asymmetric cuts.
    keywords: M: cla, S: ico
  941. Sh:998
    Malliaris, M., & Shelah, S. (2016). Cofinality spectrum theorems in model theory, set theory, and general topology. J. Amer. Math. Soc., 29(1), 237–297. arXiv: 1208.5424 DOI: 10.1090/jams830 MR: 3402699
    type: article
    abstract: We solve a set-theoretic problem ($p=t$) and show it has consequences for the classification of unstable theories. That is, we consider what pairs of cardinals $(\kappa_1, \kappa_2)$ may appear as the cofinalities of a cut in a regular ultrapower of linear order, under the assumption that all symmetric pre-cuts of cofinality no more than the size of the index set are realized. We prove that the only possibility is $(\kappa, \kappa^+)$ where $\kappa$ is regular and $\kappa^+$ is the cardinality of the index set $I$. This shows that unless $|I|$ is the successor of a regular cardinal, any such ultrafilter must be $|I|^+$-good. We then connect this work to the problem of determining the boundary of the maximum class in Keisler's order. Currently, $SOP_3$ is known to imply maximality. Here, we show that the property of realizing all symmetric pre-cuts characterizes the existence of paths through trees and thus realization of types with $SOP_2$ (it was known that realizing {all} pre-cuts characterizes realization of types with $SOP_3$). Thus whenever $\lambda$ is not the successor of a regular cardinal, $SOP_2$ is $\lambda$-maximal in Keisler's order. Moreover, the question of the full maximality of $SOP_2$ is reduced to either constructing a regular ultrafilter admitting the single asymmetric cut described, or showing one cannot exist.
    keywords: M: cla, S: str, (inv)
  942. Sh:999
    Malliaris, M., & Shelah, S. (2013). A dividing line within simple unstable theories. Adv. Math., 249, 250–288. arXiv: 1208.2140 DOI: 10.1016/j.aim.2013.08.027 MR: 3116572
    type: article
    abstract: We give the first (ZFC) dividing line in Keisler's order among the unstable theories, specifically among the simple unstable theories. That is, for any infinite cardinal $\lambda$ for which there is $\mu < \lambda \leq 2^\mu$, we construct a regular ultrafilter $\mathcal{D}$ on $\lambda$ so that (i) for any model $M$ of a stable theory or of the random graph, $M^\lambda/\mathcal{D}$ is $\lambda^+$-saturated but (ii) if $Th(N)$ is not simple or not low then $N^\lambda/\mathcal{d}$ is not $\lambda^+$-saturated. The non-saturation result relies on the notion of flexible ultrafilters. To prove the saturation result we develop a property of a class of simple theories, called $Qr_1$, generalizing the fact that whenever $B$ is a set of parameters in some sufficiently saturated model of the random graph, $|B| = \lambda$ and $\mu < \lambda \leq 2^\mu$, then there is a set $A$ with $|A| = \mu$ so that any nonalgebraic $p \in S(B)$ is finitely realized in $A$. In addition to giving information about simple unstable theories, our proof reframes the problem of saturation of ultrapowers in several key ways. We give a new characterization of good filters in terms of ``excellence,'' a measure of the accuracy of the quotient Boolean algebra. We introduce and develop the notion of {moral} ultrafilters on Boolean algebras. We prove a so-called ``separation of variables'' result which shows how the problem of constructing ultrafilters to have a precise degree of saturation may be profitably separated into a more set-theoretic stage, building an excellent filter, followed by a more model-theoretic stage: building so-called moral ultrafilters on the quotient Boolean algebra, a process which highlights the complexity of certain patterns, arising from first-order formulas, in certain Boolean algebras.
    keywords: M: cla, S: ico
  943. Sh:1001
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2019). The last forcing standing with diamonds. Fund. Math., 246(2), 109–159. arXiv: 1406.4217 DOI: 10.4064/fm898-9-2018 MR: 3959246
    type: article
    abstract: This article continues Ros{\l}anowski and Shelah [RoSh:655], [RoSh:942]. We introduce here yet another property of $({<}\lambda)$--strategically complete forcing notions which implies that their $\lambda$--support iterations do not collapse $\lambda^+$.
    keywords: S: for
  944. Sh:1002
    Garti, S., & Shelah, S. (2012). The ultrafilter number for singular cardinals. Acta Math. Hungar., 137(4), 296–301. arXiv: 1201.1713 DOI: 10.1007/s10474-012-0245-0 MR: 2992547
    type: article
    abstract: We prove the consistency of a singular cardinal $\lambda$ with small value of the ultrafilter number $\mathfrak{u}_\lambda$, and arbitrarily large value of $2^\lambda$.
    keywords: S: ico
  945. Sh:1003
    Baldwin, J. T., Larson, P. B., & Shelah, S. (2015). Almost Galois \omega-stable classes. J. Symb. Log., 80(3), 763–784. DOI: 10.1017/jsl.2015.19 MR: 3395349
    type: article
    abstract: {\bf Theorem.} Suppose that an $\aleph_0$-presentable Abstract Elementary Class (AEC), $\mathbf {K}$, has the joint embedding and amalgamation properties in $\aleph_0$ and $<2^{\aleph_1}$ models in $\aleph_1$. If $\mathbf {K}$ has only countably many models in $\aleph_1$, then all are small. If, in addition, $\mathbf{K}$ is almost Galois $\omega$-stable then $\mathbf{K}$ is Galois $\omega$-stable.
    keywords: M: nec
  946. Sh:1004
    Shelah, S. (2017). A parallel to the null ideal for inaccessible \lambda: Part I. Arch. Math. Logic, 56(3-4), 319–383. arXiv: 1202.5799 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-017-0524-0 MR: 3633799
    type: article
    abstract: It is well known how to generalize the meagre ideal replacing $\aleph_0$ by a (regular) cardinal $\lambda > \aleph_0$ and requiring the ideal to be $\lambda^+$-complete. But can we generalize the null ideal? In terms of forcing, this means finding a forcing notion similar to the random real forcing, replacing $\aleph_0$ by $\lambda$. So naturally, to call it a generalization we require it to be $(< \lambda)$-complete and $\lambda^+$-c.c. and more. Of course, we would welcome additional properties generalizing the ones of the random real forcing. Returning to the ideal (instead of forcing) we may look at the Boolean Algebra of $\lambda$-Borel sets modulo the ideal. Common wisdom have said that there is no such thing, but here surprisingly \underline{first} we get a positive = existence answer for $\lambda$ a ``mild" large cardinal: the weakly compact one. Second, we try to show that this together with the meagre ideal (for $\lambda$) behaves as in the countable case. In particular, consider the classical Cicho\'n diagram, which compare several cardinal characterizations of those ideals. Last but not least, we apply this to get consistency results on cardinal invariants for such $\lambda$'s. We shall deal with other cardinals, and with more properties related forcing notions in a continuation.
    keywords: S: for
  947. Sh:1005
    Shelah, S. (2016). ZF + DC + AX_4. Arch. Math. Logic, 55(1-2), 239–294. arXiv: 1411.7164 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-015-0469-0 MR: 3453586
    type: article
    abstract: We consider mainly the following version of set theory:``ZF + DC and for every $\lambda,\lambda^{\aleph_0}$ is well ordered", our thesis is that this is a reasonable set theory, e.g. much can be said. In particular, we prove that for a sequence $\bar\delta = \langle \delta_s:s \in Y\rangle,\textrm{cf}(\delta_s)$ large enough compared to $Y$, we can prove the pcf theorem with minor changes (using true cofinalities not the pseudo one). We then deduce the existence of covering numbers and define and prove existence of truely successor cardinals. From this we show that some diagonalization arguments (more specifically some black boxes and consequence) on Abelian groups. We end but showing some such consequences hold in ZF above.
    keywords: S: ods
  948. Sh:1006
    Shelah, S. (2013). On incompactness for chromatic number of graphs. Acta Math. Hungar., 139(4), 363–371. arXiv: 1205.0064 DOI: 10.1007/s10474-012-0287-3 MR: 3061483
    type: article
    abstract: We deal with incompactness. Assume the existence of non-reflecting stationary set of cofinality $\kappa$. We prove that one can define a graph $G$ whose chromatic number is $>\kappa$, while the chromatic number of every subgraph $G' \subseteq G,|G'| < |G|$ is $\le \kappa$. The main case is $\kappa = \aleph_0$.
    keywords: S: ico
  949. Sh:1007
    Chernikov, A., Kaplan, I., & Shelah, S. (2016). On non-forking spectra. J. Eur. Math. Soc. (JEMS), 18(12), 2821–2848. arXiv: 1205.3101 DOI: 10.4171/JEMS/654 MR: 3574578
    type: article
    abstract: Non-forking is one of the most important notions in modern model theory capturing the idea of a generic extension of a type (which is a far-reaching generalization of the concept of a generic point of a variety). To a countable first-order theory we associate its \emph{non-forking spectrum} --- a function of two cardinals $\kappa$ and $\lambda$ giving the supremum of the possible number of types over a model of size $\lambda$ that do not fork over a sub-model of size $\kappa$. This is a natural generalization of the stability function of a theory. We make progress towards classifying the non-forking spectra. On the one hand, we show that the possible values a non-forking spectrum may take are quite limited. On the other hand, we develop a general technique for constructing theories with a prescribed non-forking spectrum, thus giving a number of examples. In particular, we answer negatively a question of Adler whether NIP is equivalent to bounded non-forking. In addition, we answer a question of Keisler regarding the number of cuts a linear order may have. Namely, we show that it is possible that ${ded}\kappa<\left({ded}\kappa\right)^{ \omega}$.
    keywords: M: cla, S: pcf
  950. Sh:1008
    Shelah, S. (2013). Non-reflection of the bad set for \check I_{\theta}[\lambda] and pcf. Acta Math. Hungar., 141(1-2), 11–35. arXiv: 1206.2048 DOI: 10.1007/s10474-013-0344-6 MR: 3102967
    type: article
    abstract: We reconsider here the following related pcf questions and make some advances: (Q1) concerning the ideal $\check I_\kappa[\lambda]$ how much reflection do we have for the bad set $S^{bd}_{\lambda,\kappa}\subseteq \{\delta<\lambda: cf(\delta)=\kappa\}$ assuming it is well defined? (Q2) for an ideal $J$ on $\kappa$ how large are $S^{bd}_J[\bar f],S^{ch}_J[\bar f]$ for $\bar f=\langle f_\alpha: \alpha < \lambda\rangle$ which is $<_J$-increasing and cofinal in $(\prod\limits_{i<\kappa}\lambda_i,<_J)$? (Q3) are there somewhat free black boxes?
    keywords: S: ico, (normal)
  951. Sh:1009
    Malliaris, M., & Shelah, S. (2015). Saturating the random graph with an independent family of small range. In A. Hirvonen, M. Kesala, J. Kontinen, R. Kossak, & A. Villaveces, eds., Logic Without Borders: Essays on Set Theory, Model Theory, Philosophical Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics, Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter, pp. 319–337. arXiv: 1208.5585 DOI: 10.1515/9781614516873.319
    type: article
    abstract: Motivated by Keisler's order, a far-reaching program of understanding basic model-theoretic structure through the lens of regular ultrapowers, we prove that for a class of regular filters $\mathcal{D}$ on $I$, $|I| = \lambda > \aleph_0$, the fact that ${\mathcal{P}}(I)/ \mathcal{D}$ has little freedom (as measured by the fact that any maximal antichain is of size $<\lambda$, or even countable) does not prevent extending $\mathcal{D}$ to an ultrafilter $\mathcal{D}1$ on $I$ which saturates ultrapowers of the random graph. ``Saturates'' means that $M^I/\mathcal{D}_1$ is $\lambda^+$-saturated whenever $M \models T_{\mathbf{rg}}$. This was known to be true for stable theories, and false for non-simple and non-low theories. This result and the techniques introduced in the proof have catalyzed the authors' subsequent work on Keisler's order for simple unstable theories. The introduction, which includes a part written for model theorists and a part written for set theorists, discusses our current program and related results.
    keywords: M: cla, S: ico
  952. Sh:1011
    Kennedy, J. C., Shelah, S., & Väänänen, J. A. (2015). Regular ultrapowers at regular cardinals. Notre Dame J. Form. Log., 56(3), 417–428. arXiv: 1307.6396 DOI: 10.1215/00294527-3132788 MR: 3373611
    type: article
    abstract: ADD
    keywords: M: odm
  953. Sh:1012
    Garti, S., & Shelah, S. (2016). Open and solved problems concerning polarized partition relations. Fund. Math., 234(1), 1–14. arXiv: 1208.6091 DOI: 10.4064/fm763-10-2015 MR: 3509813
    type: article
    abstract: We list some open problems, concerning the polarized partition relation. We solve a couple of them, by showing that for every singular cardinal $\mu$ there exists a forcing notion $\mathbb{P}$ such that the strong polarized relation ${\mu^+ \choose \mu} \rightarrow {\mu^+ \choose \mu}^{1,1}_2$ holds in ${\rm\bf V}^{\mathbb{P}}$.
    keywords: S: ico, (pc)
  954. Sh:1013
    Gitik, M., & Shelah, S. (2013). Applications of pcf for mild large cardinals to elementary embeddings. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 164(9), 855–865. arXiv: 1307.5977 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2013.03.002 MR: 3056300
    type: article
    abstract: The following pcf results are proved: 1. Assume that $\kappa>\aleph_0$ is a weakly compact cardinal. Let $\mu>2^\kappa$ be a singular cardinal of cofinality $\kappa$. Then for every regular $\lambda<{\rm pp}^+_{\Gamma(\kappa)}(\mu)$ there is an increasing sequence $\langle \lambda_i \mid i<\kappa \rangle$ of regular cardinals converging to $\mu$ such that $\lambda= {\rm tcf}(\prod_{i<\kappa} \lambda_i, <_{J^{bd}_{\kappa}})$. 2. Let $\mu$ be a strong limit cardinal and $\theta$ a cardinal above $\mu$. Suppose that at least one of them has an uncountable cofinality. Then there is $\sigma_*<\mu$ such that for every $\chi<\theta$ the following holds: $$ \theta> {\rm sup}\{ {\rm sup} {\rm pcf}_{\sigma_{*}-{ \rm complete}}(\mathfrak{a}) \mid \mathfrak{a}\subseteq {\rm Reg} \cap (\mu^+,\chi) \text{ and } | \mathfrak{a}|<\mu \}.$$ As an application we show that: if $\kappa$ is a measurable cardinal and $j:V \to M$ is the elementary embedding by a $\kappa$--complete ultrafilter over a measurable cardinal $\kappa$, then for every $\tau$ the following holds: \begin{enumerate} \item if $j(\tau)$ is a cardinal then $j(\tau)=\tau$; \item $|j(\tau)|=|j(j(\tau))|$; \item for any $\kappa$--complete ultrafilter $W$ on $\kappa$,\quad $|j(\tau)|=|j_W(\tau)|$. \end{enumerate} The first two items provide affirmative answers to questions from [G-Sh] and the third to a question of D. Fremlin.
    keywords: S: pcf
  955. Sh:1014
    Lücke, P., & Shelah, S. (2014). Free groups and automorphism groups of infinite structures. Forum Math. Sigma, 2, e8, 18. arXiv: 1211.6891 DOI: 10.1017/fms.2014.9 MR: 3264251
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\lambda$ be a cardinal with $\lambda=\lambda^{\aleph_0}$ and $p$ be either $0$ or a prime number. We show that there are fields $K_0$ and $K_1$ of cardinality $\lambda$ and characteristic $p$ such that the automorphism group of $K_0$ is a free group of cardinality $2^\lambda$ and the automorphism group of $K_1$ is a free abelian group of cardinality $2^\lambda$. This partially answers a question from [MR1736959] and complements results from [MR1934424], [MR2773054] and [MR1720580]. The methods developed in the proof of the above statement also allow us to show that the above cardinal arithmetic assumption is consistently not necessary for the existence of such fields and that it is necessary to use large cardinal assumptions to construct a model of set theory containing a cardinal $\lambda$ of uncountable cofinality with the property that no free group of cardinality greater than $\lambda$ is isomorphic to the automorphism group of a field of cardinality $\lambda$.
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg
  956. Sh:1015
    Koszmider, P., & Shelah, S. (2013). Independent families in Boolean algebras with some separation properties. Algebra Universalis, 69(4), 305–312. arXiv: 1209.0177 DOI: 10.1007/s00012-013-0227-2 MR: 3061090
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that any Boolean algebra with the subsequential completeness property contains an independent family of size continuum. This improves a result of Argyros from the 80ties which asserted the existence of an uncountable independent family. In fact we prove it for a bigger class of Boolean algebras satisfying much weaker properties. It follows that the Stone spaces $K_{\mathcal A}$ of all such Boolean algebras $\mathcal A$ contains a copy of the \v Cech-Stone compactification of the integers $\beta\mathbb{N}$ and the Banach space $C(K_{\mathcal A})$ has $l_\infty$ as a quotient. Connections with the Grothendieck property in Banach spaces are discussed.
    keywords: O: top, (ba)
  957. Sh:1016
    Laskowski, M. C., & Shelah, S. (2015). Borel completeness of some \aleph_0-stable theories. Fund. Math., 229(1), 1–46. arXiv: 1211.0558 DOI: 10.4064/fm229-1-1 MR: 3312114
    type: article
    abstract: We study $\aleph_0$-stable theories, and prove that if $T$ either has eni-DOP or is eni-deep, then its class of countable models is Borel complete. We introduce the notion of $\lambda$-Borel completeness and prove that such theories are $\lambda$-Borel complete. Using this, we conclude that an $\aleph_0$-stable theory satisfies $I_{\infty, \aleph_0}(T, \lambda) = 2^\lambda$ for all cardinals $\lambda$ if and only if $T$ either has eni-DOP or is eni-deep.
    keywords: M: cla, S: dst
  958. Sh:1017
    Shelah, S. (2014). Ordered black boxes: existence. Geombinatorics, 23(3), 108–126. arXiv: 1302.3426 MR: 3184377
    type: article
    abstract: We defined ordered black boxes in which for a partial $J$ we try to predict just a bound in $J$ to a function restricted to $C_\alpha$. The existence results are closely related to pcf, propagating downward. We can start with trivial cases.
    keywords: S: ico
  959. Sh:1020
    Shelah, S., & Usvyatsov, A. (2019). Minimal stable types in Banach spaces. Adv. Math., 355, 106738, 29. arXiv: 1402.6513 DOI: 10.1016/j.aim.2019.106738 MR: 3994442
    type: article
    abstract: We prove existence of wide types in a continuous theory expanding a Banach space, and density of minimal wide types among stable types in such a theory. We show that every minimal wide stable type is ``generically'' isometric to an $\ell_2$ space. We conclude with a proof of the following formulation of Henson's Conjecture: every model of an uncountably categorical theory expanding a Banach space is prime over a spreading model, isometric to the standard basis of a Hilbert space.
    keywords: M: cla, O: top
  960. Sh:1022
    Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. (2014). Around cofin. Colloq. Math., 134(2), 211–225. arXiv: 1304.5683 DOI: 10.4064/cm134-2-5 MR: 3194406
    type: article
    abstract: We show the consistency of ``there is a nice $\sigma$--ideal $I$ on the reals with $add(I)=\omega_1$ which cannot be represented as the union of a strictly increasing sequence of length $\omega_1$ of $\sigma$-subideals''. This answers a question by Borodulin--Nadzieja and G{\l}\c{a}b.
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  961. Sh:1024
    Kuhlmann, F.-V., Kuhlmann, K., & Shelah, S. (2015). Symmetrically complete ordered sets abelian groups and fields. Israel J. Math., 208(1), 261–290. arXiv: 1308.0780 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-015-1199-z MR: 3416920
    type: article
    abstract: We characterize and construct linealy ordered sets, abelian groups and fields that are {\emph symmetrically complete}, meaning that the intersection over any chain of closed bounded intervals is nonempty. Such ordered abelian groups and fields are important because generalizations of Banach's Fixed Point Theorem can be proved for them. We prove that symmetrically complete ordered abelian groups and fields are divisible Hahn products and real closed power series fields, respectively. We show how to extend any given ordered set, abelian group or field to one that is symmetrically complete. A main part of the paper establishes a detailed study of the cofinalities in cuts.
    keywords: S: ico, O: alg
  962. Sh:1025
    Juhász, I., & Shelah, S. (2015). Strong colorings yield \kappa-bounded spaces with discretely untouchable points. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 143(5), 2241–2247. arXiv: 1307.1989 DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9939-2014-12394-X MR: 3314130
    type: article
    abstract: It is well-known that every non-isolated point in a compact Hausdorff space is the accumulation point of a discrete subset. Answering a question raised by Z. Szentmikl\'ossy and the first author. We show that this statement fails for countably compact regular spaces, and even for $\omega$-bounded regular spaces. In fact, there are $\kappa$-bounded counterexamples for every infinite cardinal $\kappa$. The proof makes essential use of the so-called {\em strong colorings} that were invented by the second author.
    keywords: S: ico, O: top, (gt)
  963. Sh:1026
    Shelah, S. (2018). The spectrum of ultraproducts of finite cardinals for an ultrafilter. Acta Math. Hungar., 155(2), 201–220. arXiv: 1312.6780 DOI: 10.1007/s10474-018-0847-2 MR: 3831292
    type: article
    abstract: We complete the characterization of the possible spectrum of regular ultrafilters $D$ on a set $I$, where the spectrum is the set of infinite cardinals which are ultra-products of finite cardinals modulo $D$
    keywords: S: ico
  964. Sh:1027
    Shelah, S. (2019). The colouring existence theorem revisited. Acta Math. Hungar., 159(1), 1–26. arXiv: 1311.1026 DOI: 10.1007/s10474-019-00953-2 MR: 4003692
    type: article
    abstract: We prove a better colouring theorem for $\aleph_3$
    keywords: S: ico
  965. Sh:1029
    Shelah, S. (2016). No universal group in a cardinal. Forum Math., 28(3), 573–585. arXiv: 1311.4997 DOI: 10.1515/forum-2014-0040 MR: 3510831
    type: article
    abstract: For many classes of models there are universal members in any cardinal $\lambda$ which "essentially satisfied GCH", i.e. $\lambda = 2^{\le \lambda}$. But if the class is "complicated enough", e.g. the class of linear orders, we know that if $\lambda$ is "regular and not so close to satisfying GCH" then there is no universal member. Here we find new sufficient conditions (which we call the olive property), not covered by earlier cases (i.e. fail the so-called SOP$_4$). The advantage of those conditions is witnessed by proving that the class of groups satisfies one of those conditions.
    keywords: M: non, S: ico
  966. Sh:1030
    Malliaris, M., & Shelah, S. (2016). Existence of optimal ultrafilters and the fundamental complexity of simple theories. Adv. Math., 290, 614–681. arXiv: 1404.2919 DOI: 10.1016/j.aim.2015.12.009 MR: 3451934
    type: article
    abstract: We characterize the simple theories in terms of saturation of ultrapowers. This gives a dividing line at simplicity in Keisler's order and gives a true outside definition of simple theories. Specifically, for any $\lambda \geq \mu \geq \theta \geq \sigma$ such that $\lambda = \mu^+$, $\mu = \mu^{<\theta}$ and $\sigma$ is uncountable and compact (natural assumptions given our prior work, which allow us to work directly with models), we define a family of regular ultrafilters on $\lambda$ called \emph{optimal}, prove that such ultrafilters exist and prove that for any $\mathcal{D}$ in this family and any $M$ with countable signature, $M^\lambda/\mathcal{D}$ is $\lambda^+ $-saturated if $Th(M)$ is simple and $M^\lambda/ \mathcal{D}$ is not $\lambda^+ $-saturated if $Th(M)$ is not simple. The proof lays the groundwork for a stratification of simple theories according to the inherent complexity of coloring, and gives rise to a new division of the simple theories: $(\lambda, \mu, \theta) $-explicitly simple.
    keywords: M: cla
  967. Sh:1031
    Filipczak, T., Rosłanowski, A., & Shelah, S. On Borel hull operations. Real Anal. Exchange, 40(1), 129–140. arXiv: 1308.3749 http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.rae/1435759199 MR: 3365394
    type: article
    abstract: We show that if the meager ideal admits a monotone Borel hull operation, then there is also a monotone Borel hull operation on the $\sigma$--algebra of sets with the property of Baire.
    keywords: S: ico, S: str
  968. Sh:1032
    Machura, M., Shelah, S., & Tsaban, B. (2016). The linear refinement number and selection theory. Fund. Math., 234(1), 15–40. arXiv: 1404.2239 DOI: 10.4064/fm124-8-2015 MR: 3509814
    type: article
    abstract: The linear refinement number $\mathfrak{lr}$ is a combinatorial cardinal characteristic of the continuum. This number, which is a relative of the pseudointersection number $\mathfrak{p}$, showed up in studies of selective covering properties, that in turn were motivated by the tower number $\mathfrak{t}$. It was long known that $\mathfrak{p}=\min\{\mathfrak{t},\mathfrak{lr}\}$ and that $\mathfrak{lr}\le\mathfrak{d}$. We prove that if $\mathfrak{lr}=\mathfrak{d}$ in all models where the continuum is $\aleph_2$, and that $\mathfrak{lr}$ is not provably equal to any classic combinatorial cardinal characteristic of the continuum. These results answer several questions from the theory of selection principles.
    keywords: S: ico, S: str
  969. Sh:1033
    Cherlin, G. L., & Shelah, S. (2016). Universal graphs with a forbidden subgraph: block path solidity. Combinatorica, 36(3), 249–264. arXiv: 1404.5757 DOI: 10.1007/s00493-014-3181-5 MR: 3521114
    type: article
    abstract: Let $C$ be a finite connected graph for which there is a countable universal $C$-free graph, and whose tree of blocks is a path. Then the blocks of $C$ are complete. This generalizes a result of F\"uredi and Komj\'ath, and fits naturally into a set of conjectures regarding the existence of countable $C$-free graphs, with $C$ an arbitrary finite connected graph.
    keywords: M: odm
  970. Sh:1034
    Shelah, S., Veličković, B., & Väänänen, J. A. (2015). Positional strategies in long Ehrenfeucht-Fraïssé games. J. Symb. Log., 80(1), 285–300. arXiv: 1308.0156 DOI: 10.1017/jsl.2014.43 MR: 3320594
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that it is relatively consistent with ${\rm ZF + CH}$ that there exist two models of cardinality $\aleph_2$ such that the second player has a winning strategy in the Ehrenfeucht-Fra{\"\i}ss\'e-game of length $\omega_1$ but there is no $\sigma$-closed back-and-forth set for the two models. If ${\rm CH}$ fails, no such pairs of models exist.
    keywords: M: smt, S: for
  971. Sh:1035
    Chernikov, A., & Shelah, S. (2016). On the number of Dedekind cuts and two-cardinal models of dependent theories. J. Inst. Math. Jussieu, 15(4), 771–784. arXiv: 1308.3099 DOI: 10.1017/S1474748015000018 MR: 3569076
    type: article
    abstract: For an infinite cardinal $\kappa$, let ${\rm ded}\kappa$ denote the supremum of the number of Dedekind cuts in linear orders of size $\kappa$. It is known that $\kappa<{\rm ded}\kappa \leq2^{\kappa}$ for all $\kappa$ and that ${\rm ded}\kappa< 2^{\kappa}$ is consistent for any $\kappa$ of uncountable cofinality. We prove however that $2^{\kappa}\leq{\rm ded}\left( {\rm ded}\left({\rm ded}\left({\rm ded} \kappa\right)\right)\right)$ always holds. Using this result we calculate the Hanf numbers for the existence of two-cardinal models with arbitrarily large gaps and for the existence of arbitrarily large models omitting a type in the class of countable dependent first-order theories. Specifically, we show that these bounds are as large as in the class of all countable theories.
    keywords: M: odm, S: pcf
  972. Sh:1037
    Baldwin, J. T., Laskowski, M. C., & Shelah, S. (2016). Constructing many atomic models in \aleph_1. J. Symb. Log., 81(3), 1142–1162. arXiv: 1503.00318 DOI: 10.1017/jsl.2015.81 MR: 3569124
    type: article
    abstract: (none)
    keywords: M: nec, M: non
  973. Sh:1038
    Shelah, S., & Spinas, O. (2015). Mad spectra. J. Symb. Log., 80(3), 901–916. arXiv: 1402.5616 DOI: 10.1017/jsl.2015.9 MR: 3395354
    type: article
    abstract: The mad spectrum is the set of all cardinalities of infinite maximal almost disjoint families on $\omega$. We treat the problem to characterize those sets $\mathcal A$ which, in some forcing extension of the universe, can be the mad spectrum. We solve this problem to some extent. What remains open is the possible values of min$({\mathcal A})$ and max$({\mathcal A})$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  974. Sh:1039
    Greenberg, N., & Shelah, S. (2014). Models of Cohen measurability. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 165(10), 1557–1576. arXiv: 1309.3938 DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2014.05.001 MR: 3226055
    type: article
    abstract: We show that in contrast with the Cohen version of Solovay's model, it is consistent for the continuum to be Cohen-measurable and for every function to be continuous on a non-meagre set.
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  975. Sh:1040
    Garti, S., Magidor, M., & Shelah, S. (2018). On the spectrum of characters of ultrafilters. Notre Dame J. Form. Log., 59(3), 371–379. arXiv: 1601.01409 DOI: 10.1215/00294527-2018-0006 MR: 3832086
    type: article
    abstract: We show that the character spectrum ${\rm Sp}_\chi(\lambda)$ (for a singular cardinal $\lambda$ of countable cofinality) may include any prescribed set of regular cardinals between $\lambda$ and $2^\lambda$. Nous prouvons que ${\rm Sp}_\chi(\lambda)$ (par un cardinal singulier $\lambda$ avec cofinalit\`e nombrable) peut comporter tout l'ensemble prescrit de cardinaux reguliers entre $\lambda$ et $2^\lambda$.
    keywords: S: ico, S: for
  976. Sh:1041
    Bagaria, J., & Shelah, S. (2016). On partial orderings having precalibre-\aleph_1 and fragments of Martin’s axiom. Fund. Math., 232(2), 181–197. arXiv: 1502.05500 DOI: 10.4064/fm232-2-6 MR: 3418888
    type: article
    abstract: We define a countable antichain condition (ccc) property for partial orderings, weaker than precalibre-$\aleph_1$, and show that Martin's axiom restricted to the class of partial orderings that have the property does not imply Martin's axiom for $\sigma$-linked partial orderings. This yields a new solution to an old question of the first author about the relative strength of Martin's axiom for $\sigma$-centered partial orderings together with the assertion that every Aronszajn tree is special. We also answer a question of J. Steprans and S. Watson (1988) by showing that, by a forcing that preserves cardinals, one can destroy the precalibre-$\aleph_1$ property of a partial ordering while preserving its ccc-ness.
    keywords: S: for
  977. Sh:1042
    Farah, I., & Shelah, S. (2016). Rigidity of continuous quotients. J. Inst. Math. Jussieu, 15(1), 1–28. arXiv: 1401.6689 DOI: 10.1017/S1474748014000218 MR: 3427592
    type: article
    abstract: The assertion that the \v Cech--Stone remainder of the half-line has only trivial automorphisms is independent from ZFC. The consistency of this statement follows from Proper Forcing Axiom and this is the first known example of a connected space with this property. The existence of $2^{\aleph_1}$ autohomeomorphisms under the Continuum Hypothesis follows from a general model-theoretic fact. We introduce continuous fields of metric models and prove countable saturation of the corresponding reduced products. We also provide an (overdue) proof that the reduced products of metric models corresponding to the Fr\'echet ideal are countably saturated. This provides an explanation of why the asymptotic sequence C*- algebras and the central sequence C*-algebras are as useful as ultrapowers.
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  978. Sh:1044
    Fischer, A. J., Goldstern, M., Kellner, J., & Shelah, S. (2017). Creature forcing and five cardinal characteristics in Cichoń’s diagram. Arch. Math. Logic, 56(7-8), 1045–1103. arXiv: 1402.0367 DOI: 10.1007/s00153-017-0553-8 MR: 3696076
    type: article
    abstract: We use a (countable support) creature construction to show that consistently $\mathfrak{d} = \aleph_1 = cov(\mathcal{N}) < non (\mathcal{M}) < non (\mathcal{N}) < cof(\mathcal{N}) < 2^{\aleph_0}$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  979. Sh:1047
    Garti, S., & Shelah, S. (2018). Random reals and polarized colorings. Studia Sci. Math. Hungar., 55(2), 203–212. arXiv: 1609.00242 DOI: 10.1556/012.2018.55.2.1393 MR: 3813351
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that if $\mathfrak{r}=\mathfrak{c}$ then $\mathfrak{s}\leq\textrm{cf}(\mathfrak{c})$, and conclude that if $\mathfrak{r}=\mathfrak{s}=\mathfrak{c}$ then $\mathfrak{s}$ is a regular cardinal. Nous prouvons que $\mathfrak{s}\leq\textrm{cf}(\mathfrak{c})$ si $\mathfrak{r}=\mathfrak{c}$, et conclurons que $\mathfrak{s}$ est un cardinal regulier si $\mathfrak{r}=\mathfrak{s}= \mathfrak{c}$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  980. Sh:1050
    Malliaris, M., & Shelah, S. (2018). Keisler’s order has infinitely many classes. Israel J. Math., 224(1), 189–230. arXiv: 1503.08341 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-018-1647-7 MR: 3799754
    type: article
    abstract: We prove, in ZFC, that there is an infinite strictly descending chain of classes of theories in Keisler's order. Thus Keisler's order is infinite and not a well order. Moreover, this chain occurs within the simple unstable theories, considered model-theoretically tame. Keisler's order is a large scale classification program in model theory, introduced in the 1960s, which compares the complexity of theories. Prior to this paper, it was thought to have finitely many classes, linearly ordered. The model-theoretic complexity we find is witnessed by a very natural class of theories, the $n$-free $k$-hypergraphs studied by Hrushovski. Notably, this complexity reflects the difficulty of amalgamation and appears orthogonal to forking.
    keywords: M: cla, S: ico
  981. Sh:1051
    Malliaris, M., & Shelah, S. (2017). Model-theoretic applications of cofinality spectrum problems. Israel J. Math., 220(2), 947–1014. arXiv: 1503.08338 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-017-1526-7 MR: 3666452
    type: article
    abstract: We apply the recently developed technology of cofinality spectrum problems to prove a range of theorems in model theory. First, we prove that any model of Peano arithmetic is $\lambda$-saturated iff it has cofinality $\geq \lambda$ and the underlying order has no $(\kappa, \kappa)$-gaps for regular $\kappa < \lambda$. We also answer a question about balanced pairs of models of PA. Second, assuming instances of GCH, we prove that $SOP_2$ characterizes maximality in the interpretability order $\triangleleft^*$, settling a prior conjecture and proving that $SOP_2$ is a real dividing line. Third, we establish the beginnings of a structure theory for $NSOP_2$, proving that $NSOP_2$ can be characterized by the existence of few so-called higher formulas. In the course of the paper, we show that $\mathfrak{p}_{\mathbf{s}} = \mathfrak{t}_{\mathbf{s}}$ in \emph{any} weak cofinality spectrum problem closed under exponentiation (naturally defined). We also prove that the local versions of these cardinals need not coincide, even in cofinality spectrum problems arising from Peano arithmetic. *2015.02.12 The new note from Feb on the delayed lemma make no sense:- the finite satisfiability ensure the formulas are compatible. Look back at the old.. The second theorem which is delayed (union of few pairwise non-contradictory) - a debt, look again
    keywords: M: cla, M: odm
  982. Sh:1052
    Shelah, S. (2016). Lower bounds on coloring numbers from hardness hypotheses in pcf theory. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 144(12), 5371–5383. arXiv: 1503.02423 DOI: 10.1090/proc/13163 MR: 3556279
    type: article
    abstract: We prove that the statement ``for every infinite cardinal $\nu$, every graph with list chromatic $\nu$ has coloring number at most $\beth_\omega(\nu)$" proved by Kojman [koj] using the RGCH theorem [sh:460] implies the RGCG theorem via a short forcing argument. By the same method, a better upper bound than $\beth_\omega(\nu)$ in this statement implies stronger forms of the RGCH theorem whose consistency as well as the consistency of their negations are wide open. Thus, the optimality of Kojman's upper bound is a purely cardinal arithmetic problem, which, as discussed below, may be quite hard to decide.
    keywords: S: for, S: pcf
  983. Sh:1053
    Shelah, S., & Wohofsky, W. (2016). There are no very meager sets in the model in which both the Borel conjecture and the dual Borel conjecture are true. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 62(4-5), 434–438. DOI: 10.1002/malq.201600002 MR: 3549562
    type: article
    abstract: We show that the model in~[GoKrShWo:969] (for the simultaneous consistency of the Borel Conjecture and the dual Borel Conjecture) actually satisfies a stronger version of the dual Borel Conjecture: there are no uncountable very meager sets.
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  984. Sh:1054
    Kaplan, I., & Shelah, S. (2016). Forcing a countable structure to belong to the ground model. MLQ Math. Log. Q., 62(6), 530–546. arXiv: 1410.1224 DOI: 10.1002/malq.201400094 MR: 3601093
    type: article
    abstract: Suppose that $P$ is a forcing notion, $L$ is a language (in $\mathbb{V}$), $\dot{\tau}$ a $P$-name such that $P$ forces ``$\dot{\tau}$ is a countable $L$-structure''. In the product $P\times P$, there are names $\dot{\tau_{1}},\dot{\tau_{2}}$ such that for any generic filter $G=G_{1}\times G_{2}$ over $P\times P$, $\dot{\tau}_{1}\left[G\right]= \dot{\tau}\left[G_{1}\right]$ and $\dot{\tau}_{2}\left[G\right]=\dot{\tau}\left[G_{2}\right]$. Zapletal asked whether or not $P\times P$ forces $\dot{\tau}_{1} \cong\dot{\tau}_{2}$ implies that there is some $M\in\mathbb{V}$ such that $P$ forces $\dot{\tau}\cong\check{M}$. We answer this negatively and discuss related issues.
    keywords: M: odm
  985. Sh:1055
    Kaplan, I., Lavi, N., & Shelah, S. (2016). The generic pair conjecture for dependent finite diagrams. Israel J. Math., 212(1), 259–287. arXiv: 1410.2516 DOI: 10.1007/s11856-016-1286-9 MR: 3504327
    type: article
    abstract: We consider a $(\mathbf D,\bar\kappa)$-homomorphism, $\mathbf D$ a finite diagram. Another case is fixing a compact cardinal $\theta$, we look at $(\bar\kappa,\mathcal{L})$-saturated monster $\mathfrak{C}$. Our intention is to generalize [Sh:900].
    keywords: M: nec
  986. Sh:1056
    Bartoszyński, T., Larson, P. B., & Shelah, S. (2017). Closed sets which consistently have few translations covering the line. Fund. Math., 237(2), 101–125. DOI: 10.4064/fm191-8-2016 MR: 3615047
    type: article
    abstract: We characterize those compact subsets $K$ of $2^{\omega}$ for which one can force the existence of a set $X$ of cardinality less than the continuum such that $K+X=2^{\omega}$.
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  987. Sh:1057
    Dow, A. S., & Shelah, S. (2018). Asymmetric tie-points and almost clopen subsets of \mathbb N^*. Comment. Math. Univ. Carolin., 59(4), 451–466. arXiv: 1801.02523 MR: 3914712
    type: article
    abstract: A tie-point of compact space is analogous to a cut-point: the complement of the point falls apart into two relatively clopen non-compact subsets. We review some of the many consistency results that have depended on the construction of tie-points of $\mathbb{N}^*$. One especially important application, due to Velickovic, was to the existencce of non-trivial involutions on $\mathbb{N}^*$. A tie-point $\mathbb{N}^*$ has been called symmetric if it is the unique fixed point of an involution. We define the notion of almost clopen set to be the closure of one of the proper relatively clopen subsets of the complement of a tie-point. We explore asymmetries of almost clopen subsets of $\mathbb{N}^*$ in the sense of how may an almost clopen set differ from its natural complementary almost clopen set.
    keywords: S: for, O: top
  988. Sh:1058
    Raghavan, D., & Shelah, S. (2017). On embedding certain partial orders into the P-points under Rudin-Keisler and Tukey reducibility. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 369(6), 4433–4455. arXiv: 1411.0084 DOI: 10.1090/tran/6943 MR: 3624416
    type: article
    abstract: The study of the global structure of ultrafilters on the natural numbers with respect to the quasi-orders of Rudin-Keisler and Rudin-Blass reducibility was initiated in the 1970s by Blass, Keisler, Kunen, and Rudin. In a 1973 paper Blass studied the special class of P-points under the quasi-ordering of Rudin-Keisler reducibility. He asked what partially ordered sets can be embedded into the P-points when the P-points are equipped with this ordering. This question is of most interest under some hypothesis that guarantees the existence of many P-points, such as Martin's axiom for $\sigma$-centered posets. In his 1973 paper he showed under this assumption that both ${\omega}_{1}$ and the reals can be embedded. This result was later repeated for the coarser notion of Tukey reducibility. We prove in this paper that Martin's axiom for $\sigma$-centered posets implies that every partial order of size at most continuum can be embedded into the P-points both under Rudin-Keisler and Tukey reducibility.
    keywords: S: for, S: str
  989. Sh:1059
    Haber, S., & Shelah, S. (2015). An extension of the Ehrenfeucht-Fraïssé game for first order logics augmented with Lindström quantifiers. In Fields of logic and computation. II, Vol. 9300, Springer, Cham, pp. 226–236. arXiv: 1510.06581 DOI: 10.1007/978-3-319-23534-9_13 MR: 3485648
    type: article
    abstract: We propose an extension of the Ehrenfeucht-Fra\"{\i}sse game able to deal with logics augmented with Lindstr\"{o}m quantifiers. We describe three different games with varying balance between simplicity and ease of use.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  990. Sh:1060
    Raghavan, D., & Shelah, S. (2017). Two inequalities between cardinal invariants. Fund. Math., 237(2), 187–200. arXiv: 1505.06296 DOI: 10.4064/fm253-7-2016 MR: 3615051
    type: article
    abstract: We prove two ZFC inequalities between cardinal invariants. The first inequality involves cardinal invariants associated with an analytic P-ideal, in particular the ideal of subsets of $\omega$ of aymptotic density $0$. We obtain an upper bound on the $\ast$-covering number, sometimes also called the weak covering number, of this ideal by proving in Section 2 that cov${\ast} (\mathcal{Z}_0) \leq \mathfrak{d}$. In Section 3 we investigate the relationship between the bounding and splitting numbers at regular uncountable cardinals. We prove in sharp contrast to the case when $\kappa = \omega$, that if $\kappa$ is any regular uncountable cardinal, then $\mathfrak{s}_\kappa \leq \mathfrak{b}_\kappa$.
    keywords: S: str
  991. Sh:1061
    Shelah, S. (2015). On failure of 0-1 laws. In Fields of logic and computation. II, Vol. 9300, Springer, Cham, pp. 293–296. DOI: 10.1007/978-3-319-23534-9_18 MR: 3485653
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\alpha \in (0,1)_{\mathbb{R}}$ be irrational and $G_n = G_{n,1/n^\alpha}$ be the random graph with edge probability $1/n^\alpha$; we know that it satisfies the 0-1 law for first order logic. We deal with the failure of the 0-1 law for stronger logics: $\mathbb{L}_{\infty,k},k$ large enough and the inductive logic.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  992. Sh:1062
    Shelah, S. (2017). Failure of 0-1 law for sparse random graph in strong logics (Sh1062). In Beyond first order model theory, CRC Press, Boca Raton, FL, pp. 77–101. arXiv: 1706.01226 MR: 3729324
    type: article
    abstract: Let $\alpha \in (0,1)_{\mathbb{R}}$ be irrational and $G_n = G_{n,1/n^\alpha}$ be the random graph with edge probability $1/n^\alpha$; we know that it satisfies the 0-1 law for first order logic. We deal with the failure of the 0-1 law for stronger logics: $\mathbb{L}_{\infty,k},k$ large enough and the inductive logic.
    keywords: M: odm, O: fin, (fmt)
  993. Sh:1063